In the name of freedom comes a totalizing war-machine.
Warburg, James Paul
Photographs of dead children regularly appear in the world press.
The killing of Anas bin Nazir, shot in the back by the Indonesian
military as he ran through a rice paddy in Aceh, is a recent example (23
May 2003). However, there is a one syndicated photograph that I cannot
get out of my mind. Taken in 2001 after an exchange of gunfire at a
checkpoint near Jerusalem, the photo stands out as carrying something
beyond the usual image of simple tragic death. It is poised at a moment
of contradictory truth. It depicts a Palestinian youth lying prone and
half-naked in the middle of a dusty street. A dog-sized
robot--camera-eyed and remote-controlled--checks to see whether or not
the boy terrorist is dead or still dangerous. To one side of the
photograph a woman carrying a shopping bag begins to cross the street.
The human moment is frozen at the point of a technical question. The
woman, and the body politic of an imposed nation, waits as the
necroscopic machine checks on a technicality: 'Is the potential
risk neutralized, or does it still present a threat?'
Certainly this act of technological mediation ameliorates risk for
the unseen soldiers. However, at the same time it also dehumanizes the
threat and safely objectifies the 'enemy'. No one mourns the
dead person--not even the bystander. There is no rite of passage to mark
the passing of life from his body. The emotional power of the photograph
works off that very contradictory abstraction, contrasting the
post-human intervention with the banal humanity of an old woman engaged
in one of the necessary transactions of everyday life. It just so
happens that she wants to cross a street where someone has been killed.
The photograph thus subjectively counterposes instrumental mediation,
human mortality and quotidian necessity, even as it carries this
condensed moment of tragedy to us, the newspaper readers thousands of
kilometres away--mediated tragedy, breakfast toast and momentary effect.
To the extent that the photograph still works emotionally, we do not
live in a post-human world. Nevertheless, I want to argue that the lines
between the human and the means of technical mediation are being
blurred. Every time that instruments of the abstract war-machine are
used--even if ostensibly to protect us--or every time we glance at yet
another image of violence and the emotional effect is diminished by even
a shade, we are allowing our world to be overlaid by a strengthening
level of the post-human.
Just as the image invokes a tension between the technologized
post-human and the mortal human, this article works across the same
field of concern. It addresses, in particular, the tension between the
rationalized deployment of technologies of death and the putative
motivation of their use to project the 'humanitarian' values
of liberty and security. I will argue three main points. First, I
suggest that the hope of 'freedom from fear', defined in its
broadest sense, has been drawn into a tragic association with a new kind
of war-machine. (1) Second, I suggest that the techniques and
technologies of the war-machine are built upon a generalizing practice
of increasingly abstract engagement, both physically, in terms of the
nature of the delivery of force, and emotionally, in terms of how we
relate to those against whom the force is being directed. The widening
war on terrorism threatens to carry us towards a condition where we are
dangerously abstracted from those defined as
'Other'--terrorists, warlords, mullahs, and children
overboard. This process of abstracting the Other has long been with us
ideologically, but it has become qualitatively more dangerous as the
processes of technical mediation have compounded the possibilities of
controlling, killing and knowing from a distance. This is further
compounded by the way in which we vacillate between active paranoid fear
of the Other and passive acceptance of the machine that promises to
moderate that fear.
In the third main thrust of the discussion I suggest that in the
context of the War on Terror the abstract war-machine is being developed
with the intention of projecting a totalizing effect. While total
control is by definition impossible, and the unwieldy machines of
'totalizing effect' have a tendency to generate chaos rather
than calm, the resources of the war-machine are being generalized across
both the international and the domestic spheres with the goal of total
control. This is the other side of the promise to win the War on Terror.
The Multiplier Effect of Terror and the Face of the
'Other'
We now fear potentially threatening strangers in ways that lead us
to consent compliantly to the deployment of a permanent war-machine
across an undefined theatre of war. We now countenance technologies of
violence that kill from high in the sky, and special forces that operate
secretly across the ground, forces from above and below especially
trained to operate in those undefined zones where no war has been
declared and civilians and social infrastructure are targeted as often
as are combatants. Although this process has historical roots in the
twentieth century going back to Dresden, Hiroshima and Nagasaki, under
the cover of this War on Terror a new stage of 'humanitarian'
state terror has been extended, with a devastating multiplier effect.
How has this consent taken hold? Alongside the image of the necrosopic
robotic, let me present another image, an image that we are supposed to
recognize as dehumanized evil: the pudgy face of the Serbian politician,
Slobodan Milosevic. Along with Saddam Hussein and Osama bin Laden, he is
presented as one of the reasons that the new totalizing military machine
is necessary.
I recently sat in the International Criminal Tribunal in The Hague
and watched the section of the trial of Slobodan Milosevic pertaining to
a little village in Kosovo called Racak. (2) In that village a massacre
of forty-five persons occurred, and, as I will discuss later, part of
its importance lies in the fact that NATO seized upon the massacre as a
turning point in its decision to bomb Serbia and Kosovo. (3)
Slobodan Milosevic sits to one side of the Court Room No. 1, acting
as his own defence. He sits alone, except for a surprisingly alert armed
guard, changed at regular intervals. The courtroom is small, divided in
half by bullet-proof glass, with the public gallery on one side and the
proceedings occurring on the other. What struck me about the trial were
some strange cross-overs with the situation that Hannah Arendt described
in the trial of the convicted Nazi war criminal Otto Adolf Eichmann.
Eichmann's trial was held in Jerusalem in April 1961. (It
incidentally takes us back to the city where our discussion started, in
which the Israeli government and its soldiers have now become oppressors
in their ill-fated attempt to totalize freedom from fear.) Back in the
postwar years, Jews were trying to come to grips with the horror of
their own oppression by the most brutally efficient totalitarian regime
the world has seen.
Otto Adolf Eichmann was rightly found guilty of crimes against
humanity, but not for the right reasons. (4) He was in charge of
efficiently transporting people across the countryside--mostly Jews and
Gypsies. The only indication of an order to kill that the prosecution
was able to produce in that trial was a scribbled note, written in 1941,
by a 'Jewish expert' in the German Foreign Office after a
telephone conversation. It says, 'Eichmann proposes shooting',
but it has little status as evidence. (By chilling coincidence, this
note was written in relation to a state-organized massacre in
German-occupied Serbia in the very year, and country, in which Slobodan
Milosevic was born.) Eichmann claimed that he 'never gave an order
to kill either a Jew or a non-Jew; I just did not do it', and he
probably didn't. He did, however, admit to 'aiding and
abetting' the commission of crimes through organizing the transport
of Jews to concentration camps, and it is on this basis that he should
have been indicted.
The problem is that because the victors were searching for a
personalized explanation of the systematic horror, the court was reduced
to a Star Chamber. If the question had been posed in terms of taking
responsibility for the effects of a war-machine--including the effective
use of its rail system--the Allies would also have logically had to
interrogate their decision to extend their machinery of war into
fire-bombing and dropping nuclear bombs on civilians. The evidence shows
that British and American policy makers effectively employed state
terror against civilians in Dresden, Hiroshima and Nagasaki, using their
mass deaths as a form of exemplary accountancy to show the military
power of the Allied forces to the Axis powers.
The circumstantial, testified evidence is similarly overwhelming
that during the period that Milosevic was President of the Federal
Republic of Yugoslavia, his forces were involved in widespread mass
killings. But it is even less clear-cut that he directly ordered the
attacks against civilians than was the case of Allied bombing during
World War II. (5) The tragedy is that given the nature of his trial the
process is certain to remain more a mediated spectacle of personality
politics than an elaboration of the complex truths of contemporary war.
Upholding the principle of individual culpability continues to be
important, but here, unfortunately, it is being tethered to the desire
of the winners to explain away the horror as the machinations of
criminality.
Milosevic protests that all he was doing was directing his
war-machine to counter terrorism in his own country. Like Eichmann, it
seems that he will rightly be found guilty of crimes against humanity,
but not for the right reasons. If we admit to ourselves that what
Milosevic is guilty of is letting loose a war-machine in an attempt to
totalize state security against a putative threat of terrorism, then
Henry Kissinger, Ariel Sharon, George Bush, Bill Clinton and George W.
Bush are similarly indictable. (6) And, on these grounds, so they should
be. In all these cases, crimes against humanity were perpetrated while
these leaders had both de jure and de facto responsibility for
questionable military operations. Let them face the words of one of the
wiser judges in the Eichmann trial:
these crimes were committed en masse, not only in regard to the
number of victims, but also in regard to the numbers of those who
perpetrated the crime, and the extent to which any one of the many
criminals was close to or remote from the actual killer of the
victim means nothing, as far as the measure of responsibility is
concerned. On the contrary, in general the degree of responsibility
increases as we draw further away from the man who uses the fatal
instrument with his own hands. (7)
This particular judgement relates to one side of my second
argument. However, the lines of the technocracy of command have been so
stretched that the perpetrators of ill-conceived 'humanitarian
intervention' can no longer even countenance the idea of being
brought to account, even for bad-faith decisions that lead to countless
deaths. The only war criminals on our side can be the occasional
(non-American) foot soldier caught in an act of unwarranted embodied
violence. Despite the number of civilians killed in the Second Iraqi
War, now conservatively estimated to be between 5000 and 7000 people,
the fact that the ostensible purpose of the war has proved to be
dubious--weapons of mass destruction have yet to be found--will not see
George W. Bush brought to trial.
The other side of that argument is that when we dehumanize the
perpetrators of obvious horror--from Milosevic and Eichmann to Saddam
Hussein and Osama bin Laden--we mask the all-toohuman possibility that
ordinary persons like George W. Bush are equally as capable as
psychopaths of presiding over campaigns of terror from a distance. In
demonizing the 'Other' we lose any capacity to understand why
all perpetrators of systematic violence, whether in good or bad faith,
might act as they do. In the case of Milosevic, when none of the NATO
policy makers felt compelled to think through the consequences of the
Serbian attachment to the heartland of Kosovo, they assumed wrongly that
a brief period of aerial bombardment would bring 'peace'. In
the case of the Palestinian martyrs, when strategists continue to
explain away suicide bombing as the result of extensive religious
brainwashing, they assume, again probably wrongly, that heavy and
unremitting military retaliation will bend the will of the 'arsenal
of believers'.
The Antimonies of Totalizing Control and the Post-human
I want now to link this discussion to the issue of totalizing
control. It is a process with contradictory outcomes. Even in the case
of totalitarian Germany it was always either a pretension, or an uneven
effect, rather than an actual possibility. Nevertheless, either way, the
current form of global totalization, I suggest, has Strangelovian
consequences that at one level are taking us towards a postmodern and
post-human condition. Michael Hardt and Antonio Negri call it
'Empire', a single power or logic of rule that manages
messiness and destroys fixed boundaries. They write: 'In contrast
to imperialism, Empire establishes no territorial centre of power and
does not rely on fixed boundaries or barriers. Empire manages hybrid
identities, flexible hierarchies and plural exchanges through modulating
networks of command'. (8) However, I find their metaphor of a
society of control presiding over a new plurality unconvincing. It
misses out both on the different structural levels of sovereignty and
the different formations that in one setting throw up, for example, the
traditionally conceived notion of martyring one's body for a sacred
cause, while engendering in another setting the postmodern confidence
that a National Missile Defence System will bring freedom from rogue
states.
While the contemporary projection of control continues to carry
with it modern techniques of efficiency and organization conceived
decades ago, it is now overlaid by various postmodern features:
totalizing organizational security (funding a massive war-machine so
that, supposedly, we can be free from fear of attack upon our bodies);
totalizing capital (advocating that the commodity be completely
unregulated so that we can be 'free' to fetishize our deepest
desires); and totalizing techo-science (granting scientists the
unfettered freedom to reconstitute nature so that we can dream of being
free of want and disease).
The first is most relevant to this article, and here we find an
apparent paradox. The only way potentially to enhance totalizing control
is to totalize the freedom of 'us, the good guys' and to
objectify the others as abstract strangers and a potential threat.
Ronald Reagan expressed it beautifully as a divine assignment to spread
the 'sacred fire of human liberty'. George W. Bush, speaking
in the context of images of falling statues of Saddam, proclaimed
'We have witnessed the arrival of a new era ... everywhere that
freedom stirs, let tyrants fear' (3 May 2003). It is an apparent
paradox because this particular concept of 'freedom' entails a
new tyranny, including developing the infrastructure to defend the free
movement and operation of some, and to strictly curtail the freedom of
others. Examples abound. The US Patriot Act of 2001 is a massive
document extending powers that were already more than adequate for the
purpose. Since September 11, there have been secret hearings and
detentions of 1200 people in the United States, mostly Muslims arrested
on immigration charges under the Act. Others have been detained without
recourse to legal representation in Guantanamo Bay, a US-controlled
section of another nation's territory. And, on 5 June 2002, we
heard the announcement of an intention to revive the long-dormant powers
of the 1952 immigration law which would see tens of thousands of
visitors from Islamic countries fingerprinted, potentially increasing to
5 million persons per year by 2005.
Just as it is counterproductive to dehumanize the perpetrators of
crimes against humanity, so too is developing techniques and
technologies of totalizing control. Every technology that has been
developed has become part of an escalation of the need for new
techniques of 'totalizing' control. The technologies either
fall into the 'wrong hands' or set up the conditions for a
counter-technology that renders them less totalizing, with the
subsequent rationalization that we need a new level of protection.
For example, after the invention of the atomic bomb, the politics
of the abstracting war-machine went through a number of overlapping
stages:
1. An atomic bomb named 'Little Boy' (9) was used
pre-emptively to free us from an evil war-maker, Japan, subsequently
spurring the Soviet Union to develop a comparable capacity.
2. The hydrogen bomb and an intercontinental ballistic missile
system was developed to free the West from the Soviet threat, leading to
the doctrine and untenable reality of Mutually Assured (totalizing)
Destruction, and thus making the technology at least potentially
unusable.
3. Nuclear weapons were further developed technologically, to make
limited battlefield use possible (leading to the fear of other states
using the weapons as they too acquired nuclear capacity), and to project
a totalizing missile defence system--Star Wars and Star Wars II.
4. With the new technological possibilities, we have been overcome
by images of terrorists carrying suitcase bombs, denoting 'dirty
bombs', or flying domestic aeroplanes into buildings, thus getting
underneath any potential missile shield by putting their own bodies on
the line. This has prompted the development of the most active and
engaged peace-time military machine that the world has ever seen.
Re-securing the Home of the Free
The failure of 'totalizing control' to ever attain static
or comfortable ascendancy gives us a way of explaining why the big sell
of the concept of 'freedom' is so important. Whether we are
talking about the polarity of 'freedom/fear',
'freedom/terror' or 'global free trade/national
closure', the concept of 'freedom' has become paramount.
In the United States, as the home of the free, all of those terms have
become linked. Writing in the days after September 11, one New York Times journalist talked epochally of prior times when normality,
security and freedom were found in the small rhythms of routine. Now,
being at home does not automatically bring freedom or security.
Although the wound is obviously deepest there, it is not the only
country that has been altered. But of course, America is not only a
place. America is also an idea. The knowledge of this secure
'elsewhere' was what kept freedom and hope alive for millions
around the globe for two centuries, so we are told. It was the force
that broke the stalemate in the first Great War, the place from
which the world dared to hope for peace after 1918. It was the
beacon toward which countless immigrants travelled, in order to
leave their somewhere behind. It was the rock upon which
Churchill summoned the will from his people's terrified hearts to
go on and win against the darkest forces that freedom had ever
encountered. It was the symbol that ultimately brought down the
Berlin Wall and faced terror in Tiananmen Square. (10)
In this account, America is freedom. Hence, for the sake of the
world, totalizing security has to be projected both outward, through
going to war, and inward, as 'homeland security'. This has
involved organizational co-ordination and breathless announcements (6
June 2002) of a new single permanent department to secure the American
homeland. The Secretary of Homeland Security is in the cabinet, and
co-ordinates with the FBI and CIA, but the most crucial task is to be
seen to be reestablishing the nexus between freedom and ultra-security.
Even the titles of bits of associated legislation exhibit intriguingly
careful language use: the title of the 'USA Patriot Act', for
example, acts as a form of cultural closure on the possibility of
criticizing the intended changes as curtailing freedoms. More than that,
the title of the Act, an acronym for Uniting and Strengthening America
by Providing Appropriate Tools Required to Intercept and Obstruct
Terrorism (USA PATRIOT), ties together the act of being American and the
act of going to War to Defend Freedom. Speeches for home consumption
continually posit a fight between willed freedom and weak fear, with
repetitive use of phrases such as 'weapons of mass
destruction', 'rogue states' and the 'need for
pre-emptive strikes'. The logic: pre-emptive intervention,
combating rogue states, makes the world safe from 'WMD'.
George W. Bush's State of the Union address in January 2003 is a
case in point:
Our war against terror is a contest of will in which perseverance is
power. In the ruins of two towers, at the western wall of the
Pentagon, on a field in Pennsylvania, this nation made a pledge,
and we renew that pledge tonight. Whatever the duration of this
struggle and whatever the difficulties, we will not permit the
triumph of violence in the affairs of men. Free people will set the
course of history ... Now, in this century, the ideology of power
and domination has appeared again and seeks to gain the ultimate
weapons of terror. Once again, this nation and all our friends are
all that stand between a world at peace and a world of chaos and
constant alarm. Once again we are called to defend the safety of
our people, and the hopes of all mankind ... Whatever action is
required, when action is necessary, I will defend the freedom and
security of the American people ... We exercise power without
conquest, and we sacrifice for the liberty of strangers. Americans
are free people, who know that freedom is the right of every person
and the future of every nation. The liberty we prize is not
America's gift to the world, it is God's gift to humanity. (30
January 2003) (11)
Even when projected externally and globally, much of the rhetoric
is for domestic consumption in the West. The 'Axis of Evil'
notion deliberately echoes Reagan's 'Evil Empire', and
both have their origins in the Second World War period. Similarly, the
concept of global action in the name of humanity has a history going
back to the middle of the twentieth century. For example, the use of
images of globalism has long been part of US institutions of war-making
or space exploration. The official icons of the US Department of
Defence, the Navy SEALS and the Joint Special Operations Command, the
Strategic Computing Program and DARPA as a whole, take the globe as
their symbol of territorial reach. The war on terrorism is predicated on
a rhetoric legitimizing attacks against the source of evil wherever it
might spring up. In George Bush's terms, 'We must be ready to
strike at a moment's notice in any dark corner of the world'
(West Point speech, 1 June 2002).
Overlaying that rhetoric is a newer claim about the legitimacy of
pre-emptive strikes to protect our way of life against totalizing evil.
Donald Rumsfeld, speaking at the NATO headquarters in Brussels (6 June
2002), opened up this convergence of the notions of the 'freedom to
act' and the necessity of taking the initiative to control a source
of risk. 'Absolute proof cannot be a precondition for action',
he said. He was supported by the British Defence Secretary who talked
about the possibility of using nuclear weapons against the threat of
chemical and biological attack, prescient, in view of the May 2003 vote
by US Congress lifting a ten-year ban on developing tactical-use nuclear
weapons, including the 'robust nuclear earth penetrator'.
Over the last century, pre-emption and retaliation became illegal
as rationales for action under the conventions of modern international
law. It became illegitimate to strike first in case something might
happen, or to respond to a single act of aggression by retaliating in
kind in order to send a message. That is, older notions of an 'eye
for an eye' were rejected. However, in these contradictory times
retaliation has made a come-back in reconstituted form--this time as a
pastiche of floating and ad hoc rationalizations. In the aftermath of
September 11, it was claimed that the attack was so massive that it
could be taken as, in effect, a declaration of continuous war thus
warranting continuous defence. (11) This was despite the fact that no
one declared such a war, no one even took responsibility for the act of
terror, and only circumstantial evidence was available to decide upon
whom the retaliation should be effected. Within no time the terrorists
had a name, they were all Islamic, and they were found in every primeval
corner of the globe.
Conclusion
War, or more technically, 'militarized peace', continues
to prevail in Iraq, Afghanistan and Israel-Palestine. In Kosovo they are
still rebuilding their devastated social infrastructure with limited
support and in North Korea new tensions are developing. In short, the
application of massive force has not brought about a positive peace
anywhere. Nevertheless, the headlines point to the United States
preparing for new zones of military engagement. The accompanying war of
words has been ratcheted up as the self-designated 'allies'
continue the cultural legitimation of further acts of state terror.
It is fitting that Australia's Foreign Affairs Minister,
Alexander Downer, gets the penultimate word. Attempting to find an
explanation for the extension of war to Iraq, Mr Downer likened the
situation to the choice the Allies had in the Second World War in
response to the totalitarian regime of Nazi Germany: appeasement of the
bad guys, or deployment of the good war-machine. The problem, as I have
been concerned to argue, is that world politics and the consequences of
military action are rarely that simple. Even the evidence from the tiny
Kosovan village of Racak produces more questions than answers. Racak,
the site of a massacre of forty-five people, was presented as a trigger
for the NATO intervention. As it turns out, of the massive list of
offences listed against Milosevic by the International Criminal
Tribunal, Racak provides the only indictable evidence of a massacre in
Kosovo prior to that fateful day, 24 March 1999, when far away some NATO
generals and politicians decided the only answer to the military
activities of the Federal Republic of Yugoslavia was a deluge of bombs.
As time goes on, it seems less and less likely that the advocates of
total security will deliver positive peace. The answer is much more
likely to come from politically engaged people, living in a diversity of
places--from Jerusalem, Belgrade and Kabul to New York and
Melbourne--working across all levels of the social from the local and
regional to the global. By contrast, hoping that the war-machine will
bring peace has its parallels half a century ago in those who hoped
that, on balance, the Third Reich would bring world stability.
(1.) The concept of the 'war-machine' is used here to
denote the institutionalization of the means of military violence and
control, organized in the contemporary period usually by a state. It is
thus used antithetically to G. Deleuze and F. Guattari's notion:
'The war machine is the invention of nomads (insofar as it is
exterior to the State apparatus and distinct from the military
institution)'. See their Nomadology: The War Machine, Semiotext(e),
New York, 1986, p. 56. The only resonance of their approach in this
article is my argument that the modern war-machine is being overlaid by
postmodern techniques of organization and extension of force that
emphasize the advantages of de-territorialization outside of its own
borders. The compound concept of the 'abstract war-machine' is
intended to emphasize this new layer of effecting power in a way that
aims to overcome the friction of distance and time.
(2.) With thanks to Monika Naslund, Victims and Witness Support
Section, International Criminal Tribunal for the Former Yugoslavia.
(3.) On 17 June 1999, the British Foreign Office Minister Geoff
Hoon, the man who also talked of the 'certainty' of Saddam
having weapons of mass destruction, was reported as claiming that 10 000
people had been killed in 100 massacres in Kosovo. The trial papers for
the International Criminal Tribunal for the Former Yugoslavia list Racak
as the only massacre site occurring before the NATO bombing began:
Indictments: Slobodan Milosevic, PIS, The Hague, 2001.
(4.) H. Arendt, 'Eichmann in Jerusalem', in Alexander
Laban Hinton (ed.), Genocide, Oxford, Blackwell Publishers, 2002.
(5.) Indictments: Slobodan Milosevic.
(6.) A dangerous juxtaposition, I know, but it is important to
make. At the same time, in making these large and general claims we need
to stay acutely aware of both subtle and profound differences. For
example, I have already juxtaposed the Nazi total solution for the Jews
and the Jewish attempt at totalizing control in Palestine. However, I do
not intend to suggest that Israel's so-called 'security
fence' and its use of tanks and helicopter gun-ships to effect
control in the Palestinian ghettos can be grouped in the category of
'genocidal' along the lines of the systematic holocaust in the
1940s that wrenched people out of parallel ghettos.
(7.) Cited in Arendt, p. 98.
(8.) M. Hardt and A. Negri, Empire, Cambridge Mass., Harvard
University Press, 2000, pp. xii-xiii.
(9.) This naming is the postmodern war-machine's equivalent of
the neo-traditional concept of the 'human bomb'. On the
latter, see Nasra Hassan's stunning feature article on the
subjectivity of the suicide bombers: 'Human Bombs', The Age,
20 January 2002.
(10.) A. Sullivan, 'This is What a Day Means', The New
York Times Magazine, 23 September 2001.
(11.) J. Steele, 'The Bush Doctrine Makes a Nonsense of the UN
Charter', Guardian, 7 June 2002.