Postulations on the fragmentary effects of multiculturalism in Canada.
Garcea, Joseph
INTRODUCTION
Multiculturalism has been the subject of substantial debates in
Canada during the past four decades (Wilson 1993; Abu-Laban 1994;
Sugunasiri 1999; Fleras and Elliot 2002). Such debates have intensified
during the most recent decade largely as a result of the attention
devoted by the media to, among other things, the large influx of
immigrants and refugees who are members of visible minorities, the
claims for and responses to what is now being termed reasonable
accommodations, and the actual and potential acts of terrorism. The
debates have focused primarily on what Fleras and Elliott (2002, 108)
have referred to as the "dialectics of multiculturalism"
regarding tive sets of positive and negative effects of multiculturalism
public philosophy and public policy (i.e., divisive vs. unifying,
essentializing vs. hybridizing, marginalizing vs. inclusive, hoax vs.
catalyst, and hegemony vs. counter-hegemony), the myths and fallacies of
multiculturalism (Burnet 1979; Peter 1981, Fleras and Elliot 2002,
112-116), and what have been described as real and perceived
contradictions related to multiculturalism (Saul 2005).
One of the central questions in such debates has been whether
multiculturalism contributes either to harmony and integration or
conflict and fragmentation within the Canadian polity. The question
applies to the effects of both the public philosophy of multiculturalism
(i.e., the normative framework that values the co-existence and
perpetuation of diverse cultures) (1) and the public policy of
multiculturalism (i.e., the actual policy and program initiatives
undertaken by various orders of government designed to deal with the
co-existence and perpetuation of diverse cultures) (Kallen 1982). (2)
That question has generated a set of postulations proffered by
postulators who believe that multiculturalism philosophy and policy have
fragmentary effects within the Canadian polity. (3)
This article has two central objectives: first, to provide an
overview and analysis of the postulations regarding the fragmentary
effects of multiculturalism philosophy and policy articulated during the
past forty years in books and journal articles within the Canadian
literature written in English; second, to provide some observations
regarding the importance that policy makers should attach to those
postulations and the type and degree of attention that they should
devote to them.
This article is based on a content analysis of a select set of
publications on Canadian multiculturalism public philosophy and public
policy written between 1965 and 2005 largely by social scientists and a
few other prominent authors and analysts. The goal was to identify some,
rather than all, publications that articulated various postulations.
Thus, the dozens of publications profiled in this article constitute
only a representative sample of a potentially larger set of publications
that articulate the various postulations. The publications were selected
through a combination of a library and web-based bibliographic search
and a scanning of the bibliographic references contained in the
publications located through the library and web-based bibliographic
search. The key words used for the searches were "Canadian
multiculturalism" and "criticisms of Canadian
multiculturalism" The postulations that are the focus of this
article were identified through a content analysis of the select set of
dozens of publications that dealt with the fragmentary effects of
Canadian multiculturalism public philosophy and public policy. More
specifically, they were identified by grouping comparable arguments
regarding the fragmentary effects of multiculturalism public philosophy
and public policy, and then producing a descriptive title and
description of the postulation embodied in each group arguments.
Before providing the overview and analysis of the postulations,
three important caveats and some information regarding the methodology
are in order. First, the differences between some of the postulations
are relatively subtle; indeed, some of the postulations are interrelated and overlapping. Nevertheless, for analytical purposes it is useful to
discuss them separately. Second, the identification of the commentators
who articulate those postulations is selective or exemplary, rather than
comprehensive or exhaustive. Third, it should not be assumed that all of
those who articulate any of the postulations are necessarily against
multiculturalism either as a public philosophy or as a public policy.
Indeed, as noted in a subsequent section of this artide, some of them
are supportive of either or both of those, but they want to see some
clarifications or correctives to those that they perceive as
problematical in achieving any one or more of the desired goals.
OVERVIEW OF POSTULATIONS
Postulation 1: Multiculturalism promotes the creation of segregated
racial and ethno-cultural enclaves
The first postulation is that multiculturalism policy, in
combination with immigration policy, creates segregated racial and
ethnocultural enclaves within local communities (Brotz 1980; Ogmundson
1992; Paquet 1988; James 1996; James and Shadd 2001; Stoffman 2002 and
2004). The postulators maintain that whereas immigration policy
facilitates the concentration of the bulk of immigrants with similar
racial or ethnocultural backgrounds into a few major cities and, in some
cases even a few neighbourhoods therein, multiculturalism policy
promotes and supports the creation of ethno-specific secular and
religious institutions to serve the needs of each major ethno-cultural
community. They add that some racial and ethno-cultural groups are able
to achieve and maintain a substantial degree of institutional
completeness that, in turn, accentuates segregation and social distances
between members of those groups and members of other groups.
This postulation was cogently articulated and popularized by Neil
Bissoondath who suggested that multiculturalism has the effect of
"... ensuring that ethnic groups will preserve their
distinctiveness in a gentle and insidious form of cultural
apartheid" and will "... lead an already divided country down
the path to further social divisiveness" (1994, 82-83).
Those who proffer this postulation suggest that such distancing
contributes to the fragmentation of the populace and that possible
negative effects include matters discussed in subsequent sections of
this article. The most notable of such effects are: the diminishing of
the fundamental unity of the Canadian state and society (Brotz 1980,
44); the growth of ethnocentrism and segmentation and the resurgence of
racism under a different name (Paquet 1988, 10-11; Sugunarisi 1999,
57-75, 109-114); and ultimately the disintegration of the Canadian
polity (Ogmundson 1992, 52).
Postulation 2: Multiculturalism creates multiple social and
political identities and divided loyalties
The second postulation is that multiculturalism creates multiple
social and political identities and divided loyalties. This postulation
was originally articulated in the mid-1960s by John Porter who suggested
that one of the key problems with Canada was its fragmented social and
political structures. Such fragmentation, he argued, creates a strong
emphasis on ethnic differentiation that, in turn, creates dual
loyalties--one to the various groups and one to the country--that
prevent the emergence of a singular Canadian identity (Porter 1965,
558).
Porter's postulation was echoed in the early 1990s by several
authors who suggested that multiculturalism contributed to the emergence
of multiple nationalities, divided loyalties, and the fragmentation of
Canadian identity. Bibby argued that, contrary to what its proponents
argue, multiculturalism does not really achieve the stated goal of
"harmonious existence" (1990, 7-8). Gairdner concurred with
this and went so far as to suggest that multiculturalism, along with
bilingualism and immigration, contributed to the silent destruction of
English Canada (Gairdner 1990, 389-420). Ogmundson argued that, contrary
to what its advocates suggested, multiculturalism policy was not needed
to reduce social inequalities (1992, 50-51), and added that, since
Canada has a "balkanized culture and a paucity of
nationalism," the federal government must concentrate on building a
singular national identity and a stronger primary loyalty to the
country. Many critics of multiculturalism go even farther in postulating
that multiculturalism has "undermined national unity"
(McRoberts 1997, 131) and that multiculturalism does not square as well
as multinationalism with Canadian federalism (McRoberts 2003, 105).
In recent years, this particular postulation regarding the effects
of multiculturalism on identities and loyalties has also been
articulated by other analysts. HowardHassmann for example, notes that
despite many salutary effects of Canadian multiculturalism policy in
conveying the message that this is a progressive and welcoming country,
it tends to encourage "individuals to think of themselves, and
identify themselves, in terms of their ancestral ethnicity" and
renders it "difficult to instill a sense of Canadian identity in
the population at large" (1999, 525). She adds that the heavy
influence of what she terms group-based "illiberal multiculturalism" espoused by some newcomers tends to accentuate the existence of members of ethnocultural groups with attachments to
their ancestral origins from other countries and negates the existence
of members of ethno-culturally hybridized group, which she refers to as
"ethnic Canadians," who do not have such attachments. She
concludes that what she terms "liberal multiculturalism,"
which focuses on a broader set of diversities and the rights of
individuals, rather than groups, is much more relevant and constructive
for the evolving nature of the Canadian policy, than the illiberal
group-based version.
In a similar vein, Mirchandani and Tastsoglou (2000) note that,
ironically, multiculturalism's drive towards "tolerance"
actually contributes to fragmentation by profiling and accentuating
group differences. Similarly, Barry suggests that multiculturalism
contributes to the "politicization of group identities" (2001,
5) and creates a majority-minority duality and enhances the notion of
"otherness" (11-15) that leads racial and ethno-cultural
groups and their members to develop and act upon their group identities
within the political sphere. Barry criticizes proponents of Canadian
multiculturalism philosophy and public policy such as Kymlicka (1998)
and Tully (1995), whom he disparagingly refers to as an "itinerant band of likeminded theorists," for their unwillingness to
acknowledge that the development of such group identifies and the
actions that flow from them are problematical, rather than salutary, for
the Canadian polity.
Postulation 3: Multiculturalism hinders the production and
perpetuation of a singular "Canadian civic culture" with a
"Canadian moral centre"
The third postulation is that multiculturalism hinders the
production and perpetuation of a singular Canadian civic culture with a
Canadian moral centre. This position, initially articulated by Porter
(1965), has been echoed during the past two decades by several analysts
(Bibby 1990; Bissoondath 1994; Roy 1995; Esses and Gardner 1996; Gwyn
1996; Granatstein 1998; Kay 1998). The general concern among these
analysts is that multiculturalism inevitably leads to the emergence of
multiple and divergent normative frameworks that are likely to intensify
intolerance and conflict. Several of them have noted that two problems
stand in the way of the production and perpetuation of a singular
Canadian civic culture. The first is that multiculturalism fosters a
reluctance to identify and proselytize a singular set of Canadian values
and norms. The second is that within the multiculturalism paradigm there
is no imperative for ethno-cultural groups to espouse one set of
Canadian values or practices and to assimilate. Instead, it encourages
and supports the efforts of a wide range of such groups, with different
cultural and religious backgrounds, values, and practices to maintain
and perpetuate their distinct cultures (Esses and Gardner 1996). This,
they argue, creates a normative relativism that compromises efforts to
develop a set of widely shared set of norms and values (Porter 1965;
Granatstein 1998).
According to Bibby, for example, multiculturalism has compounded
the fragmentary effects of contemporary liberalism ideology by
privileging individualism, pluralism, and relativism over hegemonic
social and political norms shared by the majority of the population.
Bibby thinks that pluralism establishes choices and that relativism
declares those choices valid. He maintains that excessive
"relativism has slain moral consensus" and has "stripped
us of our ethical and moral guidelines, leaving us with no authoritative
instruments at the national level with which to measure social
life" (1990, 14). He makes it clear that he is not opposed to
individualism, pluralism and relativism, but to what he considers the
excesses that they have spawned (10).
This postulation is also evident in an article by Gregg in which he
argues that the secular humanism and liberalism that underpin
immigration, settlement, and multiculturalism policies in Canada have
resulted in an increase in the number of people without allegiances to
the Canadian nation or state or with due appreciation and respect for
the prevailing values, some of whom are willing to undertake radical
political action, including actual or attempted acts of terrorism
comparable to those witnessed in many countries prior to, on, and after
9/11. Gregg suggests that there may be some validity to suggestions that
Canada's multiculturalism experiment may have gone wrong, and that
the time has come to review it and possibly reform it (2006, 47).
The postulation that multiculturalism hinders the production and
perpetuation of a singular Canadian civic culture with a Canadian, or at
least a western, moral centre is also articulated by Kay. In explaining
the backlash against multiculturalism, he notes that one of the major
problems is that the accommodation of the distinct values of various
minority groups leads to an unacceptable and problematical normative
relativism that confronts and challenges the moral and social fabric of
the country (1998, 31). He adds that the prevailing view is that
whenever there is a conflict between any such values and fundamental
liberal principles like freedom of speech and equality before the law,
those values are not acceptable within the parameters set for
multiculturalism (32-33). He concludes by siding with conservatives who
suggest that there is, and that there must be, a limit to the degree of
tolerance and accommodation for values that are not commensurate with
western cultural values that prevail in Canada and other liberal
democracies.
Postulation 4: Multiculturalism hinders the development and
delivery of a singular "civic education"
The fourth postulation is that multiculturalism hinders the
development and delivery of a singular civic education (Brotz 1980).
Granatstein (1998) maintains that the irrational and unexamined
assumptions of what he terms "multiculturalism mania"
contributes to fragmentation within Canada in two ways. First,
multiculturalism has seriously compromised the content and quality of
teaching many important aspects of Canadian history. Second, the
propagation of multiculturalism has produced a misallocation of
governmental resources needed for the integration of newcomers. He
argues that resources that are being devoted to supporting
multiculturalism policies and programs should be devoted both to turning
immigrants into citizens as quickly as possible and also to educating
both those seeking Canadian citizenship and those who already have it
about Canada's history, its shared civic culture, and the
importance of the perpetuation of that civic culture to provide the
social and political glue needed to secure not only a singular Canadian
identity but also the optimal degree of solidarity and unity.
Postulation 5: Multiculturalism hinders the construction of a
shared civic citizenship or intercultural citizenship
The fifth postulation is that multiculturalism hinders the
construction of a shared civic citizenship or intercultural citizenship.
This postulation is articulated by several academic analysts who believe
that there is a fundamental difference between the multiculturalism and
interculturalism paradigms, and who favour the latter over the former.
Hutcheon, for example, states that the latter should be privileged over
the former because there is a "dark side to multiculturalism"
(1994, 1). She argues that whereas multiculturalism emphasizes the
retention of group identities and differences that foster social
distance and segregation, interculturalism emphasizes the breaking down
of such identities and differences as "all citizens (longtime as
well as new) are nourished by an ever-expanding general culture"
(ibid.). In a similar vein, Gagnon suggests that Canada's
multiculturalism model is more problematic than Quebec's
interculturalism model. He argues that in Canada social fragmentation is
the result of accepting the existence of cultural groups as distinct and
self-contained entities "... without any expectation that they may
contribute to the overall direction of the larger society in an
evolutionary interplay of ideas" (2000, 21). He adds that the
principal virtue of Quebec's interculturalism model is its ability
to establish a balance between the requirements of unity by providing
everyone with a shared identity (i.e., as francophone Quebecois) and the
recognition, understanding, and appreciation of different cultures.
The hindrance that state-sponsored multiculturalism policy has
posed for a shared civic or intercultural citizenship has also been
articulated by others. Day (2000, 3-4), for example, suggests that this
"state-sponsored attempt to design a unified nation has
paradoxically led to an increase in both the number of minority entities
and in the amount of effort required to 'manage' them."
To overcome this problem, he proposes what might be termed a libertarian
or anarchical laissez-faire multiculturalism model wherein the policy
role of the state would shift from the proactive management of
multiculturalism to a passive or even non-existent one. This would
entail the abandonment not only of the current multiculturalism policy,
but also of what he depicts as an unrealistic and unhealthy fixation
with a type of group harmony and unity that is simply not attainable. He
summarizes his libertarian or anarchical laissez-faire position as
follows (225):
Instead of the nation-state being wielded as a tool to build
a pre-designed nation, the Canadian state's role would be to
create a space of free play. It would be seen not as a
guardian of a perfect, yet fragile order, but as providing
a minimal field of structure out of which almost anything
might emerge, and where even this minimal role would not
have essential content, but would itself be subject to
ongoing revision. Not a static, solidified order, but a
dynamic and fluid chaos.
Postulation 6: Multiculturalism frustrates the aspirations of
Quebecois nationalists and Aboriginal nationalists
The sixth postulation is that multiculturalism frustrates the
aspirations of Quebecois nationalists and Aboriginal nationalists. The
postulators posit that Canadian multiculturalism has created uneasiness
and even resistance among many nationalist Quebecers and Aboriginals
because it recognizes the existence of a multiplicity of groups and
views all groups as essentially the same in terms of claims and rights
(McRoberts 1997; McRoberts 2003, 105).
The criticism of the adverse effects of multiculturalism for the
aspirations of Quebecois nationalists has been articulated by analysts
such as Breton (2000), Gagnon (2000), and Gagnon and Iacovino (2002).
They point out that while some of the Quebecois nationalists share the
view that multiculturalism has an adverse effect on the national and
linguistic duality valued by Quebecois who subscribe to the "two
founding nations theory" of Canada, others share the view that
multiculturalism is contributing to the loss of community within the
Quebecois nation because the existing communitarianism is being
superseded by excessive individualism, cultural relativism and deepening
diversity.
A substantial critique of the adverse effects of multiculturalism
on the Quebecois nation and to some extent also on the Aboriginal
nations has been provided by Gagnon. In his view, the multiculturalism
paradigm is flawed because, "while seemingly respectful of
differences on the surface, [it] is actually homogenizing (in a federal
context) due to its failure to distinguish between 'ethnic'
minorities and 'national' communities" such as the
Quebecois nation and the Aboriginal nations (2000, 20). He concludes
that any benefits that the Canadian government hoped to achieve by
establishing this comparability or parity between immigrant ethnic
communities and national communities is more than offset by the
antipathy that it creates among Quebecois and Aboriginal nationalists
who are inclined to view multiculturalism as a Machiavellian strategy
designed to negate two conceptions of those communities within the
Canadian polity which they value very highly. The first is the negation of their respective conceptions that they are distinct nations and, in
the minds of some of them, even relatively sovereign nations within a
multinational Canadian polity. The second is their respective
conceptions of the fundamental nature of federalism within that polity,
which for Quebec nationalists is the "dual-nation federalism"
model in which the English and the French are the two founding nations,
and for Aboriginal nationalists it is the "treaty federalism"
model in which Aboriginal nations are also party to the original and
continuing compacts that led to the construction of a Canadian polity.
Postulation 7: Multiculturalism facilitates the importation and
perpetuation of ethnic and religious conflicts from other countries
The seventh postulation is that multiculturalism facilitates the
importation and perpetuation of ethnic and regional conflicts from other
countries. Those who articulate this postulation suggest that liberal
immigration and multiculturalism policies in recent decades have
accelerated and increased not only the diversity of Canada's
population, but also the level of inter-group and intra-group conflicts
via political and cultural transnationalism. Field (2003, 397), for
example, maintains that such conflicts exist because ethnic groups bring
with them legacies of conflict from their countries of origin. This
postulation has gained greater prominence in recent years as a result of
the increased linkages of ethnocultural communities in Canada and their
Countries of origin resulting from at least two major factors. One
factor is the particularistic form of transnationalism that fosters
affinities and connections across national boundaries between members of
a particular nation or ethnocultural group. The other factor is
extensive news coverage of the various types of linkages among members
of such groups in supporting, among other things, resistance and
liberation movements, rebellions and revolutions, and acts of terrorism.
Kay (1998, 31) has suggested that this postulation is rooted more in the
public perception, than in reality. He maintains that regardless of the
empirical evidence on this matter, when some people think of
multiculturalism, they generally think of immigrant groups importing
conflicts into Canada. Other analysts have added that the perception of
imported conflict is fostered not only by people's preconceptions
of the effects of multiculturalism policies, but also by the goals and
rationales of government policies produced in response to problematical
situations, such as those enacted for security purposes in the wake of
9/11 (Kruger and Korenic 2004, 72-78). This last point is an important
reminder regarding the need to take careful stock in selecting policy
responses to problematical situations.
Postulation 8: Multiculturalism creates conflicts within
ethno-cultural groups
The eighth postulation is that multiculturalism creates conflicts
within ethno-culrural groups. At the core of this postulation is the
notion that ethnic groups are not as homogenous and essentialized as the
multiculturalism paradigm suggests. There are differences of values and
preferences within groups on an array of matters, and conflicts are
particularly acute when there are fundamental differences in cultural
and religious values between what are commonly referred to as the
"orthodox fundamentalists" and the "modernists." In
addition to creating intra-group problems, such differences could
potentially result in the establishment and operation of intragroup
tyrannies that impose particularistic normative frameworks that conflict
with the norms and values of the national civic culture. To ensure that
this does not happen, such critics argue that it is imperative for the
state to set limits to such particularistic normative frameworks that
not only run counter to the norms of the national civic culture, but
actually harm others either within or outside the ethnocultural group.
Cohen-Almagor, for example, asks what the limits should be in the face
of increased cultural fragmentation in tolerating individuals and groups
who are importing norms and practices that run counter to those espoused
by the majority in host countries such as Canada. He argues that some
things lie beyond the limits of toleration of liberal democracies and
that "democracy cannot endure norms that deny respect to people and
that are designed to harm others, although they might be dictated by
some cultures." He asserts that the reason for this is that the
right of a group against its own members is not absolute (2001, 83). For
this reason, and "to prevent the likelihood of coercion and
abuse," he argues that it is important that liberal democracies
such as Canada set limits to multiculturalism that result in the
stretching of accepted norms and practices (90). Those who share this
view tend to emphasize the importance of either or both a greater
commitment to the appreciation and application of a "rule of
law" that applies to all groups and individuals regardless of their
ethnocultural or religious background and the adoption of and conformity
to the values of a national civic culture.
Postulation 9: Multiculturalism fosters competition and inequality
between groups
The ninth postulation is that multiculturalism fosters competition
and inequality between ethnocultural groups as well as within
ethnocultural groups. Paquet (1988, 11) expresses concern regarding the
potential dangers of multiculturalism in fostering inequality of
ethnocultural groups, and cautions that the idea that each ethnocultural
group can be different but equal is an illusion because, ultimately, an
ethnic hierarchy will emerge. Some have suggested that this inequality
results from the political dynamics between the relationships of the
leadership of ethnocultural groups and some political parties whereby
the former seek political status and financial resources to advance the
group's and personal interests and the latter seek various forms of
support to win elections (Brimelow 1986, 142-143; Gairdner 1990,
392-396). In a similar vein, Ogmundson (1992, 52) suggests that
eventually multiculturalism will have dire consequences for Canada
because it fosters group competition and "after some period of
struggle a very clear group hierarchy will emerge" and thereafter
"life chances will again be a direct consequence of ethnic
background" Moreover, he disputes the claim that multiculturalism
is needed to combat ethnic stratification because, in his words,
"Serious and competent work has shown that ethnic stratification is
minimal (ethnicity explains only two percent of the variance in
socio-economic status), is declining, and looks good in an international
perspective" (50).
Postulation 10: Multiculturalism hinders the mobilization of
activism for progressive policies in achieving an equitable distribution
of economic and social benefits
The tenth postulation, and closely related to the ninth, is that
multiculturalism hinders the mobilization of activism for progressive
policies in achieving an equitable distribution of economic and social
benefits. Multiculturalism is viewed as reactionary and anti-egalitarian
because it tends to preserve an existing hierarchically ordered
socio-economic class structure that favours some ethnocultural groups
over others (Bannerji 2000). A related critique of this feature of
multiculturalism policy is that it offers members of ethnocultural
groups "... an illusion of cultural freedom, while denying them any
real power" (Peter 1981, 8) within the political and economic
systems.
Porter articulates this notion in his discussion of the
perpetuation of the vertical mosaic in Canada. He argues that the
vertical mosaic is perpetuated not only because within the Canadian
polity some groups are privileged over others, but also because
segregation within Canada's polyethnic society perpetuates certain
occupational choices among members of various ethnocultural groups. The
reason for this, according to Porter, is that when ethnic groups are
closely knit, as they are in Canada, certain occupational choices are
encouraged while others are discouraged. In effect, he is arguing that
tightly knit ethnocultural geographic enclaves create ethnocultural
occupational enclaves. This type of occupational enclaving or
clustering, he argues, contributes to the difficulties faced by members
of some ethnic groups to move from a lower into a higher socio-economic
class (1965, 558).
Similarly, Mazurek (1992, 21) suggests that multiculturalism policy
does not contribute to progressive politics and policy largely because
not all of the original goals of that policy were being pursued to the
same extent. He argues that rather than focusing on improving the
material well-being of members of multicultural groups, too much
attention and too many resources were devoted to facilitating the
nurturing, perpetuation, and social acceptance of diverse cultures.
One critic of Canadian multiculturalism philosophy and policy
argues that multiculturalism is anti-egalitarian in the economic domain
because "the politics of multiculturalism undermines the politics
of redistribution" (Barry 2001, 8, 11-12, 317). He believes that
the tendency of the politics of multiculturalism to produce
particularistic policies aimed at ethnocultural groups, rather than the
population as a whole, is especially problematic.
A similar critique regarding the adverse effects of at least one
facet of multiculturalism policy on equity in the context of the arts
sector is articulated by Li. He notes that funding for the arts in
Canada consists of a dual system--"one for [the] formal legitimized
high-status art world of mainly white Canadians, and the second is a
marginal, folkloric, and low-status multicultural circle reserved for
immigrants and made up largely of visible minorities" (1994, 366).
The central theme of his critique is that "... the Canadian state,
through its role as a sponsor and patron of [the] arts and minority
cultures, creates the unequal infrastructural conditions which are
conducive in developing two types of arts and culture. In this sense,
dominant arts and subordinate minority cultures are at least partly
perpetuated by state intervention" (366-367).
ANALYSIS OF THE POSTULATIONS
The ten postulations highlighted in the previous section regarding
the fragmentary effects of multiculturalism and the literature devoted
to them have some notable features that are noteworthy for the purpose
of advancing both the analyses of and discourses on multiculturalism
public philosophy and public policy in Canada.
First, the postulations identified in this paper can be grouped,
albeit somewhat roughly, into the following four general themes:
* multiculturalism segregates the population in Canada
(postulations 1, 2, and 3)
* multiculturalism is problematical for the Canadian, Quebecois,
and Aboriginal cultures, identities, and nationalism projects
(postulations 3, 4, 5, and 6)
* multiculturalism perpetuates conflicts between and within groups
(postulations 7 and 8)
* multiculturalism hinders equity and equality in society and the
economy (postulations 9 and 10)
Second, generally the postulations are presented as propositions
that have been proved, rather than what they are--propositions that have
not been proved, but which postulators believe are self-evident. There
is a tendency for the postulators to comment on the fragmentary effects
of multiculturalism public philosophy and public policy more on the
basis of what they believe, rather than on the basis of facts produced
by any systematic research and analysis. Moreover, generally, the
postulators do not concede that producing facts either on the
fragmentary or unifying effects of multiculturalism is very difficult,
if not impossible, due to the challenges of establishing clear causal
relationships and producing reliable measurements. This situation is not
unique to multiculturalism public philosophy and public policy; most, if
not all, other public philosophies and public policies are confronted
with similar challenges in generating facts regarding causes and
effects. This is an important point that should not be lost on any of
the protagonists involved in debates regarding causes and effects either
in the multiculturalism sector or in any other policy sector.
Third, the postulations are generally based on an inadequate
distinction between multiculturalism public philosophy and
multiculturalism public policy. The postulators tend to comment on the
problems of multiculturalism without explicitly specifying either
whether it is the public philosophy or the public policy that is
problematical, or which particular facets of either of those is
problematical.
Fourth, the postulations are generally based on an inadequate
acknowledgement that either the public philosophy or the public policy
of multiculturalism and the fragmentation problems attributed to them
evolve over time. Instead, the postulators tend to discuss the
philosophy, policy, and problems as if they are all immutable phenomena.
This tendency may be explained, in part, by the fact that most
postulators focus on those matters as they are at the time they are
writing, and do not take a broader historical perspective in their
respective analyses and commentaries.
Fifth, the postulations are not very precise regarding the
magnitude of the fragmentation that is attributed to multiculturalism
public philosophy or public policy in the social, political, and
economic spheres. Instead, the discussion usually entails some inference
that either there is an incremental movement toward a critical
fragmentation threshold or that the threshold has already been reached
or surpassed.
Sixth, the postulations are based largely on Canada's national
multiculturalism public philosophy and public policy, and generally
devote almost no attention to provincial and municipal multiculturalism
philosophies and policies of varying scope and importance (Garcea 2006;
Poirier 2004). There tends to be a conflation of national, provincial
and even existing and emerging municipal multiculturalism philosophies
and policies, all of which are treated as a single undifferentiated whole. The only exception to this is the attention given to
Quebec's interculturalism public philosophy and public policy.
Seventh, the postulations are potentially problematical. The reason
for this is that, ironically perhaps, the postulations regarding the
fragmentary effects of multiculturalism philosophy and public policy
generate debates that are potentially fragmentary in their own right.
This is particularly true when the debates become highly rancorous and
confrontational (Burnet 1979). In some instances, such debates emerge
not only because of fundamental differences between the protagonists
regarding the value of multiculturalism philosophy or public policy, but
also because of the conceptual ambiguity that surrounds both
multiculturalism philosophy and public policy (Abu-Laban and Stasiulis
1992; Li 1999; Padolsky 2000; Stoffman 2002 and 2004). Evidence of such
debates is found in the views expressed by one analyst who suggests that
multiculturalism both at the societal and policy levels in Canada is an
illusion. At the societal level he asserts that, although Canada is
culturally diverse, it is not truly multicultural because there is a
dominant or hegemonic culture. Canada's multiculturalism policy is
not highly cosmopolitan and accepting of diversity because people who
exercise some of their cultural values or traditions are likely to fmd
themselves arrested for doing so (Stoffman 2002; Stoffman 2004). The
ambiguity surrounding multiculturalism is also articulated by another
analyst who notes that "...the disagreements over multiculturalism
policy do not necessarily represent divergent opinions on a universally
accepted version of multiculturalism since such a version does not
exist; rather, they often indicate different emphases attributed to
multiculturalism" (Li 1999, 148). He adds that "the
multiculturalism debate can never be resolved as long as the content and
meaning of multiculturalism are left ambiguous to suit the interest of
individuals and social groups in Canada" (ibid.). While there is
some merit to this suggestion, the notion that the phenomenon of
institutionalized ambivalence (Tuohy 1992) accounts for some of the
unity and harmony in the Canadian polity would suggest that it is the
search for clarity at the policy, statutory, and constitutional levels
that should be pursued judiciously by policy makers.
Eighth, the postulations are rooted in three major perspectives
regarding alternative policy options, namely the anti-multiculturalism
perspective, the laissez-faire multiculturalism perspective, and the
reformist multiculturalism perspective. These perspectives differ either
on the value of the multiculturalism public philosophy and public policy
or on the potentially fruitful directions for reform to them. They
provide alternative policy directions that may be placed on a continuum
consisting of radical departures from the current paradigm at one end
and minor adjustments at the other end.
The anti-multiculturalism perspective is articulated by analysts
who are opposed to multiculturalism both as a philosophy and as a public
policy (e.g., Porter 1965, Bibby 1990, Barry 2001). There are at least
two sub-categories of the anti-multiculturalism perspective--one that
advocates monoculturalism over multiculturalism (e.g., Bibby 1990;
Bissoondath 1994; Esses and Gardner 1996; Gwyn 1996; Granatstein 1998;
Kay 1998), and another that advocates interculturalism over
multiculturalism (e.g., Breton 1986; Hutcheon 1994; Gagnon 2000; Gagnon
and Iacovino 2002). The fundamental difference between the
monoculturalism perspective and the interculturalism perspective is
that, unlike the former, the latter is open to diversity management
initiatives driven by state or societal actors designed to recognize and
reconcile cultural diversity within the polity. In some instances,
however, it is difficult to distinguish between the monoculturalism and
interculturalism perspectives. This is particularly true when the latter
assumes a form that privileges a particular culture based on language,
social norms, religious norms, or nationhood within the context of
diversity management.
The laissez-faire multiculturalism perspective is articulated by
those who support multiculturalism as a philosophy, but oppose state
intervention in both the construction and propagation of
multiculturalism philosophy and public policy (e.g., Day 2000; Ogmundson
1992). Those who espouse this perspective believe that the state should
not engage either in articulating a vision of cultural co-existence or
in managing diversity. Instead, the state should leave it to societal
forces and dynamics to construct and reconstruct cultural identities.
The reform multiculturalism perspective is articulated by those who
support multiculturalism both as a public philosophy and as a public
policy, but are critical of some aspect(s) of the precise substantive
content of either the philosophy or the public policy (e.g., Li 1994; Li
2003; Cohen-Almagor 2001; Howard-Hassmann 1999; Sugurasiri 1999;
Mirchandani and Tastsoglou 2000). They believe that more could and
should be done to improve the multiculturalism public philosophy and/or
the multiculturalism public policy for the purpose of better managing
diversity to minimize or eliminate fragmentation.
POLICY DIRECTIONS IN LIGHT OF POSTULATIONS
The postulations regarding the fragmentary effects of
multiculturalism should not be dismissed as insignificant. The reason
for this is that many of them have considerable support among
intellectuals and members of the general public, and are likely to
continue to have in the near future. Regardless of their validity, they
tend to be quite significant in providing critiques of multiculturalism
public philosophy and public policy. For this reason policy makers
engaged in managing diversity should be cognizant of those postulations,
along with those related to other multiculturalism dialectics (Fleras
and Elliott 2002, I08), and they should be prepared to address them both
whenever there is any discussion of multiculturalism public philosophy
or public policy and also in undertaking any policy analysis and reform
initiatives in managing diversity.
The postulations should be assessed to determine which of them
point to real problems and which of them point to perceived problems
both in relation to the multiculturalism philosophy and the
multiculturalism policy. The aphorism that "perception is
reality" serves as a reminder not only that differentiating between
these two types of problems is by no means easy, but, more important,
that perceived problems may be as significant as, and possibly even more
significant than, real problems.
Furthermore, in identifying real and perceived problems, special
attention should be devoted both to the symbolic and the substantive
dimensions of multiculturalism philosophy and policy. The reason for
this is that both dimensions are important, especially given that, as
Breton (1986, 27) noted in his analysis of the relationship between
multiculturalism and nation-building, people have symbolic as well as
material interests. Thus, the symbolic dimensions of multiculturalism
philosophy and policy may be as important as, if not more important
than, the substantive dimensions.
After differentiating between real and perceived problems at the
substantive and symbolic levels, policy makers should assess the
relative tractability of the various problems associated with existing
multiculturalism philosophy and policy to determine, among other things,
the proper sequence in which to tackle them, the nature and scope of the
initiatives that will be required to deal with them, and, insofar as
possible, the positive and negative effects, if any, that those changes
might have. In identifying and implementing any such initiatives, policy
makers should consider very carefully the current and potential roles
and responsibilities of key actors in the governmental,
non-governmental, educational, research, and media sectors.
Regardless of precisely what they focus on and what they do when
dealing with various symbolic or substantive aspects of multiculturalism
philosophy and policy, policy makers should ensure that neither the
efficacy nor the morality of the Canadian management of diversity is
adversely affected. It may well be that greater efficacy and morality in
diversity management is to be found either in a modified or reformed
version of the current multicultural paradigm or hybridized
multiculturalism/interculturalism paradigm that has emerged at the
national level during the past two decades, or in a substantially
different paradigm. However, that is a matter that should be the
subjected to very careful analysis before any radical changes are made
to the status quo.
Given that Canada is a liberal democracy that ostensibly is
committed to respecting and protecting the rights of individuals and
minorities, it must operate within the parameters of the
multiculturalism and interculturalism paradigms because they embody the
values of that particular aspect of liberal democracy (Kay 1998, 33).
Thus, so long as Canada wishes to remain a liberal democracy, the
critical question is not whether Canada should or should not operate
according to either the multiculturalism or the interculturalism
paradigm. Instead, the critical question is according to what particular
configuration of either of these two paradigms, or some hybrid version
of the two, it should operate.
In answering that question, the differences between the
multiculturalism and interculturalism paradigms should not be
overestimated. The two public philosophies, which invariably are not
conceptualized in a very precise manner, have much more in common than
is generally acknowledged. The explicit or implied distinction commonly
made between multiculturalism and interculturalism to the effect that
the former is somehow more segregationist and the latter is more
integrationist is highly questionable. This is especially true in the
Canadian context where the general consensus is that an integrationist
modus vivendi is more desirable than a segregationist modus vivendi. The
prevailing Canadian political culture is much more favourably
predisposed to building bridges than to building walls. The most
important policy task is to ensure that this virtuous aspect of Canadian
political culture is perpetuated.
ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS
The author would like to express his appreciation to Dr. Anna
Kirova and Dr. Lloyd Wong, as well as to his research assistants for
their respective contribution in the preparation of this article. This
article was produced with research assistance funded by Canadian
Heritage and the Prairie Metropolis Centre.
WORKS CITED
Abu-Laban, Yasmeen. 1994. The Politics of Race and Ethnicity:
Multiculturalism as a Contested Arena. In Canadian Politics: An
Introduction to the Discipline, ed. James P. Bickerton and Main G.
Gagnon, 242-263. Scarborough: Broadview Press.
Abu-Laban, Yasmeen, and Daiva Stasiulis. 1992. Ethnic Pluralism
under Siege: Popular and Partisan Opposition to Multiculturalism.
Canadian Public Policy 18.4: 365-387.
Bannerji, Himani. 2000. The Dark Side of the Nation: Essays on
Multiculturalism, Nationalism, and Gender. Toronto: Canadian Scholars
Press.
Barry, Brian. 2001. Culture and Equality: An Egalitarian Critique
of Multiculturalism. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
Bibby, Reginald W. 1990. Mosaic Madness: The Poverty and Potential
of Life in Canada. Toronto: Stoddart.
Bissoondath, Neil. 1994. Selling Illusions: The Cult of
Multiculturalism in Canada. Toronto: Penguin Books.
Breton, E. 2000. Canadian Federalism, Multiculturalism, and the
Twenty-First Century. International Review of Canadian Studies 21:
155-175.
Breton, R. 1986. Multiculturalism and Canadian Nation-Building. In
The Politics of Gender, Ethnicity, and Language in Canada, ed. A. Cairns and C. Williams, 27-66. Toronto: University of Toronto Press.
Brimelow, Peter. 1988. The Patriot Game: Canada and the Canadian
Question Revisited. Stanford: Hoover Institution Press.
Brotz, Howard. 1980. Multiculturalism Policy in Canada: A Muddle.
Canadian Public Policy 6.1: 41-46.
Burnet, Jean. 1979. Myths and Multiculturalism. Canadian Journal of
Education 4.4: 43-58.
Cohen-Almagor, R. 2001. Liberalism and the Limits of
Multiculturalism. Journal of Canadian Studies 36.1: 80-93.
Day, Richard J. F. 2000. Multiculturalism and the History of
Canadian Diversity. Toronto: University of Toronto Press.
Esses, V. M., and R. C. Gardner. 1996. Multiculturalism in Canada:
Context and Current Status. Canadian Journal of Behavioural Science 28.3: 145-152.
Field, Dick. 2003. Multiculturalism Undermines Values Held by
Canadians. In A Country Nourished on Self-Doubt: Documents in
Post-Confederation Canadian History, 2nd ed., Thomas Thorner and Thor
Frohn-Nielsen, 397. Peterborough: Broadview Press.
Fleras, Augie, and Jean Leonard Elliott. 2002. Engaging Diversity:
Malticulturalism in Canada. Scarborough: Nelson.
Gagnon, Alain-G. 2000. Unity and Diversity in Canada--Under Trudeau
and Chretien. In Democracy and Cultural Diversity, ed. Dennis Austin and
Michael O'Neill, 12-26. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Gagnon, A-G., and R. Iacovino. 2002. Framing Citizenship Status in
an Age of Polyethnicity: Quebec's Model of Interculturalism. In
Canada: The State of the Federation 2001, Canadian Political Cultures in
Transition, ed. H. Telford and H. Lazar, 313-342. Montreal:
McGill-Queen's University Press.
Gairdner, William. 1990. The Trouble with Canada: A Citizen Speaks
Out. Toronto: Stoddart.
Garcea, Joseph. 2006. Provincial Multiculturalism Policies in
Canada, 1974-2004: A Content Analysis. Canadian Ethnic Studies 38.3:
1-20.
Granatstein, J. L. 1998. Who Killed Canadian History? Toronto:
Harper Collins.
Gregg, A. 2006. Identity Crisis: Is Canadian Multiculturalism
Dangerously Outdated? The Walrus 3.2: 38-47.
Gwyn, Richard. 1996. Nationalism without Walls: The Unbearable
Lightness of Being Canadian. Toronto: McClelland and Stewart.
Howard-Hassman, Rhoda E. 1999. "Canadian" as an Ethnic
Category: Implications for Multiculturalism and National Unity. Canadian
Public Policy 25.4: 523-537.
Hutcheon, Pat D. 1994. Is There a Dark Side to Multiculturalism?
Humanist in Canada, summer: 26-29.
James, C. E. 1996. Race, Culture, and Identity. In Perspectives on
Racism and Human Services Sector: A Case of Change, ed. C. E. James,
15-55. Toronto: University of Toronto Press.
James, C. E., and A. Shadd, eds. 2001. Talking about Identity:
Encounters in Race, Ethnicity, and Language. Toronto: Between the Lines.
Kay, Jonathan. 1998. Explaining the Modern Backlash against
Multiculturalism. Policy Options 19: 30-34.
Kallen, E. 1982. Multiculturalism, Ideology, Policy, and Reality.
Journal of Canadian Studies 17.1:51-63.
Kymlicka, Will. 1998. Finding Our Way: Rethinking Ethnocultural
Relations in Canada. Toronto: Oxford University Press.
Kruger, E., M. Mulder, and B. Korenic. 2004. Canada after 11
September: Security Measures and "Preferred" Immigrants.
Mediterranean Quarterly 15.4: 72-87.
Li, Peter S. 2003. Deconstructing Canada's Discourse of
Immigrant Integration. Journal of International Migration and
Immigration 4.3:315-333.
--. 1999. The Multiculturalism Debate. In Race and Ethnic Relations
in Canada, 2nd ed., ed. Peter S.
Li. Don Mills: Oxford University Press.
--. 1994. A World Apart: The Multicultural World of Visible
Minorities and the Art World of Canada. Canadian Review of Sociology and
Anthropology 31.4:365-391.
Manzer, Ronald. 1985. Public Policies and Political Development in
Canada. Toronto: University of Toronto Press.
Mazurek, Kas. 1992. Defusing a Radical Social Policy: The
Undermining of Multiculturalism. In Twenty Years of Multiculturalism:
Successes and Failures, ed. Stella Hryniuk, 17-28. Winnipeg: St.
John's College Press.
McRoberts, Kenneth. 2003. Conceiving Diversity: Dualism,
Multiculturalism, and Multinationalism. In New Trends in Canadian
Federalism, 2nd ed., ed. Francois Rocher and Miriam Smith, 85-110.
Peterborough: Broadview Press.
--.1997. Misconceiving Canada: The Struggle for National Unity.
Toronto: Oxford University Press.
Mirchandani, Kiran, and Tastsoglou, Evangelia. 2000. Towards a
Diversity Beyond Tolerance. Studies in Political Economy 61: 49-78.
Moodley, Kogila. 1983. Canadian Multiculturalism as Ideology.
Ethnic and Racial Studies 6.3: 320-332.
Ogmundson, Richard. 1992. On the Right to be Canadian. In Twenty
Years of Multiculturalism: Successes and Failures, ed. Stella Hryniuk,
45-58. Winnipeg: St. John's College Press.
Padolsky, Evan. 2000. Multiculturalism at the Millennium. In
Journal of Canadian Studies 35.4: 138-260.
Paquet, Gilles. 1988. Multiculturalism as National Policy. Ottawa:
University of Ottawa.
Peter, Karl. 1981. The Myth of Multiculturalism and Other Political
Fables. In Ethnicity, Power, and Politics in Canada, ed. J. Dahlie and
T. Fernando, 56-67, Toronto: Methuen.
Poirier, Christian. 2004. Diversity Management in Canadian Cities:
The Dynamics and Issues of the Representation of Ethnic Interests. In
Rendez-Vous Immigration 2004, ed. Helene Destrempes and Joe Ruggeri,
541-554. Moncton: Policy Studies Centre and Atlantic Metropolis Centre.
Porter, John. 1965. The Vertical Mosaic: An Analysis of Social
Class and Power in Canada. Toronto: University of Toronto Press.
Roy, Patricia E. 1995. The Fifth Force: Multiculturalism and
Canadian Identity. Annals of the American Academy of Political and
Social Science 538.1: 199-209.
Saul, Roger. 2005. Multiculturalism: A Discourse of Contradictions.
In Possibilities and Limitations: Multicultural Policies and Programs in
Canada, ed. Carl James. Halifax: Fernwood.
Stoffman, Daniel. 2002. Who Gets In: What's Wrong with
Canada's Immigration Policy, and How to Fix it. Toronto:
Macfarlane, Walter, and Ross.
Stoffman, Daniel. 2004. The Illusion of Multiculturalism. In
Multiculturalism and Immigration in Canada: An Introductory Reader, ed.
Elspeth Cameron, 217-242. Toronto: Canadian Scholars' Press.
Sugunasiri, Suwanda. 1999. How to Kick Multiculturalism in Its
Teeth: Towards a Better Tomorrow with Critical Compassion. Toronto:
Village Publishing House.
Tully, James. 1995. Strange Multiplicity: Constitutionalism in an
Age of Diversity. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Tuohy, Carolyn. 1992. Policy and Politics in Canada:
Institutionalized Ambivalence. Philadelphia: Temple University Press.
Wilson, V. Seymour. 1993. The Tapestry Vision of Canadian
Multiculturalism. Canadian Journal of Political Science 26.4: 645-669.
NOTES
(1.) The concept of "multiculturalism public philosophy"
is influenced by Manzer's (1985, 13) conceptualization of public
philosophy.
(2.) What is referred to as "multicultural public
philosophy" in this article is generally referred to as ideology
(Moodley 1983), and what is referred to as "multiculturalism public
policy" in this article is commonly referred to as official
multicultural policy.
(3.) For the intents and purposes of this article, a postulate is a
proposition that is not proved or demonstrated but considered to be
self-evident, and a postulator is someone who articulates such a
proposition as the basis of an argument.
JOSEPH GARCEA is an associate professor in the department of
Political Studies at the University of Saskatchewan. His research and
publications focus on immigration, citizenship, diversity management,
and multilevel governance.