Van Dun on freedom and property: a critique.
Block, Walter E.
THE THESIS OF VAN DUN (2009) (1) is that there is a conflict
between freedom and property rights, and that libertarians ought to side
with the former. If not, people, many people, will likely starve to
death by being trapped in their houses, unable to get out of them, or,
caught outside of them, without the ability to return home. This is
unjust, and hence unlibertarian, since such people will in effect be
imprisoned, without being found guilty of any crime, indeed, without
even having been accused of perpetrating any illegal action.
This sad state of affairs will come about (VD) asserts, if the
libertarian emphasis on private property rights is fully implemented.
How so? If the non-aggression principle (NAP) of libertarianism is
adhered to, private road owners will be able to charge the veritable
"arm and a leg" to homeowners for access and egress. These
capitalists will thus be empowered to trap individuals in their homes,
prevent them from returning there unless they pay large fees, and/or
forbid such movement outright. The highway corporations would have every
right to impinge upon the freedom to travel of their clients, since, in
the libertarian society, all property, including roads, would be
privately owned, and the proprietors of these vehicular passageways
would have every right to charge price they wished, up to and including
an infinite price, which would be equivalent to out right prohibition.
They could engage in this sort of encirclement, or as I (Block, 2008)
have characterized this problem, as "entrapment." (2)
VD is a well written article. Hence, the author's thesis is
crystal clear, and there is little danger of misinterpretation. His
vision of the Quasi-Earth, populated by creatures just like us, only
they are all libertarians, is inspiring. His depiction of such a society
is highly accurate as it focuses on the twin pillars of libertarianism:
the non-aggression axiom or principle (NAP) and private property rights
based on homesteading (Locke, Rothbard, Hoppe.) He states VD (224-25,
footnote deleted):
Thus, unlike us Earthlings, the Quasi-Earthlings (1)
unconditionally respect every person's rights of self-ownership,
private appropriation of unowned resources, unrestricted
noninvasive use his own property, and exchange by mutual consent,
and (2) unconditionally abide by the nonaggression principle when
it comes to dealing with interpersonal problems. In other words,
there is no crime and every property owner is free to do with, to,
and on his property whatever he likes provided his actions have no
significant physical effects on others or their properties.
However, I cannot fully buy my way into VD's thesis. What
obstacles stand in the way of our agreement?
1. Freedom
Although VD nowhere in his essay explicitly defines
"freedom," it is clear what he means by this, the right to
come and go as one pleases. States VD (230):
there is need to have a "free movement" proviso regarding ownership
of material resources, to the effect that the rights of a property
owner do not include the right to deprive others of the possibility
of moving between their own property and any place where they are
welcome.
But this "freedom" is not at all the negative right not
to have one's person or property free from external aggression.
Rather, it is the positive right, beloved of our friends on the left, to
be able to utilize the property belonging to other people, for our own
ends, without their permission. (3) If freedom from hunger means the
right to force other people to feed you at their expense, and freedom
from nakedness implies the right to compel others to clothe you, again
at their expense, then VD's freedom to travel, or his "free
movement proviso" obligates others to make available to the
recipient a "route" as part of a "right of way
network" which includes "seas, (uninhabited or uncultivated
land) and streets, roads, canals," and, presumably, highways,
byways, roads, avenues, lanes and other vehicular traffic arteries.
But positive "rights" are not rights at all. Rather, they
are a not so heavily concealed demand for (the use of) the property
belonging to others. Just as the welfare recipient of food or clothes
forces farmers, restaurant owners, grocers or tailors to feed and clothe
oneself (or to finance this out of general tax revenues) so do those who
demand freedom to travel intend to legally obligate route owners to
subsidize their movement.
Why limit this "right" to access routes? Trespass on
other people's property might be necessary to move (VD, 230)
"between their own property and any place where they are
welcome," but it is hardly sufficient. Also required in the modern
era are things like cars and tires to support them, and fuel to push
them. If there should be "public space" for "routes"
(VD, 231) should there not also be public financing for
"rights" of way? And, if so, it would appear easy to reconcile
a welfare system that provides automobiles and gasoline to all and
sundry with the libertarianism that VD so obviously favors in other
contexts.
Another difficulty arises with the phrase "any place they are
welcome." Suppose that the person in question is so personally
obnoxious (but is not a criminal nor insane) that there is no one else
on the entire planet Quasi-Earth who would welcome him onto their
premises. Then, it would appear, such as person has as fully lost his
freedom as the man who VD (226) is "locked up in a regular
prison." The implication of this is that there must be a sort of
quasi affirmative action policy for such obnoxious people. Others must
take him in, like it or not, if his "freedom" to move around
is to be respected.
2. NAP and the Blockian proviso
According to VD (224): "... according to the nonaggression
principle, only aggressive invasions of another's property are
unlawful and every act of any other kind is lawful." But this
characterization, while a very good first approximation, is not entirely
correct. It reckons in the absence of what Kinsella (2007) has called
the "Blockian proviso." (4) What is this? It is an implication
of the logical of homesteading. Part and parcel of this doctrine is the
notion that it is illicit to control land that was not homesteaded.
Picture a bagel (or donut) with a hole in it. Label the hole in the
center as "A," the bagel itself as "B" and the
surrounding territory, lying outside of the bagel, as "C."
Suppose that someone, call him Mr. B, homesteads the land depicted by B.
Assume away any possibility of tunneling under, or bridging or flying a
helicopter over (VD, 226) this terrain, B. (5) Mr. B, then, controls
area A, without every having lifted a finger in the direction of
homesteading this land, A. Yes, as of now, Mr. B does not own A. But,
under our assumptions, he can homestead this territory whenever he wants
to do so. Mr. B and gained an untoward advantage, vis-a-vis all other
potential homesteaders of A, who are now residing in territory C, and
cannot reach A, without trespassing on B, Mr. B's property. This, I
claim, is incompatible with the logic of homesteading. (6)
Thus, it is not strictly correct to say that according to the NAP,
only aggressive invasions of another's property are unlawful, and
every act of any other kind is lawful. In the bagel case, we have an
exception to VD's otherwise very well stated premise regarding the
NAP. The a priori axiom of homesteading, the logical core of this
principle, prevents Mr. B from engaging in his preferred homesteading
pattern. If Mr. B want to own territory A, he must homestead it. He may
not prevent others from so doing via his homesteading of B. There are no
"savesies" or reserving theater seats or parking spaces for
late arrivals. The homesteading rule should be, "first come, first
served."
If Mr. B wants to own only B, but not A, well and good. Let him
then homestead B, and ignore A. But, he may not preclude others from so
doing, such as Mr. A, who wants to homestead A, but cannot reach A (he
is now stuck in C) because of Mr. B's ownership of B. Mr. B must
create a path through which Mr. A can travel to and from area A and C,
right through B, so that Mr. A can mix his labor with A, thus
homesteading A, en route to legitimately owning A.
This does not count as a nationalization or land grab or theft from
Mr. B of the area that Mr. B must clear through his land, B, into order
to set up this path for the would-be Mr. A. It stems, rather, from the
fact that without this access route bisecting B, Mr. B would be guilty
of precluding, or forestalling. (7)
Suppose that Mr. B fully intends to homestead the entire area, A+B.
He starts off by erecting a fence around the perimeter of B, thus, also,
of course, enclosing A as well. At this point, however, he owns, only,
the fence itself, plus a few feet on either side of it. He starts off
homesteading at the southern end of B, working northwards, pulling out
trees, crushing rocks, planting seeds. He works steadily every day. But,
before he can bring this process to the northern end of B, passing
through A, of course, some other person, Mr. C, breaks through the
northern end of Mr. B's fence (on the ground that Mr. B is
precluding and forestalling.) My claim is that as long as the size of B
is "reasonable," (8) Mr. C is in the wrong. Mr. B is in the
process of homesteading all of B (+A). He has staked it out. Mr. C is
interfering with the process first begun by Mr. B.
What are the size limitations on B (+A)? this issue is not
unrelated to the one concerning how intensive or extensive must the
homesteading be, in order to count as a justification of ownership.
According to Rothbard (), this depends upon the culture, the common
practices, the history of the area, and can legitimately vary depending
upon these considerations. For example, the land is better watered, on
average, and more fertile, east of the Mississippi, than west of it.
Therefore, the tradition is likely to be a requirement of more intensive
homesteading and farming east of this river than west of it. Similarly,
the optimal size of the farm holding is likely to follow this pattern.
For example, if Mr. B initially enclosed 160 acres in Louisiana, or 1600
acres in New Mexico, this would be far more reasonable than the reverse.
(9) If Mr. B somehow places a fence around the entire U.S., and then
starts homesteading it, working from the south to the north as in our
previous example, then Mr. C would be entirely justified in breaking
through the fence, say, in North Dakota, and working south.
Let us now return to the case where Mr. B placed the fence around
(a reasonable sized) B (+A). Only instead of working from the south to
the north, he began at the perimeter fence, and worked his way inwardly,
toward A. After a week or so, we may suppose that Mr. B had now covered
the entire terrain, B, and was continuing inwardly to A. At this precise
point in time, Mr. C breaks through already homesteaded land in B, and
starts erecting a path toward A, on the ground that Mr. B is a
forestaller of A. My point is that as long as Mr. B is in the process of
homesteading the entire area A+B, has already planted his crops in B,
then Mr. C is in the wrong.
How long should this process take? What are the time limitations?
Again, it is a matter of context. It should depend upon custom, the
terrain, history, etc. as in the case of the intensivity of the
homesteading. For example, 100 years is way too long. But Mr. B need not
rush, and plant all of his 160 (or 1600) acres in one day either. It is
another continuum issue as to precisely how much time Mr. B has at his
disposal before it would be justified for he must build, or allow to be
built, a path in B to allow Mr. A, or Mr. C to begin homesteading in
area A. (10)
3. Imprisonment
It would appear that the analogy between the prisoner and the
hemmed in landowner is not as strong as VD would have it. For one thing,
it is illegal for the inmate to break out of his jail. If he does so,
the forces of law and order will and properly so (11) apprehend him if
they can, and compel him to return to his proscribed quarters. In
contrast, in sharp contrast, it is not at all illicit for the house
occupant to exit or enter his own premises. Yes, to be sure, he may not
do so by trespassing on the "encircler's" property. But,
he may travel toward or away from his house in complete compatibility
with the law if he does so by using a helicopter or tunneling (far
enough below) under the surrounding terrain.
Secondly, we must enquire, carefully, into the history of the
prisoner and the homeowner (or, renter.) If we are still on the
Quasi-Earth where all are libertarians, it is difficult to see how there
can be any inmates at all. If everyone obeys the NAP, no one,
presumably, is guilty of any crime, and thus cannot be properly
incarcerated. But, clearly, there is a jailbird here, so, I think, we
must consider this as an exception to this rule. If the prisoner is in
jail, there, justly, it is because he has committed a crime, is a flight
risk, and is now being forced to labor to compensate his victim. Not so
for the house owner. So, how comes he to be there in the first place?
This is more than passing curious, much more so. For, at present, no one
in his right mind would purchase a dwelling without carefully inquiring
into the legitimacy of the property title being conveyed to him, and/or
by purchasing title insurance and having that company guarantee against
any difficulties in this regard.
In the Quasi-Earth world depicted by VD, in addition to title
insurance, there would also be access insurance. No sober individual
would ever purchase a home without first ascertaining the access and
egress rights (Block, 2009) that accompanied it. And/or, he would hire a
professional insurance company to look into the matter, and guarantee
him against any such goings on.
It is also strange that the homeowner should be in such dire
straights as VD places him in, given the incentives of the road owners.
Assume that the roadway was there in existence before the house was
built. (It is difficult to see how the home could have been built in the
first place without a road to bring wood, cement, glass, labor and other
such inputs needed for construction.) So, here we have the firm that
owns the thoroughfare, and, so far, there are no houses abutting it.
Without such edifices, there can be precious little traffic, and hence
profits for the corporation that owns the street. (12) Thus, the owner
of the route would have every incentive to encourage homeowners to
locate themselves on his street or avenue. How can he do so? But
threatening to box them in, after they have made their land purchase
from him, and are starting to build? Not very likely in any real world
situation. Maybe things work differently on Quasi-Earth, but on this
planet the route owner will maximize profits by contractually obligating
himself not to act in the capricious manner we see in VD's
objection to private roads.
Thus we do not even have to "think" about "public
space in the libertarian order (VD, 231), let alone implement any such
contrary to libertarian scheme. Nor do we have to (VD, 229) "adopt
the stance of otherworldly, sanctimonious saints ignoring the pervasive
causal, physical, and psychological aspects of the human
condition." Of course, the story VD tells is horrific. But, it
cannot and does not arise from the operation of the free enterprise
system. Like all road socialists (see Block, 1996), VD fails to
appreciate the "magic" of the market. (13)
VD (232) condemns innocent road owners as "lords" or
"rulers." Nothing could be further from the truth.
"Cartels" might be closer to the truth. But cartels are a
legitimate part of the market (Rothbard, 2004) as any other form of
business organization. And, in this case, they will have a very salutary
role to play. For, suppose homeowner Mr. X, whose house is located on
street X, wants to travel to his friend Mr. Y, who is located on avenue
Y. The owners of these two thoroughfares will have to come to some sort
of (cartelistic) agreement if they are both to have any hope of
maximizing profits. The value of the property of each will be enhanced
if there is an agreement between them to allow their respective clients,
Mr. X and Mr. Y, to visit each other. They will have every incentive to
allow this, nay, to encourage it. But the process will not stop there.
For, what of avenue Z? It, too, has its client base, who can gain by
being brought into this (cartel) agreement. And so on, with virtually
all roadways (14) agree to allow their clients access to the property of
all the others.
Contrary to VD (227) we should "make light of the ease with
which a thing such as a privately owned road can be turned from a mere
revenue-generating commercial asset into a means for exercising
unilateral control over others and their properties." VD's
fears bespeak an unawareness of how free enterprise actually functions.
References
Block, Walter E. 1977. "Toward a Libertarian Theory of
Abortion." The Libertarian Forum. Vol. 10, No. 9, September, pp.
6-8; www.mises.org/journals/lf/1977/1977_09.pdf; Block, Walter. Undated
(1997?). "L'Aborto: Una Legittima Difesa," Claustrofobia,
anno 1, n. 3, pp. 16-22.
--. 1978. "Abortion, Woman and Fetus: Rights in
Conflict?" Reason, April, pp. 18-25.
--. 1986. The U.S. Bishops and Their Critics: An Economic and
Ethical Perspective, Vancouver: The Fraser Institute.
--. 1996. "Road Socialism," International Journal of
Value-Based Management, Vol. 9, pp. 195-207; walterblock.com/wp
content/uploads / publications/road_socialism.pdf
--. 1998. "Roads, Bridges, Sunlight and Private Property:
Reply to Gordon Tullock," Journal des Economistes et des Etudes
Humaines, Vol. 8, No. 2/3, June-September, pp. 315-26;
http://141.164.133.3/faculty/Block/Blockarticles/roads2_vol8.htm
--. 2001. "Stem Cell Research: The Libertarian
Compromise", LewRoockwell.com, Sep. 3;
www.lewrockwell.com/block/block5.html
--. 2004. "Libertarianism, Positive Obligations and Property
Abandonment: Children's Rights," International Journal of
Social Economics; Vol. 31, No. 3, pp 275-86;
www.emeraldinsight.com/Insight/viewContainer.do?containerType=Is
sue&containerId=18709; www.walterblock.com / wp-content/uploads /
publications /blockchildren.pdf
--. 2008. "Homesteading, ad coelum, owning views and
forestalling." The Social Sciences. Vol. 3, No. 2, pp. 96-103;
www.medwelljournals.com/fulltext/TSS/2008/96-103.pdf;
http://medwelljournals.com/new/5/archivedetails.php?id=5&jid=TSS
&theme=5&issueno=12
--. 2009. The Privatization of Roads and Highways: Human and
Economic Factors; Auburn, AL: the Mises Institute;
http://mises.org/books/roads_web.pdf
--. Forthcoming A. "Terri Schiavo: A Libertarian
Analysis," Journal of Libertarian Studies (414)
--. Forthcoming B. "Stem cell research: the libertarian
compromise," Journal of Medicine and Philosophy.
Block, Walter and William Barnett II. 2008. "Continuums"
Journal Etica e Politica / Ethics & Politics, Vol. 1, pp. 151-66,
June; www2.units.it/~etica/;
www2.units.it/~etica/2008_1/BLOCKBARNETT.pdf
Block, Walter and Matthew Block. 1996. "Roads, Bridges,
Sunlight and Private Property Rights," Journal Des Economistes Et
Des Etudes Humaines, Vol. VII, No. 2/3, June-September, pp. 351-62;
http://141.164.133.3/faculty/Block/Blockarticles/roads1_vol7.htm;
www.business.loyno.edu/bios/Blockarticles/roads1_vol7.htm
Block, Walter and Roy Whitehead. 2005. "Compromising the
Uncompromisable: A Private Property Rights Approach to Resolving the
Abortion Controversy," Appalachian Law Review, 4 (2) 1-45;
www.walterblock.com / wp-content/uploads / publications /blockwhitehead
abortion-2005.pdf
Gordon, David. 2004. "Liberty and Obedience." The Mises
Review. Fall; http://mises.org/misesreview detail.aspx?control=262
Katz, Joshua. 2009. "Why Libertarians Should Reject Positive
Rights," Libertarian Papers 1, 6
Kinsella, Stephan. 2007. "The Blockean Proviso,"
Mises.org Blog (September 11); http://blog.mises.org/archives
/007127.asp
--. 2009. "Van Dun on Freedom versus Property and Hostile
Encirclement," Mises.org Blog (August 3);
http://blog.mises.org/archives /010396.asp
Long, Roderick T. 1993. "Abortion, Abandonment, and Positive
Rights: The Limits of Compulsory Altruism," Social Philosophy and
Policy vol. 10 no.1 (Winter)
--. 2007 "Easy Rider," AustroAthenian Empire (September
11); http://praxeology.net/blog/2007 /09 /11easyrider
Rothbard, Murray N. 1982. "Law, Property Rights, and Air
Pollution," Cato Journal, Vol. 2, No. 1, Spring; reprinted in
Economics and the Environment: A Reconciliation, Walter Block, ed.,
Vancouver: The Fraser Institute, 1990;
www.mises.org/rothbard/lawproperty.pdf; http://mises.org/story/2120
--. 1998. "Isaiah Berlin on Negative Freedom," in The
Ethics of Liberty, New York: New York University Press, chapter 27, pp.
215-18; www.mises.org/ rothbard/ethics / ethics.asp
--. (2004 [1962]). Man, Economy and State, Auburn AL: Ludwig von
Mises Institute, Scholar's Edition; www.mises.org/rothbard/mes.asp
Van Dun, Frank. 2009. "Freedom and Property, Where They
Conflict," Mises Daily, October, 29; http://mises.org/story/3794;
also, chapter 23 in Hulsmann, Jorg Guido and Stephan Kinsella, eds.,
Property, Freedom and Society: Essays in Honor of Hans-Hermann Hoppe,
Auburn, AL: Ludwig von Mises Institute, pp. 223-34
WALTER E. BLOCK *
* Walter E. Block, (www.WalterBlock.com; wblock@loyno.edu) is
Harold E. Wirth Eminent Scholar Endowed Chair and Prof. of Economics,
College of Business, Loyola University New Orleans and a Senior Fellow
of the Ludwig von Mises Institute.
(1) Hence, VD.
(2) Also see Kinsella, 2009.
(3) For the incompatibility between libertarianism and positive
rights, and thus for the contradictions in the latter, see Block, 1986;
Gordon, 2004; Katz, 2009; Long, 1993; Rothbard, 1998.
(4) Also see Long, 2007.
(5) Also see Block and Block, 1996; and Block, 1998.
(6) Hoppe, 2007, 66, discusses the a priori axioms of action and
argumentation. What we have here with the bagel or the so-called
Blockian proviso might better be called the a priori axiom of
homesteading.
(7) In like manner, a parent may not licitly hide a baby he no
longer wishes to feed and care for in the back room of his house. That
would be murder. If such a person wishes to give up his guardianship
rights over the baby, well and good. He must then bring the infant to
the hospital, or church, or adoption agency or in some other manner make
it publicly known that he is renouncing his mentorship of the baby. He
may not legally preclude or forestall others from adopting this child.
Nor does this count as a positive obligation, anathema to the
libertarian philosophy, and more than does compelling Mr. B to clear a
path through B for the use of Mr. A. See on this: Block, 1977, 1978,
2001, 2004, 2008, forthcoming A, B, Block and Whitehead, 2005. I
apologize for so heavily citing myself on this issue, and no one else. I
do this only because I am unaware of other publications on this issue.
(8) Rothbard (1982) discusses this.
(9) For an analysis of continuum problems, see Block and Barnett,
2008.
(10) It is more than passing curious that after mentioning this
material in his footnote 7, VD ignores its implications for his own
deliberations on "freedom."
(11) Here, we are presumably talking about Quasi-Earth, where only
criminals (there cannot be any) who violate the NAP are punished. Would
that the actual earth could be run in this manner.
(12) Yes, a limited access highway owner would not be faced with
exactly this problem; motorists could transfer from each of their home
cites that lie at the endpoints of the road to the other. But, even here
it would be to the interest of the corporation owning the highway to
encourage people settle on the abutting land. It would add to the
traffic flows, and thus enhance the value of the roadway. Restaurants on
the side of the road could serve travelers, and pay rent to the highway
owner. In any case, private dwellings of the sort VD asks us to consider
cannot be located on a limited access highway. If they were, it would no
longer be a limited access facility.
(13) It sounds harsh to condemn VD in such a manner. And,
certainly, VD is no socialist on a plethora of questions. Indeed, he is
one of the leading libertarian theoreticians in the entire world. But,
how else are we to characterize a scholar who rejects private roads on
the ground that they are inhumane, will force innocent people into a
life worse than that of prisoners (prisoners are at least fed; VD's
trapped homeowner on Quasi-Earth will die from lack of food.)
(14) There may be a few gated communities who hold back.