Multiculturalism and ethnic pluralism in sociology: an analysis of the fragmentation position discourse.
Wong, Lloyd
INTRODUCTION
The two quotations (above) come from front page articles in the
Calgary Sun (summer, 2006) that highlighted sociologist Mahfooz
Kanwar's views of official Canadian multiculturalism policy shortly
after the arrests in Toronto of eighteen people, including five youths,
in an alleged bomb plot. These two newspaper articles subsequently
appeared on the web sites of several conservative anti-immigration and
anti-multiculturalism organizations to give credence to their cause, as
many of the public debates about immigration and multiculturalism are
entwined. However, it is safe to say that many Canadian sociologists,
over the past several decades, have been supportive of cultural and
ethnic diversity in Canada and supportive of official multiculturalism
policy, as has the general Canadian population. Public opinion polls in
recent years have consistently found that the vast majority of Canadians
(75%) approve of multiculturalism in Canada. However, there is a growing
minority which does not. Thus, one would also expect to find in the
academic sociological literature, in Canada and elsewhere, a clear
critique of ethnic pluralism or multiculturalism (1) that approximates
the views of Kanwar. Earlier work by Roberts and Clifton (1990, 122)
stated that multiculturalism is problematic for integration in Canada,
although this statement, like others that articulate the same
postulation, was not evidence-based.
In the post-9/11 era, public discourse on anti-multiculturalism has
grown, largely because it has been fuelled by the Madrid bombings in
2004, the London bombings in the summer of 2005, and in Canada by the
alleged terrorist plot in 2006. Similarly, academic sociological
discourse that is anti-multiculturalism has also increased since 9/11.
This discourse has produced the term "post-multiculturalism"
that suggests the need to move beyond current policies of
multiculturalism and different approaches to the processes of immigrant
and ethnic integration. The term "post--multiculturalism" was
popularized in Europe by Vertovec (n.d.), who meant it to be a call for
alternatives to multiculturalism that includes a search for new models
that foster social cohesion and promote assimilation and a common
identity. It would be erroneous to attribute the rise of
"post-multiculturalism" discourse specifically to the
aforementioned terrorist events, since some post-multiculturalism public
discourse had been articulated in the 1990s. Much of the discourse was
rooted in a view that multiculturalism was "everywhere" and
that there was "too much" of it. This view was particularly
evident in the "anti-multiculturalism" and
"anti-immigration" movements in Europe. A central aspect of
"post-multiculturalism" discourse is based on the perception
and claim that multiculturalism is not working, or perhaps has not
worked, and is segregating (rather than integrating) diverse
"racial," ethnic, and religious groups. In other words, the
perception and claim is that multiculturalism policy and the reality of
cultural pluralism contribute to a fragmentation of society and make
social cohesion difficult if not impossible.
This article provides an overview and analysis of some of this
sociological discourse that views multiculturalism as a force of
societal fragmentation. It begins with a contextualization of
multiculturalism (or ethnic/cultural pluralism) in terms of sociological
theory. This allows for different conceptualizations of multiculturalism
vis-a-vis the bases of social cohesion. A brief description of the
sociological literature search methodology follows, together with the
findings of what the sub-themes of the fragmentation perspective are.
This is followed, in turn, by a highlighting of the ideas of some of the
major sociologists in Canada and Europe who have adopted some form of
the fragmentation perspective on multiculturalism over the past three to
four decades. These sociologists include John Porter, Reginald Bibby,
Michel Wieviorka, Bruno Latour, and Tahir Abbas. There is not only a
description of the fragmentation position on multiculturalism of each of
them, but also a brief application of a "sociology of
knowledge" approach to their work. The article ends with a
discussion and conclusion that considers what the implications of this
discourse might be.
ETHNIC PLURALISM AND SOCIOLOGICAL THEORY
The sociological literature on the meaning of ethnic and cultural
pluralism is muddled and is often situated or framed within national
perspectives. Recently Hartmann and Gerteis' work (2005) provided a
lucid approach to mapping multiculturalism sociologically in terms of
social cohesion. Their model is adopted here to provide a framework in
which to position the sociological critiques of multiculturalism that
focus on fragmentation. Hartmann and Gerteis suggest that there are two
approaches to conceptualizing multiculturalism. The first approach is a
one-dimensional conceptualization that is a narrow and binary approach
to social order where the two extremes encompass notions of unity and
fragmentation (see fig.l).
[FIGURE 1 OMITTED]
In order to move beyond the problematic one-dimensional framework,
Hartmann and Gerteis conceptualize a framework for some visions of
pluralism in American culture by providing a theoretical grid that has
two dimensions and encompasses what they term "visions of
difference" (222). One dimension specifies two different cultural
bases for social cohesion that include: 1) substantive moral bonds and
2) procedural norms (see fig. 2). The former emphasizes shared
substantive moral bonds and practices and is deemed as a
"thick" form of social cohesion. The latter emphasizes that
adherence to common norms and legal codes (rule of law) is all that is
required, and this is deemed a "thin" form of social cohesion.
The second dimension relates to the basis for association, and is
segmented into the centrality off 1) individual interaction and 2)
mediating groups. By combining these two dimensions they create a
two-by-two table with four cells of which three cells portray their
distinct "visions of difference," or what can be considered as
three forms of multiculturalism: cosmopolitanism, interactive pluralism,
and fragmented pluralism.
This two-dimensional framework can be further elaborated
diagrammatically to illustrate the nature and strength of internal or
sub-national group boundaries where the salient boundaries would
normally be ethnic, cultural, and religious (see fig. 3). Fragmented
pluralism is the direct opposite of assimilationism and social
homogeneity, and some political projects (particularly on the right)
fear what they deem the disuniting and moral relativism of this vision
(Harmann and Gerteis, 230). It is precisely the fragmented pluralism
vision that is the focus of this analysis, as this is the heart of the
sociological critiques of multiculturalism in the English-language
literature. In providing the analysis of fragmented pluralism, specific
reference will be made to the Canadian sociological literature where
possible. Nevertheless, a brief discussion of interactive pluralism is
included in the concluding section of this article.
[FIGURE 3 OMITTED]
METHODOLOGY AND THEMATIC FINDINGS
In the fall of 2006 an extensive search of the sociological
literature in English was conducted seeking direct or indirect critiques
of multiculturalism because of its alleged fragmentary characteristic.
This literature search yielded forty-six articles and books. (2) What is
revealing is that thirty-five were published in the 2000s or in what may
be called the post-9/11 era. There was only one work in the 1960s, none
in the 1970s and 1980s, and ten works in the 1990s. Thus one can
conclude that there is currently a post-multiculturalism trajectory in
the sociological discourse that utilizes the fragmentation critique.
From a reading of summaries of these works, it is possible to identify
some sub-dimensions or sub-themes of the overall fragmented pluralism
theme. These sub-themes cover the nature of the fragmentation itself
and, in some cases, where applicable, their implication for Canada.
These sub-themes of fragmented pluralism include the following:
1. Multiculturalism leads to ethnic marginalization and ethnic
stratification particularly when there is unequal distribution of power
in Canadian society
2. Multiculturalism emphasizes differences, hence it is divisive
and subverts social cohesion in Canada and the development of Canadian
identity
3. Multiculturalism's emphasis on cultural relativism potentially leads to a clash of cultures in Canada. At a global level
the notion of clash of cultures is best exemplified by the notion
of"clash of civilizations" (Huntington 1993,1996)
These three sub-themes overlap with several of those found in Prins
and Slijper (2002) in their summary of the themes in the public debates
on multiculturalism. The third sub-theme can also be characterized as a
"domestic clash of civilizations." Within these three
sub-themes numerous criticisms are articulated either explicitly or
implicitly in the literature. The primary focus here is on a few
selected works from this literature, mostly revolving around sub-themes
2 and 3, and, where possible, of relevance to Canadian society. In this
analysis, as mentioned earlier, a sociology of knowledge approach is
also utilized to contextualize the works of these scholars. (3) In
assessing these works it is important to contextualize their work in
terms of the social setting, background, and the theoretical positions
of the authors.
Ethnic Pluralism Potentially Keeps the Mosaic Vertical: John Porter
In the 1960s and 1970s John Porter was the first sociological voice
critiquing multiculturalism as a form of fragmented pluralism. His book
The Vertical Mosaic (1965) covered this position briefly at the end.
Subsequently, he repeated this view in several journal articles written
in the 1970s after multiculturalism had become official Canadian state
policy.
Porter concluded The Vertical Mosaic by stating:
It seems inescapable that the strong emphasis on ethnic
differentiation can result only in those continuing dual loyalties
which prevent the emergence of any clear Canadian identity.
From the point of view of this study of social class and power, it
is likely that the historical pattern of class and ethnicity will
be perpetuated as long as ethnic differentiation is so highly valued
(558).
The first part of the quote illustrates the second sub-theme of
fragmented pluralism (see above) where multiculturalism's emphasis
on differences is seen to be divisive, subverts social cohesion, and
hence is a barrier to the development of a unified Canadian identity.
The second part also illustrates the first sub-theme that suggests that
multiculturalism, when practiced in inequalitarian societies, leads to
ethnic marginalization and ethnic stratification. Thus Porter argued
that multiculturalism has the potential to keep the mosaic vertical,
thereby ensuring an ethnic stratification system.
In his article "Dilemmas and Contradictions of a Multi-Ethnic
Society" (1972), Porter forecast that the decade of the 1970s in
Canada would be the decade of organized minorities, in contrast to the
1960s, the decade of concern with poverty, and the 1950s, which were
characterized by a naive belief in the affluent society. He thus
reaffirmed the argument he had made in The Vertical Mosaic that the cost
of multiculturalism would be the perpetuation of ethnic stratification.
It should be noted that Porter did not deny the value of cultural
diversity since he stated, "No academic would seriously dispute the
desirability and responsibility of preserving culture...."
Nevertheless, he thought that diversity should not be promoted via
institutionalized and permanent ethnic communities (1972, 199, 201).
Porter described himself as a "liberal assimilationist"
clearly supporting assimilationism as a better choice than ethnic
stratification resulting from ethnic pluralism. Furthermore, Porter
pointed out that multicultural practices were contradictory to the
upcoming post-industrial era: "There is much confusion in the
current discussion of multi-ethnicity and multiculturalism.... I am not
able fully to understand how biculturalism and multiculturalism have any
meaning in the post-industrial world into which we are moving"
(198). From this assimilationist position, Porter also critiqued the
ethnicity question in the Canadian census, suggesting that it created a
statistical artifact and that it also posed a dilemma for liberal social
scientists.
Porter's next essay on multiculturalism was "Ethnic
Pluralism in Canadian Perspective" (1975; 1979a). This work
continued to articulate the dilemmas and contradictions of ethnic
pluralism and the idea that cultural differences were not only divisive,
but posed a risk in the development of a socially stratified society
along ethnic lines. He stated: "My own view is that ethnic saliency or differentiation in social structure always creates a high risk of
ethnic stratification" (Porter 1975, 289; 1979a, 122). Moreover, he
predicted in 1975 that, with the coming of a post-industrial society,
the next twenty-five years would see rapid social change and possibly
the end of cultural differentiation (1975, 303-304).
Porter reiterated his liberal assimilationist position in his 1979
essay, entitled "Melting Pot or Mosaic: Revolution or
Reversion?," that compared the developments of ethnicity and
ethnicization in the United States and Canada. Here Porter arrived at
the conclusion that the "melting pot" is more revolutionary
than the "mosaic": "A melting pot course towards the
development of a universalistic modern character and culture emphasizing
common human qualities and the unity of mankind and shedding the
particularisms of history continues as the revolutionary option"
(1979b, 160).
When Porter was critiquing multiculturalism in the mid-1960s and
early 1970s, Canada was experiencing a time of extremely strained
English-French relations, Quebec nationalism, and political violence.
The FLQ, a group of Quebec ultranationalists, conducted bombings of
mailboxes and public monuments which culminated in the October Crisis of
1970 and the kidnapping of James Cross and the kidnapping and murder of
Pierre Laporte. At the same time the Royal Commission on Bilingualism
and Biculturalism was not only inquiring into the state of the deux
nations in Canada, but also responding to the voices of the "third
force" of non-English and non-French in Canada and facilitating the
creation of official multiculturalism. As Winter (2005) has recently
demonstrated, the view that multiculturalism and binationalism are
integrally related, rather than opposing, forces dates back to the B and
B Commission.
During the time that Porter's lens was focused on a fragile
Canada, the ethnic population consisted of approximately 75% who were
either English or French and 23% who were other Europeans. This was the
social context that undoubtedly influenced Porter's concern for a
singular Canadian identity and a Canadian unity that might not be
possible if there was an emphasis on ethnic differentiation that would
contribute to divided and dual loyalities. Some observers, such as
Buchingnani, noted: "Crudely put, it seems that Canadian
nationalists like Porter have long argued that ethnic culture is
intrinsically divisive and destructive of a unified Canadian identity:
so, the argument goes, its perpetuation inevitably leads to less than
full socio-economic participation for minority groups members"
(1982, 28). Kallen (1982, 54) also noted Porter's critique of
multicultural social policy as being divisive and fragmentary. She
states:
One line of argument put forward by scholars who oppose this policy
objective (notably, the late lohn Porter ...) is that encouragement
of ethnic diversity and cultural distinctiveness fosters
(implicitly, if not explicitly) ethnic separation, enclavement, and
retention of traditional values. Ethnic particularism, in turn,
perpetuates the vertical (ethnic) mosaic by creating barriers to
upward mobility in post-industrial society which is predicated on
universalistic norms. In this view, government encouragement of
ethnic diversity legitimates the proliferation of particularistic
value differences among Canadians and thus impedes the development
of national unity.
It should be remembered that when Porter was writing, sociological
research in Canada tended to reflect majority group views on ethnicity
and also had methodological and theoretical constraints on what was
considered an appropriate line of social science inquiry (Buchignani
1982, 16).
Excessive Relativism Leads to Mosaic Madness: Reginald Bibby
In the 1980s there were virtually no critical academic works of
multiculturalism, but in the 1990s this changed dramatically. Reginald
Bibby's Mosaic Madness: Pluralism without a Cause (1990) utilized
sociological language to critique official pluralism in the form of
multiculturalism policy. (4) A few years later Nell Bissoondath wrote
Selling Illusions: The Cult of Multiculturalism (1994), which utilized a
more personal and individualistic account to suggest that
multiculturalism was subscribed to by unthinking individuals and created
ethnic segregation and ghettoization. Only Bibby's work will be
discussed here as it is more directly sociological. It should be noted
that in addition to these two books and a few other academic critiques
(approximately ten articles), there was also strong criticism of
official multiculturalism by the Reform Party of Canada in the 1990s. In
the 1991 policy manual of the Reform Party, there is explicitly stated
opposition to the "... current concept of multiculturalism and
hyphenated Canadianism pursued by the Government of Canada. We would end
funding of the multiculturalism program and support the abolition of the
Department of Multiculturalism" (cited in Kirkham 1998, 257). While
not in direct response to academic or Reform Party critiques, there was
a withering away of the Department of Multiculturalism under
Chretien's Liberal Government in the 1990s.
Bibby's critique touches on sub-themes 2 and 3 of the
fragmented pluralism position. He sees multiculturalism as entailing an
overemphasis on cultural relativism and difference that is divisive,
prevents moral consensus, and creates individual mosaic fragments. To
him, cultural relativism and pluralism go hand-in-hand, and he uses a
baseball analogy to illustrate his point:
In Canada, pluralism articulates the pathway to group and individual
freedom. But relativism plays the important role of providing the
rationale for freedom of thought and behavior. If pluralism is the
pitcher, relativism is the center-fielder. Relativism pronounces
that it is appropriate and ideal that a culture encourages a wide
variety of views and lifestyles. Pluralism establishes choices;
relativism declares the choices valid (1990, 9-10).
However, he considers that cultural relativism and pluralism, while
desired virtues in Canada, lack overarching societal expectations
regarding the preferred outcomes of such virtues, i.e., the overarching
expectation of social cohesion. Consequently, one of the unintended
consequences is strain between ethnic groups. The result is having
"too much of a good thing"; it would be naive to assume that
this would lead to social cohesion. Bibby states:
... our expectation has been that fragments of the mosaic will
somehow add up to a healthy and cohesive society. It is not at all
clear why we should expect such an outcome. To encourage individual
mosaic fragments may well result in the production of individual
mosaic fragments and not much more (1990, 10).
Thus, according to Bibby, "relativism has slain moral
consensus" as it has "stripped us of our ethical and moral
guidelines, leaving us with no authoritative instruments with which to
measure social life" (14). What we are left with then, he argues,
are just the standards of our local cultural and religious domains and
not anything more, which is tantamount to ethnocentrism without a common
culture. He considered that multiculturalism creates ethnic separation
and ethnic solidarity that takes away from broader social participation.
His critique of relativism continues as a theme throughout his work, and
various sections in the book have sub-titles such as "Excessive
Relativism" and "Open-Minded Mindlessness." He also
discusses "visionless coexistence" in Canada where he suggests
that the outcome of multiculturalism policy is coexistence--no more, no
less. However, the danger is that there is no sub-sequent vision, nor
national goal, nor common purpose. Hence, he states: "Pluralism
ceases to have a cause. The result: mosaic madness" (104).
Was it "mosaic madness" in the late 1980s and early
1990s? Certainly, the "face of Canada" had changed
dramatically from the time Porter was writing. In 1965, approximately
14% of immigrants came from non-European and non-U.S, regions of the
world, but by 1985, almost 70% of immigrants were coming from these
regions. Consequently, Canada became much more diverse in the decade or
so between Porter's and Bibby's critiques. The visible
minority population in Canada doubled from approximately 5% in 1981 to
almost 10% in 1991. In Canada's larger metropolitan areas, where
most visible minorities are located, their population also doubled so
that by 1991, approximately 26% of Toronto's and 24% of
Vancouver's populations consisted of visible minorities.
In the 1980s, when Bibby was writing Mosaic Madness, Canada was a
relatively tranquil country in terms of ethnic and racial conflict.
While the decade began with the first Quebec Referendum (1980), the rest
of the decade was void of overt ethnic and racial tensions.
Multicultural policy, however, was "under siege,' as there was
considerable opposition in popular discourse and in the platforms of the
Reform Party and the Conservative Party (Abu-Laban and Stasiulis 1992).
In terms of the implementation of multiculturalism as a policy, this
decade has been referred to as "equity" multiculturalism as
distinct from "ethnicity" and the "song and dance"
multiculturalism of the 1970s. Equity multiculturalism meant that the
focus of the policy was to manage diversity or ethnic and race relations by addressing the problem of systemic discrimination with solutions of
employment equity and equality of opportunity (Fleras and Elliott 2002,
69; Kunz 2007). For Bibby, it was important at this time to be looking
for a more macro-level purpose in Canadian life in the sense of a
"Canadianess" where diverse peoples would engage in a national
conversation. He thought that this was not happening and that people in
Canada did not have any moral bonds or moral consensus (see figs. 2 and
3) and what existed was fragmented pluralism or individual mosaic
fragments. For Bibby, moral consensus was necessary for a civil society.
In a recent blog entitled "Whatever Happened to Mosaic
Madness" (2008), Bibby reflects on his 1990 book and his concept of
mosaic madness. He states:
My presentations [in Japan] involved my revisiting the "mosaic
madness" of the 1990 period. I was intrigued to realize that much of
the madness that characterized Canada then and was anticipated to
continue and perhaps become even worse has largely dissipated. In
2008 we find Canada characterized by a remarkable calm. My data and
that of others such as Michael Adams document what most of us know
experientially--that Canada today seems quite sane, complete with
highly positive interpersonal life, an extremely positive economic
environment, and highly content individuals. In the title of my
first presentation, one might well ask, "Whatever Happened to Mosaic
Madness?"
By the late 1990s, particularly in Europe, the number of critiques
of multiculturalism was increasing, and by the time of the post-9/11 era
the numbers increased dramatically. Nine articles in the Canadian and
European literatures were published between 1990 and 1999. One of the
works from the European literature is examined in the next section.
Multiculturalism is Not the Solution: Michel Wieviorka
Of the European critiques of multiculturalism, Wieviorka's
1998 work tops the list in terms of a clear theoretical explanation and
dissection of the fragmentation critique. His is not only a sociological
approach, but also a political philosophy and a political science
approach. Wieviorka argues that a sociological approach is interested in
the social processes of multicultural societies and the nature of social
differentiation and cultural differences. Moreover, this sociological
approach suggests it is multiculturalism itself that is problematic:
A sociological approach, stricto sensu, will primarily be interested
in the working of the society in which multiculturalism is found, in
the way in which the cultural differences within it are produced,
received or reproduced, and in the questions and tensions which this
generates. This approach will describe multiculturalism as the
problem rather than the response (1998, 883).
As he argues in this quote, ethnic pluralism and cultural
differences are not only reproduced, but they are also in the constant
process of being produced, which means that fragmentation and
recomposition are a permanent probability. He argues that the tendency
for cultural fragmentation is much greater than the tendency and trend
toward homogenization because of the impact of the globalization of the
economy and/or the internationalization of mass culture under American
hegemony (891).
At the beginning of his article he provides a history of the
concept of multiculturalism and then discusses multiculturalism in
practice. He discusses Canada, along with Australia and Sweden, as an
example of a relatively "integrated multiculturalism" (884),
while the U.S. is discussed as an example of a "disintegrated
multiculturalism" (886). He then discusses the tensions inherent in
cultural differences that are produced by multicultural societies even
when some societies are able to demonstrate tensions that may be at
equilibrium. In other cases, disequilibrium is considerable with
tensions reaching a breaking point:
The tensions reach breaking point and the logic of fragmentation
gains the upper hand, with all that this implies--some people
assimilating into the society as a whole, others possibly opting for
radicalization and living in a closed community (892).
In his conclusion Wieviorka cautiously answers the question
embodied in the title of his article and suggests that multiculturalism
is not the solution. He considers that multiculturalism is "more of
a risk than a satisfactory response" and multiculturalist policies
and approaches, as they stand now, are dated and that we now need to go
further than multiculturalism or, in other words, toward
"post-multiculturalism."
In the mid-1990s, when Wieviorka wrote this piece, France was
experiencing a re-emergence of racism and increasing ethnic and
immigrant unrest. For example, the controversial issue of Islamic veils
and head scarves worn by Muslim women and girls in the French public
school system emerged at this time and stirred heated debate. France was
also coming to terms with the tension resulting from the realization of
the economic need for immigrants and immigrant communities and the
growing visibility in, and occupation of, French social spaces by
immigrants. Thus, issues of assimilation, ethnic pluralism, and racial
and ethnic fragmentation came to the forefront of French public policy
and academic discourses.
In the early--and mid-1990s the "clash of civilization"
or "cultural contestation" thesis and discourse had emerged
(Lewis 1990; Huntington 1993, 1996) with the main premise of a
fundamental conflict between the Islamic world and the West. Huntington
had suggested that the fundamental source of conflict in global politics
would no longer be primarily ideological or economic. He stated:
The great divisions among humankind and the dominating source of
conflict will be cultural. Nation states will remain the most
powerful actors in world affairs, but the principal conflicts of
global politics will occur between nations and groups of different
civilizations. The clash of civilizations will dominate global
politics. The fault lines between civilizations will be the battle
lines of the future (1993, 22).
Thus, the critique of multiculturalism as over-emphasizing cultural
relativism and potentially leading to clashes of cultures could, by
extension, be conceptualized also as a domestic clash of civilizations.
The clash of civilization thesis, fraught with over-tones of
Orientalism, was considered by many scholars in the mid- to late-1990s
as simplistic and racist. Nevertheless, Silverman (1992) pointed out
that the headscarves affair in France was symptomatic of a wider
national or nation-state crises in contemporary France related to
immigration, race, and ethnicity. It was at that time, and arguably
still is today, a crisis of the l'etranger and citizenship in
France and also other parts of Europe. In the 1990s these developments
in Europe, along with the "clash of civilization theses," were
a prelude of the discourse that emerged in the 2000s and of
Latour's analysis of the "war of the worlds."
The literature search for the years 2000-2006 produced thirty-five
works. As noted earlier, relative to earlier times, this is a growing
literature, and the next two sections will briefly examine the work of
Latour in 2002 and Abbas in 2005--two prominent examples of the current
period.
War of the Worlds: Bruno Latour
The events of 9/11 and the subsequent Madrid and London train
bombings contributed to the angst that some European sociologists
experience regarding multiculturalism. Moreover, soon after 9/11, the
work of Lewis and Huntington and the "clash of civilizations"
thesis soared in popularity and became more widely accepted.
Latour's focus is the "war of the worlds." He argues
that it has been in existence all along in the so-called "modern
age" (2002, 3-4). He considers that 9/11 served as a reminder that
peace and unity have to be achieved through diplomatic efforts. He
further argues that modernists made the notion of culture sacred and
that this gave rise to multiculturalism of which he is highly critical:
"In this combination of respect and complete indifference, we may
recognize the hypocritical condescension of cultural relativism
..." (15). Latour is highly critical of multiculturalism, and he
states that multiculturalism is a form of condescension of
ethnocentrism. At the height of modernization, according to Latour (16),
the West says that "the one world is ours, the many worlds are
yours; and if your disputes are too noisy, may the world of harsh
reality come in to pacify your disputes," and that this is "a
peculiar offer of peace, one which had never recognized the existence of
a war in the first place!" Latour looks at the rise of both
"globalization" and "fragmentation" and points to a
paradox:
... We identify precisely the deep transformation that took us
out of modernism and the convenient solution it offered to the
problems of unity and multiplicity. Fragmentation shatters
mononaturalism; globalization destroys multiculturalism. On both
sides, whether the aim is to create multiplicity or unity,
opponents, fronts, and violent contradictions are finally
starting to appear (24).
Latour's general message is that humanity might be able work
its way out of the "war of the worlds" given the awareness
that the West can no longer view minority groups as the
"other" and that honest dialogue is essential.
Writing a year after the 9/11 era, Latour is critical of the West
regarding its practice of using cultural relativism in a condescending
way to "others" in the world and thus causing fragmentation at
a global level. This analysis moves downward toward a critique of
multiculturalism at the national level. Arguably ethnic tensions and
hatreds have increased not just in the post-9/11 era, but over the past
couple of decades of neo-liberalism. As Chua (2003) points out, the
movement and exportation of free markets and democracy have not
diminished ethnic and ethno-religious conflict as they were supposed to
do. Rather, the dynamic of globalization and free market democracy have
led to heightened situations where some ethnic groups dominate markets
and contribute to ethnic tensions. This dynamic, she argues, explains
the rise of anti-Americanism in recent decades. Thus the global context
of Latour's work was not just 9/11 as a watershed event, but rather
a global movement that has been occurring for decades.
The Retreat of Multicultural Theory, Policy and Practice: Tahir
Abbas
The post-9/11 era in Europe has seen a retreat in multiculturalism
at the level of theory and policy in many liberal states (Joppke 2004).
This backing away from multiculturalism is due to a perception by policy
makers and many academics that cultural recognition does not contribute
to minority and immigrant integration. Abbas' work reflects this
retreat as he critiques, using the case of British Muslims, liberal
multicultural political philosophy and British multiculturalism policy.
He argues that the management of diversity, through British
multicultural policy, has been ineffective, and he goes so far as to
support the argument made by others for a return to assimilation (2005).
His critique, however, is from the left and is congruent with sub-theme
1 (above), but applied in the British context. He believes that
multiculturalism leads to further ethnic segregation and stratification
under already existing economic and political inequality. He states that
a multicultural society
... is seemingly where "African immigrants clean toilets," and the
"upper-middle-class English gents are lawyers, pilots, surgeons and
hankers." The word multicultural no longer carries with it any
connotation of equality or respect--if it ever did. Worse, it
implies that all "moral obligations" have been met when a society
is "multicultural" (156).
Abbas' argument is that in an already ethnically stratified
society, multiculturalism reinforces the existing fragmentation by not
addressing social inequality. He also argues that multiculturalism
oppresses migrants culturally in that they are obliged to rejoin the
culture of their ancestral origin and that cultures in multiculturalism
are thought to narrowly correspond to existing nation-states producing
cultural nationalism (156). Consequently, he argues that policy needs to
move toward emphasizing "shared citizenship" and areas of
"sameness." For Abbas, the political climate of the time will
determine the future of multiculturalism. He asserts that in Britain the
development of multiculturalism policy is closely tied to what happens
with British Muslims because in the post-9/11 era they have become the
test case and the gaze of the "other" (164).
It must be remembered, however, that official multiculturalism
policy is relatively new in Britain, having been implemented in the late
1990s, and, like multiculturalism policy in the Netherlands, quickly
became a target due in part to specific situations of ethnic and
religious antagonism and terrorist events in Europe in the mid-2000s.
These included, among others, the 2004 murder of Dutch filmmaker Theo
Van Gogh in Amsterdam, the Danish cartoons issue in 2005, the previously
mentioned Madrid and London train bombings, and the "urban
riots" in France in 2005. The practice of multiculturalism was
increasingly associated with forms of "unhealthy" political
transnationalism that made it potentially divisive and fragmentary.
Thus, the context of Abbas' work is a continuation of the times
that began when Latour was writing with a narrower focus on Europe
"being on fire," rather than on the world "being on
fire," (Chua 2003). Much of this discourse utilizes terms such as
"the death of multiculturalism" (Kundnani 2002);
"farewell to multiculturalism?" (Baubock 2002); "retreat
of multiculturalism" (Joppke 2004); "Too Diverse"
(Goodhart 2004); "re-inventing multiculturalism" (Uitermark et
al. 2005). All fall into the purview of the post-multiculturalism genre
in which multiculturalism itself is viewed as being problematic.
DISCUSSION AND CONCLUSION
This last section begins with a discussion of some of the
sociological literature and discourse mentioned above that critiques
multiculturalism as a form of "fragmented pluralism", in light
of multiculturalism as a form of"interactive pluralism." (5)
This is followed by a brief discussion of the policy implications that
this discourse might have for Canada, while being cognizant of the
possibility that academic research in Canada by sociologists has limited
impact and influence on immigration related policies and programs
(Richmond 2000).
The Sociological Literature on "Multiculturalism as
Fragmentation"
The work of the five scholars in the previous section illustrates
aspects of the fragmentation critique of multiculturalism in the
sociological literature over the past three decades and the three
sub-themes of the fragmentation thesis found in the literature review
regarding social divisiveness, clash of cultures, and ethnic
marginalization and stratification. Of these, Porter and Bibby's
work represents Canadian sociological critiques of multiculturalism that
touch on these three sub-themes. These critiques, together with many
non-sociological critics such as Bissoondath (1994), may have led to the
Canadian government commissioned reviews of Canada's
multiculturalism program in the mid-1990s that included the Spicer
Commission and the Brighton Report--the latter including recommendations
that grappled with the fragmentation critique of multiculturalism
(Abu-Laban and Gabriel 2002, 113). Not surprisingly, many popular
non-sociological critiques utilizing the fragmentation perspective can
be found today in popular journalistic form, e.g., Mlan Gregg's
article in The Walrus (2006), and in scholarly studies, e.g., Stein et
al.'s Uneasy Partners (2007).
What all five of the works reviewed have in common is a lack of a
clear meaning or definition of what constitutes societal
"fragmentation." These works point to social divergence,
conflict and tension, and examples thereof, as illustrative of
fragmentation. In many respects, these works take a one-dimensional and
binary approach to multiculturalism (see fig. 1). For example, Bibby
(1990, 14) argues that cultural relativism erases agreement on the norms
that are essential to social life. Antecedent to this is Bibby's
assumption that multiculturalism inevitably leads to relativism. As
Satzewich and Liodakis (2007, 134) illustrated, using examples from
Canadian law, this is not necessarily the case. Further, in response to
Bibby's argument, one could also ask why agreement on procedural
norms, such as rule of law and democracy, is not sufficient and does not
meet the essence of social life. If it is sufficient, then social
cohesion is not at risk and the "fragmentation" is simply at
the level of differential values. One can then ask the question whether
it is necessary for Canadians to have a set of common values, as the
evidence is clear that Canadians diverge on many social issues and
values, (6) which is certainly deemed acceptable in a democracy. What
was assumed here is that these five works fall under the fragmented
pluralism vision (noted earlier) in which multiculturalism is viewed as
disuniting and problematic. If this fragmented pluralism is really
problematic, then the alternative visions are assimilationism,
cosmopolitanism, or interactive pluralism.
According to Jedwab (2005, 96), recent polling shows that more
Canadians agree that multiculturalism helps, rather than hinders,
integration. Yet only one-half of Canadians believe that multicultural
policy helps people of various backgrounds and religions to fully
integrate into Canadian society. If fragmented pluralism is problematic,
as the sociological discourse surrounding this critique of
multiculturalism suggests, then how does a society move toward an
interactive pluralism that involves some substantive moral bonds as the
basis for social cohesion and integration? Fragmented pluralism
represents a "thin" citizenship, while interactive pluralism
represents a "thick" citizenship. What are the conditions
necessary for interactive pluralism to exist? It would require a context
where particularism and universalism are recognized simultaneously. This
would be a new strategic approach to multiculturalism requiring a new
political logic that makes it possible to "effect a new and radical
reconfiguration of the particular and the universal, of liberty and
equality with difference" (Hall 2000, 236). For example, with
regard to Britain, Madood (2005) argues for an extension and
strengthening of multicultural policy so that there is a "politics
of equal respect" that is inclusive of British Muslims in a shared
multicultural Britishness. A new approach also entails the backing away
from culturally essentializing ethnic and immigrant communities and
recognizing that communities and their cultures are not static, but are
undergoing cultural translation. Li (1999, 165-166) points out that one
cannot assume: 1) that ethnicity and race are essentially primordial in
nature; 2) that ethnic culture primarily determines how ethnic groups
relate to each other; or 3) that ethnic groups are distinct and
culturally homogeneous. Hall points out that cultures revise their own
systems of reference, norms, and values in negotiations (2000, 226).
This new strategic approach also entails recognizing that diversity and
difference does not mean fragmentation and lack of social cohesion. Here
Hall draws upon Derrida's work on differance:
This is not the binary form of difference, between what is
absolutely the same, and what is absolutely "Other." It is
a "weave" of similarities and differences that refuse to
separate into fixed binary oppositions (216).
Moreover, he points out that differance does not prevent any system
or society from stabilizing or reaching social cohesion or, as he puts
it, "a fully sutured totality" (216). The current state of
most multiculturalism policies, such as those in Canada, is what Hall
describes as "pluralist multiculturalism," which entails
enfranchising the differences among groups along cultural lines and also
according different grouprights to different communities within a
communitarian political order (210). This is the kind of
multiculturalism that the critics have called fragmented pluralism. To
move to the interactive pluralism vision, there needs to be a civic
component to pluralist multiculturalism.
Soutphommasane (2005, 412) describes civic pluralist
multiculturalism as a form of multicultural citizenship which is
grounded in a shared civic culture, but this civic culture is constantly
exposed to critical collective reflection and re-examination. A move in
this direction of interactive and civic pluralism was advocated by Bibby
(1991) when he advocated the necessity of making "... it possible
for Canadians of diverse backgrounds to interact with each other in
order to speak openly about their differences and concerns, to reflect
on their values and dreams, to evaluate the merits of their respective
ideas and lifestyles." By interacting with each other, the national
Canadian conversation, as advocated by Kymlicka (1998, 175), might
emerge over time and this could lead to a shared identity.
Policy Implications for Canada
It is easy to say that interaction and conversation need to occur
and that when they occur, there is interactive pluralism. However, for
this to actually occur, there are certain ground rules and
presuppositions that would need to be affirmed and accepted by everyone.
Although it should not be thought of as a contested political
battlefield, there is an element of negotiation and contestation that
would be involved. With the waning of assimilationism, there were
increasing numbers of immigrants who demanded that the "reigning
formula" be adapted in order to accommodate them, as opposed to the
other way around (Taylor 2001, 187). This has contributed to a debate
about the nature of integration in many multicultural countries. The
Metropolis Project in Canada has summed up this debate succinctly in an
overview for one of its knowledge transfer sessions (2003) by referring
to two major approaches to frame integration. These two approaches are
referred to as 1) immutable core and 2) dynamic nucleus, with the former
being basically the assimilationism position and the latter being
interactive pluralism. With an immutable core, there is conformity to
common values, language, and culture; with the dynamic nucleus, there is
constant negotiation about what constitutes the core so that there is a
social compact that sees the core as dynamic and evolving over time
(Metropolis 2003). (7) Metropolis outlined these two approaches as a way
of framing the debate and posed it as a question in terms of which one
of these approaches is preferable. The expectation of conformity is
based on the belief that many cultural differences are unbridgeable and
irreconcilable with the core values of democracy and liberalism. Thus,
many academics adopt the principle of conformity to an immutable core as
the benchmark of integration and do not interrogate the relationship
between diversity and integration (Li 2003, 328).
In conclusion, I would argue that the immutable core approach
represents the "old reigning formula" (referred to by Taylor
2001), and that the viability of multiculturalism as social and public
policy requires a vision of interactive pluralism. This can only occur
under a dynamic nucleus approach where there is ongoing discussion,
negotiation, critical collective reflection, and a re-examination of
what Canada is in terms of identity and how it works in terms of social
processes. This, then, would allow movement away from a fragmented
pluralism vision and cultural essentialism that is held by many critics
of multiculturalism, including many influential sociologists whose ideas
have been discussed in this article. The dynamic nucleus approach would
ensure civic pluralist multiculturalism and integrative pluralism. The
persistent challenge would be to negotiate issues related to the
"dynamic nucleus" in a civil and respectful manner that does
not create conflict that would hamper social and political cohesion.
Current Canadian public-policy discourse now uses catchwords and phrases
such as "two-way street," "inclusive citizenship,"
and "identity" (Metropolis 2007; Kunz 2007). Thus, the
fundamental question is whether an interactive pluralism can become a
reality in Canada or whether it remains merely on paper. The Metropolis
Project and Canadian Heritage could certainly take a leadership role and
provide the forum for this to happen--if they have the political will.
ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS
I would like to thank Dr. Anna Kirova and Dr. Joe Garcea for their
helpful comments on earlier drafts of this article. As well, thanks to
Paul Lawton for his research on the literature. I gratefully acknowledge
the funding for the research for this paper and the entire project from
Canadian Heritage and the Prairie Metropolis Centre.
NOTES
(1.) The term "ethnic pluralism" is utilized in this
paper as being synonymous with the term "cultural pluralism and
multiculturalism" Li (1999, 148) points out that
"multiculturalism" while a nebulous concept, has also been
adopted by academics for various analytical interpretations, and thus
has added more confusion to the term.
(2.) Examples of search terms include "post,"
"anti," "critique," "problem"
"fragmentation" combined with "multiculturalism,"
"pluralism," "cultural pluralism," "ethnic
pluralism," "diversity." Of the 46 articles, 18 were
specifically on European countries, 16 on Canada, 5 on other countries
(mostly the United States and Australia), and 7 were not country
specific, but more theoretical in nature.
(3.) More specifically, a classical sociology of knowledge approach
is used here: the production of knowledge is shaped by social structures
and the social locations of individuals (who are producing the
knowledge) within those structures (Mannheim 1936, 282; Meja and Stehr
1999).
(4.) A crude discourse analysis of the words in the title of this
book suggests that the mosaic or multiculturalism is pathological and
deviant ("madness" and "pluralism [as in rebel] without a
cause") although Bibby may not have meant it to be interpreted this
way.
(5.) These obviously include such values as those concerning
abortion, capital punishment, gun control, the welfare state, same-sex
marriage, and many others. Satzewich and Liodakus (2007, 133) point out
that those critics of multiculturalism who appeal to the
"national" character of Canada are usually vague in describing
what constitutes Canadian culture, by which they usually mean the
Anglo-tradition, and are also vague in defining what Canadian values
are.
(6.) See figs. 2 and 3. The other visions of assimilationism and
cosmopolitanism, while important, are not the focus here.
Assimilationism would involve the "strategy of privatization"
of cultural differences and conflict (Barry 2001, chap. 2) and is part
of the recent liberal critique of multiculturalism. Cosmopolitanism
remains an important conceptualization and recent work by Delanty and He
(2008), for example, link critical cosmopolitanism to Asian and European
transnationalism.
(7.) These two approaches were described by Metropolis as follows:
The first approach revolves around the belief that a strong
immutable core--often defined as national identity--is essential
for the successful integration of newcomers. Indeed, this approach
maintains that integration is only possible when newcomers and
those in the "host" society understand and adhere to the
component parts of the core.... In this first approach, an
exclusive national identity, or immutable core, is strongly
articulated through shared values, a shared language, shared
ethnicity and culture, or, in the most extreme form, racial or
religious homogeneity. Newcomers must accept and conform to this
core and its articulations to be granted citizenship....
Proponents of this approach fear that a country with a weak sense
of national identity is prone to fractures and fault-lines....
They may also believe that immigration-fuelled diversity challenges
a stable national identity and may threaten the core values of
the "host" society.
The other approach revolves around the belief that the core can,
and indeed must, evolve by including citizens and newcomers in
ongoing discussion on the construction of the national identity.
This, proponents suggest, ensures support for shared
responsibilities, values and goals.... The composition of a
national identity is viewed as an on-going process that engages
newcomers and fosters a sense of shared citizenship ... and acts
as the dynamic nucleus that holds a diverse citizenry together.
Proponents of this approach maintain that the social compact is
renewed and reinforced when national identity is allowed to evolve
through discussions between newcomers and "host" societies that
allow them to redefine and re-articulate the values and
responsibilities that comprise their shared citizenship
(Metropolis 2003).
WORKS CITED
Abbas, Tahir. 2005. Recent Developments in British Multicultural
Theory, Policy, and Practice: The Case of British Muslims. Citizenship
Studies 9.2: 153-166.
Abu-Laban, Yasmeen, and Daiva Stasiulis. 1992. Ethnic Pluralism
under Siege: Popular and Partisan Opposition to Multiculturalism.
Canadian Public Policy 18.4: 365-386.
Abu-Laban, Yasmeen, and Christina Gabriel. 2002. Selling Diversity:
Immigration, Multiculturalism, Employment Equity, and Globalization.
Peterborough: Broadview Press.
Barry, Brian. 2001. Culture and Equality. Cambridge: Polity Press.
Baubock, Rainer. 2002. Farewell to Multiculturalism? Sharing Values
and Identities in Societies of Immigration. Journal of International
Migration and Integration 3.1: 1-16.
Bibby, Reginald. 1990. Mosaic Madness: Pluralism without a Cause.
Toronto: Stoddart.
--. 1991. Toward Dignifying Diversity. Globe and Mail, October 9.
http://www.reginaldbibby.com/fromthearchives.html
--. 2008. Whatever Happened to Mosaic Madness? Bibby's
Blog--Research, Reflections, and Rants, March 1.
http://reginaldbibby.blogspot.com/
Bissoondath, Neil. 1994. Selling Illusions: The Cult of
Multiculturalism in Canada. Toronto: Penguin.
Buchignani, Norman. 1982. Canadian Ethnic Research and
Multiculturalism. Journal of Canadian Studies 17.1: 16-34.
Chua, Amy. 2003. World on Fire: How Exporting Free Murket Democracy
Breeds Ethnic Hatred and Global Instability. New York: Anchor Bonks.
Corbella, Licia. 2006a. Dangerous Disconnect. Calgary Sun, June 11.
--. 2006b. Sociology Prof Warns Multiculturalism Creates
"Nations within Nation." Calgary Sun, June 19.
Delanty, Gerard, and Baogang He. 2008. Cosmopolitan Perspectives on
European and Asian Transnationalism. International Sociology 23.3:
323-344.
Fleras, Augie, and Jean Elliott. 2002. Engaging Diversity:
Multiculturalism in Canada. 2nd ed. Toronto: Nelson.
Goodhart, David. 2004. Too Diverse? Prospect 95.
http://www.prospect-magazine.co.uk/articledetails.php?id-5835
Gregg, Mlan. 2006. Identity Crisis. The Walrus 3.2: 38-47.
Hall, Stuart. 2000. Conclusion: The Multi-cultural Question. In
Un/settled Multiculturalisms: Diasporas, Entanglements,
"Transruptions," ed. B. Hesse, 209-241. London: Zed Books.
Hartmann, Douglas, and Joseph Gerteis. 2005. Dealing with
Diversity: Mapping Multiculturalism in Sociological Terms. Sociological
Theory 23.2: 218-240.
Huntington, Samuel. 1993. The Clash of Civilizations? Foreign
Affairs 72.3: 22-49.
--.1996. The Clash of Civilizations and the Remaking of World
Order. New York: Simon and Schuster.
Jedwab, lack. 2005. Neither Finding nor Losing Our Way: The Debate
over Canadian Multiculturalism. Canadian Diversity 4.1: 95-102.
Joppke, Christian. 2004. The Retreat of Multiculturalism in the
Liberal State: Theory and Policy. British Journal of Sociology 55.2:
237-257.
Kallen, Evelyn. 1982. Multiculturalism: Ideology, Policy, and
Reality. Journal of Canadian Studies 17.1:5163.
Kirkham, Della, 1998. The Reform Party of Canada: Discourse on
Race, Ethnicity, and Equality. In Racism and Social Inequality in
Canada, ed. V. Satzewich, 243-267. Toronto: Thompson Educational.
Kundani, Arun. 2002. The Death of Multiculturalism. London:
Institute of Race Relations.
http://www.irr.org.uk/2002/april/ak000001.html
Kunz, Jean. 2007. Multicultural Canada in the 21st Century:
Harnessing Opportunities and Managing Pressures. Cultural Diversity.
http://www.policyresearch.gc.ca/page.asp?pagenm=rp_mult_bkg
Kymlicka, Will. 1998. Finding Our Way: Rethinking Ethnocultural
Relations in Canada. Toronto: Oxford University Press.
Latour, Bruno. 2002. War of the Worlds: What About Peace? Chicago:
Prickly Press.
Lewis, Bernard. 1990. The Roots of Muslim Rage. Atlantic Monthly
266.3: 47-60.
Li, Peter. 2003. Deconstructing Canada's Discourse of
Immigrant Integration. Journal of International Migration and
Integration 4.3:315-333.
--.1999. The Multicultulturalism Debate. In Race and Ethnic
Relations in Canada, 2nd ed., ed. P.S. Li, 148-177. Don Mills, ON:
Oxford University Press.
Madood, Tariq. 2005. Remaking Multiculturalism after 7/7. Open
Democracy. http://www.opendemocracy.net/conflict-terrorism/multiculturalism_2879.jsp
Mannheim, Karl. 1936. Ideology and Utopia. New York: Harcourt,
Brace.
Meja, Volker, and Nico Stehr. 1999. Introduction. In The Sociology
of Knowledge, ed. Volker Meja and Nico Stehr, xiii-xxvi. Northampton,
MA: Edward Elgar.
Metropolis. 2003. Metropolis Presents: Shared Citizenship:
Immutable Core of Dynamic Nucleus? Ottawa: October 14.
http://canada.metropolis.net/events/
metropolis_presents/shared-citizenship/index_e.htm
Metropolis. 2007. Metropolis Phase III (2007-2012) Annexes A-L,
Memorandum of Understanding between Social Sciences and Humanities
Research Council and Citizenship and Immigration Canada.
http://canada.metropolis.net/policypriority/citizenship_e.htm
Porter, John. 1972. Dilemmas and Contradictions of a Multi-ethnic
Society. Transactions of the Royal Society of Canada 10.4: 193-205.
--. 1975. Ethnic Pluralism in Canadian Perspective. In Ethnicity,
Theory and Experience, ed. N. Glazer and D. Moynihan, 267-304,
Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
--. 1979a. Ethnic Pluralism in Canadian Perspective. In The Measure
of Canadian Society, ed. J. Porter, 103 - 138. Toronto: Gage.
--.1979b. Melting Pot or Mosaic: Revolution or Reversion? In The
Measure of Canadian Society, ed. J. Porter, 139-162. Toronto: Gage.
--. 1965. The Vertical Mosaic. Toronto: University of Toronto Press.
Prins, Baukje, and Boris Slijper. 2002. Multicultural Society under
Attack. Journal of International Migration and Integration 3.3-4:
313-328.
Richmond, Anthony H. 2000. Immigration and Policy Research in
Canada: Pure or Applied? Journal of Ethnic and Migration Studies 26.1:
109-125.
Roberts, Lance, and Rodney Clifton. 1990. Multiculturalism in
Canada: A Sociological Perspective. In Race and Ethnic Relations in
Canada, 1st ed., ed. P.S. Li, 120-147. Don Mills, ON: Oxford University
Press.
Satzewich, Vic, and Nikolaos Liodakis. 2007. Race and Ethnicity in
Canada: A Critical Introduction. Don Mills, ON: Oxford University Press.
Silverman, Maxim, 1992. Deconstructing the Nation: Immigration,
Racism, and Citizenship in Modern France. London: Routedge.
Soutphommasane, Tim. 2005. Grounding Multicultural Citizenship:
From Minority Rights to Civic Pluralism. Journal of Intercultural
Studies 26.4:401-416.
Stein, Janice, David Cameron, John Ibbitson, Will Kymlicka, John
Meisel, Haroon Siddiqui, and Michael Valpy, eds. 2007. Uneasy Partners.
Waterloo: Wilfrid Laurier University Press.
Taylor, Charles. 2001. Democracy, Inclusive and Exclusive. In
Meaning and Modernity: Religion, Polity, and the Self, ed. R. Madsen, W.
Sullivan, A. Swidler, and S. Tipton, 181-194. Berkeley: University of
California Press.
Vertovec, Steven. n.d. Pre-, High-, Anti- and
Post-Multiculturalism. Institute for European Studies.
http://www.ies.be/activities/multicult/vertovec-ies.pdf
Uitermark, Justis, Ugo Rossi, and HenkVan Houtum. 2005.
Re-inventing Multiculturalism: Urban Citizenship and the Negotiation of
Ethnic Diversity in Amsterdam. International Journal of Urban and
Regional Research 29.3: 622-640.
Wieviorka, Michel. 1998. Is Multiculturalism the Solution? Ethnic
and Racial Studies 21.5:881-910.
Winter, Elke. 2005. Debating Binationalism and Multiculturalism in
Canada: Toward a Sociology of Ethnic Pluralism. Ph.D. diss., York
University. In Dissertations & Theses: Full Text.
http://www.proquest.com/Publication number AAT NR11642
LLOYD WONG is associate professor of Sociology at the University of
Calgary and a research affiliate and domain leader at the Prairie
Metropolis Centre. His research interests include ethnicity,
immigration, transnationalism, and citizenship.
Fig. 2. A two-dimensional framework.
Dimension 2 Dimension 1
Basis for Social Cohesion
Basis for Association Substantive Moral Bonds Procedural Norms
Individual in Society Assimilationism Cosmopolitanism
Mediating Groups I Interactive Pluralism Fragmented Pluralism
Source: Adapted with permission from Hartmann and Gerteis, 224, fig. 2.