Beyond a postnationalist imaginary: grounding an alternative ethic (1).
Warburg, James Paul
In an understandable disillusion with the limitations of the
national liberation movements, particularly as the movements harden into
advocating conventional nation-state politics, critics are beginning to
put their faith in the new possibilities of postnationalism. This form
of subjectivity can be defined as a discursive 'attachment' to
others who have been lifted out of the modern boundaries of national
identification. (2) In this definition, postnationalism is a
subjectivity abstracted from and therefore only residually beholden to
imagined past forms of national identification such as ethnicity, felt
common history or bounded territory. (3) It is the late-modern
subjectivity of the mobile person in a world of traversed spaces. Some
theorists go so far as to suggest that it is possible to discern the
beginnings of a 'postnational imaginary'. These postmodern
theorists find it in the messy configurations of modern migrant
consciousness, transnational religious revivals of tradition, and
movements of postmodern diasporic hybridity. It is treated as an
incipient development: both good and bad in the short term, but with
positive, almost utopian, possibilities in the long term as the
nation-state ceases to enthral and enrage. For example, Arjun Appadurai writes that 'These elements for those who wish to hasten the demise
of the nation-state, for all their contradictions, require both nurture
and critique. In this way, transnational social forms may generate not
only postnational yearnings, but also actually existing postnational
movements, organizations, and spaces'. (4)
For all the sympathy we may spontaneously have with such a view,
(5) this article argues as its core proposition that without a
thorough-going exploration of the principles of solidarity and
community, advocating postnationalism amounts to little more than a
postmodern passion for mobile openness on the one hand, or an
ideologically insensitive support for 'banal' official
nationalism and global capitalism on the other. (6) The second part of
that proposition is counterintuitive, but it refers to the way in which
nation-states at the centre of the global order, such as the United
States, increasingly present themselves as postnational. Even as they
maintain a modern defence of the national projection of globalizing
power, the leading proponents of global capitalism no longer proclaim
'my country, right or wrong'. Instead, they invoke variants on
the postnational language of 'my country as exemplary of the new
openness to global mobility'. In doing so they mask the iniquitous
nature of structural conditions that frame such words. Postcolonial
advocates of postnationalism fail to see that they walk in the shadow of
these quite differently motivated advocates of global mobility.
That is my core argument expressed most bluntly, but it should not
be taken to mean that I think postnationalism is damnable. What I will
be criticizing is the tendency to look uncritically to
postnationalism--much as some nineteenth-century philosophers looked to
nationalism--as the way out of the problems of an earlier social
formation. In this case it is the problems that we have created through
the excesses of modernity, but it does not mean that a postmodern
politics provides the answer. One such postmodern excess is the
increasingly intensified and contradictory use of modern rationalized
violence, projected in the name of either abstract peace or
'traditional' integrity. From above, it comes in the form of
NATO bombers over Iraq or Kosovo. From below it is clothed in the
language of re-traditionalization: including the modernist
millenarianism of Saddam Hussein and the violent nationalism of the UCK,
better known to English speakers by their acronym the KLA, the Kosovo
Liberation Army.
It is clear that we need to develop new institutionalized forms of
polity and community that go beyond the modern national state, but
designating the way of the future as 'postnationalism' does
little to achieve that purpose. Neither does emphasizing the virtues of
deterritorialized mobility. This article takes as its central task the
need for a critical exploration of the limits of postnationalism. It
concludes by arguing that we need to put back into the centre of
politics deliberations over the principles that frame how we are to live
with each other. Unless this is given priority, current debates over
postnationalism and cosmopolitanism, globalism and localism, are bound
to end up repeating, in late-modern or postmodern terms, the dead-end
modernist arguments over the relative merits of nationalism and
internationalism.
Liberation Movements and the Politics of Modern Nationalism
Nationalist-inspired movements have inspired the best and worst of
outcomes. At their best, national liberation movements have involved
sustained and glorious passions of solidarity and commitment. However,
without principles that go beyond 'liberation from
oppression', as worthy as that aim may be, these movements have all
too often involved desperate violence of the kind that rarely translates
into sustainable, ethically driven polity-communities. In many cases,
the best that we can hope for is the restoration of legitimate
authority. (7) Whether it be the Fretilin East Timorese struggling
against Indonesian imperialism, the KLA in Kosovo or the Irish
Republican Army, the prospects for current movements only look a little
brighter if you believe that instituting the procedures of liberal
democracy is a laudable end in itself.
Even considered more narrowly, there have been few exceptions to
the counterproductive retaliatory violence of liberatory nationalism.
Examples such as Gandhi's salt march soon got lost in the
prison-house of modern nationalism. The most recent positive instance is
the Zapatista movement, whose moment of express violence was confined to
a battle with the Mexican Army in early 1994. Relevant to our argument
that positive (and non-violent) forms of postnationalism do not
necessarily derive from deterritorialization and mobility, the uprising
in Chiapas was initiated on 1 January 1994, the first day of the North
American Free Trade Zone Agreement (NAFTA). The people of Chiapas were
fighting to stabilize their relationship to place against a national
government that had just signed a treaty to transnationalize their
borders in the context of the intensified mobility of global capitalism.
For all of the postmodern romanticism about the Zapatistas, the
underlying strength of the movement is not its connections across
cyberspace, but its attempt to bring together an on-the-ground
commitment to place and embodied ways of life with a web-based means of
communicating its politics to the outside world. (8)
In this sense, the counterposition to postnationalism is not to
argue for an uncritical political defence of territorial place or
integral community. One example of counterproductive attachment to
territorialized place will suffice, the Kosovo Liberation Army, a group
that for a time the western media lionized as freedom fighters. From the
moment that a group of masked men carrying Kalashnikovs first proclaimed
the need for an armed response to Slobodan Milosevic, the possibility of
the Rugova non-violent alternative was closed off. Their response may
have been understandable. The KLA proclamation came in the village of
Llaushe just before Christmas 1997 as 20,000 Albanians met at the
funeral of a school teacher who had been killed by Serb police. (9)
However, the form of the response counterproductively hardened the
actions of the ruling national government. Arjun Appadurai gets to the
heart of the matter when he says that:
This incapacity of many deterritorialized groups to think their way
out of the imaginary of the nation-state is itself the cause of much
global violence because many movements of emancipation and identity
are forced, in their struggles against existing nation-states, to
embrace the very imaginary they seek to escape. Postnational or
non-national movements are forced by the very logic of actually
existing nation-states to become antinational or antistate and thus
to inspire the very state power that forces them to respond in the
language of counternationalism. (10)
This is the second to last time in this article that I will agree
politically with Appadurai, even if his descriptions of the world are
brilliantly evocative. If we read the sentence that follows this
insightful passage, the limitations of his proposed alternative become
clear. 'This vicious circle', he says, 'can only be
escaped when a language is found to capture complex, nonterritorial,
postnational forms of allegiance.' (11) In my view, escaping the
vicious circle of reactionary re-embedding of liberatory hopes in the
proceduralism of the modern rationalizing state has very little to do
with finding a language with which to express postnational forms of
allegiance. It certainly need not fetishize mobility or the end of
strong attachments to place. For Appadurai, postnationalism involves a
kind of post-territorial sensibility of multiple belonging. What the
analysis misses out on are the structures and subjectivities of change
and the necessity to re-embed different levels of belonging. Polities
and communities alike are being swept up in a race to leave behind the
modern nation-state and to accommodate what has been described as the
processes of 'deterritorialization'. (12) If reactionary
violence can be the outcome of the radical loss of community, then
effectively advocating the end of sustained community will not lead us
to a post-violent world. The disturbing irony of this aporia of
understanding is that some postcolonial writers thus advocate a process
of liberation from a form of polity-community--the modern
nation-state--that is already being reconstituted by processes that are
bigger than both the nation-state and the transnational groupings that
appear to be going beyond it. One aspect of this is the contradiction
that in the context of postmodern pressures towards
'deterritorialization', modern politicians are reflexively and
instrumentally invoking tradition to consolidate both their personal
power and the sovereignty of the modern nation-state while that kind of
sovereignty is no longer the assumed basis of international politics
In the particular case of Kosovo, Milosevic needs to be understood
as a modern politician with an ambiguous relation to the southern lands.
On the one hand, he works in the shadow of the philosopher Clausewitz,
who treated war as politics by other means to consolidate control of
territory. In this case Milosevic was able to efficiently carry out the
'ethnic cleansing' in the space opened to him by the KLA on
the ground, and the NATO war-machine in the air. On the other hand, he
had come to believe in and understand the depth of attachment of
'his people' to the territory. This modernist approach,
self-consciously drawing upon tradition, is brought to our attention by
Noel Malcolm in his book, Kosovo. (13) Milosevic's impassioned
April 1987 speech, spurred on by the crowd at Kosovo Polje, marked a
turning point for a politician who previously had not shown any interest
in Kosovo. Two months later, in June 1987, Milosevic made a speech to
the Central Committee of the Serbia Communist Party warning of the
dangers of 'darkest nationalism'. (14) With this as
background, any critical commentator who knew anything about the region
could have foretold that strategic bombing by NATO planes would at best
'win' the war only by shattering the country. And this is what
happened. Deterritorializing Yugoslavia became as much a part of the
problem as it might be relevant to a solution. To state the almost
obvious, a positive politics depends upon how a territory is lived and
governed. For all the technological abstraction of time and space, there
is no escaping it: questions of territory will always be with us as long
as we live in embodied relations with others, however superficial.
The Misplaced Faith in Postnationalism and Postmodern
Cosmopolitanism
Whereas modern nationalism was, and continues to be, expressed at
the political-institutional level through social movements of
compatriots acting in concert to achieve a singular nation-state, one
form of postnationalism is expressed as the subjectivity of mobile
diasporas of individuals. If these individuals-in-mutual-exile seek
'communal' connection, it is not on the basis of an underlying
attachment to territorial foundations. It is as a loosely configured
imagined community that may or may not have continuing embodied ties.
(15) Avant-garde cosmopolitanism has gone through a parallel shift from
the modern to the postmodern. Whereas modern cosmopolitanism was
projected problematically as a universalistic and singular world
community, the advocates of postmodern cosmopolitanism acknowledge
rightly the diverse historical and spatial contexts which they say still
residually frame it. However, they go on to defend multiple attachments
or displaced attachments without any obvious exploration of what is a
good way of living. (16) In either of these moves--either to advocate
postnationalism or postmodern cosmopolitanism--past forms of solidarity
such as the modern nation tend to be reduced to cliches: for example, in
Appadurai's words, 'As the ideological alibi of the
territorial state, [the nation] is the last refuge of
totalitarianism'. (17) Emergent trends are presented as a fait
accompli: 'the nation-state has become obsolete'. (18) And
solidaristic attachment and relatively bounded and embodied
placement--both principles that I will be arguing for later in the
article--come to be described as part of the problem. Appadurai writes:
'As I oscillate between the detachment of a postcolonial,
diasporic, academic identity (taking advantage of the mood of exile and
the space of displacement) and the ugly realities of being racialized,
minoritized, and tribalized in my everyday encounters, theory encounters
practice'. (19) I may be reading this incorrectly, but it appears
to treat displacement and exile as a simple opportunity to detach (at
least for the privileged), rather than as a vexed dialectic of
abstracted insight and more concrete loss.
One can get a sense of the intellectual fear of boundedness,
closure and attributed attachment from Iris Marion Young's claim
that racism and ethnic chauvinism derive in part from the desire for
community. Appeals to community in settings of xenophobia, she says,
'can validate the impulses that reproduce racist and ethnically
chauvinist identification'. (20) Of course, in the narrow sense,
she is right. It helps to make sense of Radovan Karadzic's Bosnia,
Slobodan Milosevic's Serbia-Kosovo and the whole horror-house of
official national-ethnic violence going back into the nineteenth
century. Similarly, Julia Kristeva is half right when she describes the
cult of origins as 'a hate reaction'--defensive hatred:
'so they withdraw into a sullen, warm private world, unnameable and
biological, the impregnable "aloofness" of a weird primal
paradise--family, ethnicity, nation, race'. (21) It has some
limited application to the defensive ethnocentrisms of Pauline
Hanson's One Nation in Australia when she presents the tightly
bounded nation-state as a haven in a heartless world, and it has
considerable relevance to Jean-Marie Le Pen's National Front when
he talks of expelling all immigrants from France. However, it is only
part of the story, and it certainly does not mean that the ideals of
community and its various expressions--tribe, locale, nation,
world--should be dismissed forthwith in favour of cosmopolitan cities of
contiguous strangers. (22) Here I am not being critical of city life per
se, with its rich possiblities of overlapping and multicultural life
settings. I am railing against the one-sidedness of arguments such as
expressed by Iris Marion Young when she says 'politics must be
conceived as a relationship of strangers who do not understand each
other in a subjective and immmediate sense, relating across time and
space ...'. Her ideal becomes the metropolitan world of
Manhattan-type situation-comedies, Seinfeld and Friends: 'Our
political ideal is the unoppressive city ... City life is the
"being-together" of strangers. Strangers encounter one
another, either face to face or through the media, often remaining
strangers and yet acknowledging their contiguity in living and the
contributions each makes to the other'.
Bruce Robbins' introduction to Cosmopolitics reveals a
parallel discomfort with bounded community and place, arguing instead
for located cosmopolitanism characterized by 'multiple attachment
and attachment at a distance':
To embrace this style of residence on earth (Pablo Neruda's
phrase) means repudiating the romantic localism of a certain
portion of the left, which feels it must counter capitalist
globalization with a strongly rooted and exclusivist sort of
belonging ... The devastation covered over by the complacent
talk of globalization is of course very real. But precisely
because it is real, we cannot be content to set against it
only the childish reassurance of belonging to 'a' place. (23)
(emphasis added)
If attachment to place were actually being conceived as exclusivist by sections of the Left then there would be something to criticize, but
such examples are so rare or so irrelevant to core debates that it
suggests that something else is driving the critique. What Robbins does,
despite his sophistication about 'actually existing
cosmopolitanism', is engage in misplaced derision. He so
concentrates on the indefinite article 'a', 'a
place', that he firstly misses out of the actuality that
'place' is most often lived in practice as a layering of more
and less extended relations of interchange and more and less abstract
forms of association. It is how we tie those layers together that is the
crucial political-ontological question. Secondly, he turns place into an
empty form of spatial connection: 'We are connected to all sorts of
places, causally if not always consciously, including many that we have
never travelled to, that we have perhaps only seen on television
...'. (24) As he later implicitly acknowledges, 'place'
is not the same as specified geographical locale. (25)
It is not the romance of place per se that is deeply problematic,
but the uncritical appropriation of it. The writers of books such as
Rooted in the Land or People, Land and Community (26) are struggling to
counter, even minimally, their mainstream counterparts in the
'community relations' bureaux of Nescafe, Macdonald's,
Coca Cola and IBM. Transnational corporate advertising is now dominated
by the global village motif, whether it be Buddhist monks in mountain
settings using computers, or rural farmers in Tuscany taking flexible
delivery of commodified global education. Television series depicting
rural idylls--Ballykissangel (Ireland), Heartbeat (Yorkshire), Northern
Exposure (Alaska) or SeaChange (Australia)--are indicative of a longing
for simple stability that is thoroughly exploited by the global-local
style advertising campaigns of the world's largest corporations.
Their image campaigns link the global and the local by simultaneously
romanticizing and emptying out the meaning of place. In short, much more
than a few souls positing romantic alternatives to the metropolitan
polity, it is instrumental management of a continuing and heart-felt
desire for placement that has to be challenged, particularly when it is
orchestrated by modernist barbarians like Milosevic or postmodern ones
like Bill Clinton.
Criticisms of the Advocates of Postnationalism
There are many issues to take up, but there is only the space to
mention two.
i. Postnationalist advocates miss out on the social and ethical
ambiguity of national community by treating national attachment as
either simply a bad thing or begrudgingly accepting this form of
attachment as a necessary limitation that will wither away as it is
deconstructed by a maturing cosmopolitanism.
In a sense, the advocates of postnationalism repeat the mistake of
the theorists of nationalism when the latter make the common moral
distinction between ethnic nationalism (bad) and civic nationalism
(good). There is certainly an analytic distinction to be made here, but
not an ethical one. In some hands it is turned into a blinkered politics
extolling the virtues of the kind of nationalism the writer happens to
hold. For example, Liah Greenfeld reveals her blind belief in
Anglo-American versions of the ideology when she advocates
'individualistic-libertarian' nationalism (her term). By
contrast, she says, 'Collectivist ideologies are inherently
authoritarian'. (27) I would not bother to refer to this stupid
claim except that it is positively taken up by an articulate advocate of
postnationalism, Richard Kearney. (28) By contrast, writing years ago
Tom Nairn sagely drew our attention to the ambiguity in all
nationalisms: '... the substance of nationalism as such is always
morally, politically, humanly ambiguous. This is why moralizing
perspectives on the phenomenon always fail, whether they praise or
berate it'. (29)
In short, even the most positive forms of nationalism are
potentially problematic, but they are not essentially so. They are
potentially problematic in the same way that personal expressions of
embodied human interconnection, such as romantic love, have the
potential for tragic consequences. Most murders are committed by
significant others. Good and evil cannot so easily be separated. If this
is right, the follow-up question needs to be: Where do we go from here?
Presently, there exists an ethical hierarchy on a line from
particularism to universalism--from ethnic to civic nationalism and on
to postnationalism and cosmopolitanism. Should we conclude by dismissing
nationalism out of hand and putting postnationalism in its place? Or
should we instead focus our attention on principles for underpinning and
maintaining complex ethical-social relations? I am arguing for the
latter: the naming of the relationship is much less important than its
form.
ii. Postnational advocates do not adequately incorporate into their
positions an understanding of the paradox that postnationalism is now
also the refuge of the instrumental state as it also attempts to find
its place in a globalizing world.
It is salutary for the direct advocates of postnationalism such as
Arjun Appadurai, and less explicit postnationalists such as Anthony
Appiah (30) and Richard Rorty, (31) to remember that it is that very
nation-state that they present as a post-melting-pot, postnational
experiment, the United States of America, that has over the last decade
been involved in more systematic violence projected outside its borders
than any state since Hitler's Third Reich. In the war against Iraq,
filmed as a war without significant casualties, thousands of anonymous
soldiers were drowned in sand as NATO tanks with bulldozer shields
filled in Iraqi-held trenches. In the 1999 war against Serbia, the
aerial bombing, intended to limit the ethnic cleansing of Kosovo,
firstly, fuelled the Yugoslav militia's forced exodus of hundreds
of thousands of Albanian Kosovars, and secondly, stabilized the
situation around a reverse ethnic homogeneity. Twelve hundred civilians
were killed by the bombs, the very people supposedly being protected.
Although not intended as a totalising denunciation, these facts make a
mockery of Appadurai's celebration of the 'sheer cultural
vitality of this free-trade zone' called America. True, Appadurai
does call for the further pursuit of liberty and cultural difference
through legal protections, but the full force of his call to America
takes the form of going with the flow of postmodern global capitalism:
For the United States, to play a major role in the cultural
politics of a postnational world has very complex domestic
entailments ... It may mean a painful break from a
fundamentally Fordist, manufacture-centred conception of
the American economy, as we learn to be global information
brokers, service providers, style doctors. It may mean
embracing as part of our livelihood what we have so far
confined to the world of Broadway, Hollywood, and Disneyland:
the import of experiments, the production of fantasies, the
export of styles, the hammering out of pluralities. It may mean
distinguishing our attachment to America from our willingness to
die for the United States ... America may yet construct another
narrative of enduring existence, as narrative about the uses of
loyalty after the end of the nation-state. (32)
While lots of good things have come out of the United States, this
argument is bizarre. For too long US cultural exporters have been
constructing narratives for others. Three glaring problems with this
passage deserve attention. Firstly, as many other writers have argued,
it is misguided to think that the movement from Fordism to what David
Harvey calls 'flexible accumulation', (33) brings about a
brave new world of equality-in-difference. One has only to look at the
diaspora Chicano community of the eastern sea-board to see how immigrant
cultures can be super-exploited in the information age. Secondly,
although separating attachment to the United States (presumably good)
from willingness to die for it (supposedly bad) may be laudable,
depending upon what it means in practice, it no longer takes us very far
into developing a positive form of postnationalism. In the presentation
of the technologically sophisticated wars conducted by US-led NATO
forces over Iraq and Kosovo, much was made of the fact that very few of
'our boys' died. From a position of technological military
strength, willingness to kill from a distance has largely surpassed the
old-fashioned willingness to die for one's nation as the basis of
the call to arms.
The third point concerns embracing Hollywood and the style-doctors.
For a long time now, Hollywood has joined in the postmodern game of
presenting the United States as if it were already postnational and
therefore able to stand in for the world at moments of crisis.
Postnationalist films such as Independence Day (1996) and Armageddon
(1997) have largely replaced the Cold War nationalism which had Rocky
Bilboa wearing stars-and-stripes boxing shorts and stepping into the
ring to defeat Ivan Drago, the best that Soviet science could create.
(34) Hollywood's America now only fights wars over the thin red
line of national territory as reruns of old conflicts. With some notable
exceptions such as Wag the Dog (1997), the US war-machine is
uncritically portrayed as projected globally, rather than nationally,
self-serving in orientation. (35) However, if you read between the
lines, the set speeches in these films still assume that the United
States--as on the one hand postnational representative of a set of
universalistic values, and on the other as the exemplary open-textured
nation-state--sits at the helm of world politics. It is the kind of
postnationalism that makes 'humanitarian' interventions into
Iraq and Kosovo as easily thinkable as leaving to others the
peacekeeping mission in East Timor. In Three Kings (2000), the greed of
four US soldiers as they search for an Iraqi gold cache becomes the
ironical condition for final salvation. By the end of the film, true
American values surface, refugees are saved and life returns to post-war
normality. In Independence Day (1996), Bill Pullman, President of the
United States, speaks of the fourth of July as the rallying point for
all mankind:
Good morning. In less than an hour, aircraft from here will join
with others from around the world. And you will be launching the
largest aerial battle in the history of mankind. 'Mankind'--that
word should have new meaning for all of us. We can't be consumed
by petty differences any more. We will be united in our common
interest. Perhaps it's faith. Today is the fourth of July, and
you will once more fight for our freedom. Not from tyranny,
oppression or persecution, but from alienation. We're fighting
for our right to live, to exist. And should we win the day, the
fourth of July will no longer be known as an American holiday,
but as the day when the whole world declared in one voice: 'We
will not go quietly into the night, we will not vanish without
a fight, we are going to survive'. Today we celebrate our
independence day! (emphasis added).
It is striking how comfortably Hollywood translates fighting for
transnational peace back into the heritage of one nation: Pax Americana.
When we get to the last line, 'Today we celebrate our independence
day', the ambiguous designation 'our' has linked modern
nationalism and postmodern cosmopolitanism in a comfortable pastiche that challenges nothing. Hollywood even makes it sound as if it is hard
work. In The American President, the President of the United States,
Michael Douglas, talks about the need to acknowledge the struggle:
America isn't easy. America is advanced citizenship. You've got to
want it bad, 'cause it's going to put up a fight. It's going to say
'You want free speech? Let's see you acknowledge a man who makes
your blood boil, who's standing centre-stage and advocating at the
top of his lungs that which you would spend a life-time opposing
at the top of yours. You want to claim this land as the land of the
free? Then the symbol of your country cannot just be the flag. The
symbol has also to be one of its citizens exercising his right to
burn that flag in protest.
In one very particular way, the transnational nation is hard work.
(36) It is different work from that of the modern imperial nation, for
instance, nineteenth-century England. Rudyard Kipling's England
projected itself as engaged in the 'white man's burden'
to spread its civilization territorially, globally. The new global
nations (37) are not really interested in extending global
territoriality or painting the map the latest version of 'empire
red'. The denizens of such countries, including those of Tony
Blair's new Britian and Bill Clinton's United States, have too
many competing and contradictory issues to consider: modern ideas of
old-fashioned national interest; late-modern concerns about
universalistic human rights; and postmodern aversions to the
'ultimate sacrifice' such as dying for a cause, or watching
the body-bags return from a place of foreign military intervention. They
are caught up in postnational hopes which under pressure quickly slip
back into mis-remembered national ideals. Rather than get caught up in
these complexities, I want now to turn to exploring the beginnings of an
alternative.
Principles for an Alternative Approach to Solidarity and Community
This article opened with the argument that without a thoroughgoing exploration of the principles of solidarity and community,
postnationalism amounts to little more than a postmodern yearning for
openness on the one hand, and an ideological compatriot of globalism on
the other. The postmodernist critics do assume a set of articles of
provisional belief in their politics, but it is my argument here that
these 'implicit principles' are grotesquely one dimensional.
These implicit principles (it is not possible simply to call them
principles) can be summarized as based upon the aesthetic virtue of the
following interrelated ways of acting-in-the-world:
i. radicalized choosing This involves emphasizing the ethic of
autonomy, where the individual chooses and re-chooses the constituents
of life from amongst the pastiche of possibilities, past, present and
future. It is usually associated with a critique of the search for roots
or a place to belong. This is where postmodernism repeats, at a more
radical level, the politics of modern liberalism;
ii. boundary crossing This involves an emphasis on 'the
transnational [domestic] dimension of cultural translation--migration,
diaspora, displacement, relocation'. (38) It is as if being on the
margin is always better than stabilizing one's place, as if being
related to territory is always a root cause of conflict. It is not the
fault of the postmodernists that global capitalists extol the same
virtue of the borderless world, but it should give them pause for
reflection;
iii. fragmented subjectification This involves an emphasis on
identity-as-hybridity, and a particular process of hybridity at that
--hybridity-always-in-process;
iv. ambivalence of identity, authority, power, etc.;
v. difference and alterity (at its most radical it is
anti-communitarian);
vi. cosmopolitanism, or at least postnationalism/multiculturalism;
vii. deconstruction as a method of viewing the world around. This
is relevant to the themes of this essay. It involves deconstructing the
'totalisation' of national culture without putting anything in
its place that might become a common culture.
I do not want to dismiss these articles of provisional belief
entirely but rather to question them as one sided. The following
discussion only goes a couple of faltering steps beyond earlier
discussions in Arena Journal, (39) but it is intended nevertheless to
contribute to what might be called a politics of ontological socialism.
(40) Rather than arguing for nationalism or cosmopolitanism,
transnationalism or internationalism, postnationalism or postmodern
hybridity, it suggests that social relations should be based ethically
and practically on positive principles of inter-relationship, principles
which are positively contradictory. As principles-in-tension they can
only be worked out thoroughly in reflexive practice, rather than be left
exclusively in the hands of philosophers and critics to be passed down
for occasional trials. Nevertheless, there is a place for discussion in
the abstract. In this spirit, the principles will be presented here
schematically, with no great claims being made for the terms of the
schema, only for the indicative nature of the approach. The principles
and their lived meaning, it is suggested, need to be argued about,
negotiated, and worked through over various modes of practice, and over
varying levels of space-time extension and social integration.
Principles such as the importance of reciprocity in co-operation or an
emphasis upon equality are thus treated not as discrete liberal rights
but as interwoven into a tapestry of contingent rights founded in
relation to deeper 'ways of being'. (41)
As a way of beginning, we can list a series of couplets grouped
together under the nomination an ethics of care:
reciprocity-cooperation; autonomy-freedom; equality-empathy;
solidarity-authority; identity-difference. The phrase 'an ethics of
care' is perhaps too restrictive, but it gets closer to providing a
general description than any other I can think of among the terms in
current usage. The present discussion is intended to give more
structural specificity to the work done on an ethics of care by writers
from Carol Gilligan to Joan Tronto. (42) The couplets presented here,
alongside the others that could also be added to the list, put social
relational (as opposed to universalistic procedural) concepts together,
with the definitions of each concept drawing broadly from existing
traditions of ethics, from socialism to liberalism, and from
Confucianism to Christianity. These particular concepts are chosen
precisely because they are embedded in existing debates and derive from
social forms across human history. However, rather than being a pastiche
of all that has been, historically, humanly, they are chosen as
expressing most simply the ethical range of human inter-relations in
practice. The couplets are in positive tension with each other, thus
drawing upon, but attempting to go beyond, the way in which discrete
principles are usually set negatively against each other within
different discursive traditions. For example, as socialism and
liberalism have battled it out for the ascendant moral ground, the
intersection of the principles of equality and freedom has been left
under-explored. More than that, the concepts within the couplets are
intended to resonate against each other, mitigating the tendency to drag
such concepts back to the level of procedures without ongoing reflection
on their meaning. This is not to suggest that this manifold should not
be translated into procedures and even into laws, but it is to stop
accounting methods being used to measure the 'implementation'
of each principle as a disembodied singularity.
Beyond these couplets, it is suggested that social relations should
be conditionally founded upon, and therefore qualified by, our cultural
embeddedness within nature. (43) Two ideals stand out here: firstly,
treating nature as ecologically limited and therefore economically
limiting; and secondly, treating nature as ontologically foundational
and therefore potentially culturally limiting. Importantly, this last
principle has the effect of decentering the primacy of 'the
cultural' in the so-called culture/ nature divide, or 'the
intellect' in the so-called mind/body divide. For present purposes
it has the effect of questioning the easy mobility of one's social
arrangements as valorized by the postmodern postnationalists.
In setting up this approach to ethics, a number of complications
need to be noted. The first major complication, already hinted at, is
that each of these principles is in productive tension with each of the
others. The second complication, to be discussed in a moment, is that
each principle needs not only to be discussed in relation to other
principles, but across the range of human inter-relations, from embodied
relations of the face-to-face community through to thoroughly mediated
relations of abstracted sociality.
Beginning with the first point--namely, the importance of
maintaining a productive tension between principles--it is imperative,
for example, that the principle of equality go significantly deeper than
the liberal notion of equality of opportunity. For too long that notion
has been used as an excuse for increasing divisions of wealth around
assumptions of national interest and comparative advantage: the current
United Nations' Annual Human Development Report records that the
wealth of the three richest people in the world is greater than the
combined GNP of forty-eight of the world's poorest countries. It is
clear that in the contemporary world, projecting the social-democratic
ideal of distribution of wealth as it might be expressed at the level of
procedural rights, does not take us much beyond nationally framed
welfare liberalism. On the other hand, giving equality ontological depth
should not mean turning that principle into an ontological absolute.
Proclaiming equality for indigenous peoples in settings where they are
dominated by integrative modernisms, in countries as diverse as
Australia, the United States and Indonesia, should not, for example,
involve overriding the identity-difference principle. When
Australia's One Nation Party argues that Aboriginal peoples should
be treated no differently from other Australians, the thrust, in effect,
of that position is to argue against land rights. Those rights are based
upon a different cultural relationship to place, defensible at the level
of ontological foundations. It is by the identity-difference principle
at the level of an ethic of care, in conjunction with claims about
difference at the level of an ethic of ontological foundation, that we
can defend the possibility of different forms of living, and therefore
of layered forms of governance and law being constituted into all
postcolonial settings. For example, the Inuit have been granted
relatively autonomous governmental status in one of the Canadian
territories without this involving completely separate nation-statehood.
Terry Eagleton expresses this complication, with an elegant swipe at the
postmodern position on the way through:
Equality, then, is a deeply paradoxical notion. It means that
everyone must non-particularly have their particularity attended
to -- 'non-particularity' here meaning without privilege or
exception or exclusion ... A genuine concept of equality thus
deconstructs the notions of identity and non-identity, sameness
and difference, the individual and the universal, in contrast to
the more rigidly binary theorists of postmodernism who would line
up difference on one side of the ontological fence and abstract
universality on the other. (44)
Whereas the postnationalists tend to put ethical emphasis on
difference at the expense of identity, and on freedom above equality, in
the understanding of the present approach equality has to work across
the philosophical tensions between particularity and universality.
Moreover, the tensions have to be worked out in practice between people
across the various levels of association--local community, region,
nation, world--rather than through setting up a priori formulations
which tend to privilege the particularized local or the
global-universal. In advocating an alternative politics of layered
community, including national community, we need not aim to annul these
tensions, but instead aim to open them up to transparent and
self-reflexive regimes of negotiation. Instead of arguing, even as some
writers on the Left do, for the abstract market as a means of limiting
the obligatory implications of reciprocal community (45)--and thus
supposedly enhancing autonomy (46)--the principles of reciprocity and
autonomy (expressed superficially in liberal terms as contractual
obligation and liberty) have to be considered as pertaining to all
realms of social life, including the market, the media and the state. In
this the market, the media and the state are not treated as spheres of
autonomous activity. The nature of the abstract market and the abstract
state themselves need to be qualified fundamentally by practical and
more embodied expressions of reciprocity across the various levels of
extension, from the local to the global.
This brings us to the second complication: the need to consider how
principles are lived across various levels of abstraction.
'Reciprocity', as one of the principles-in-tension to be
negotiated in the broad canvas of human relations, readily lends itself
to the discussion. (47) However, without some sense of the levels of
abstraction across which reciprocity can be lived (and given the
contemporary pressures of globalization), we too easily find ourselves
taking the more comfortable path of institutionally abstracted forms of
reciprocity and solidarity. We allow institutionalized exchange
relations conducted by nation-states, corporations, aid agencies and the
like to mediate our relations to others. It thus reduces the layered
possibilities of public reciprocity to national tax redistribution
regimes, regional balance-of-trade agreements and global aid programs.
There is nothing wrong with these kinds of abstract reciprocity as such;
quite the opposite. Nevertheless, we do need to keep in mind the proviso
that the way in which abstract reciprocity is handled is often
instrumental, self-serving and oriented to the extension of
institutional power. This is not to dismiss it out of hand. Abstract and
universalizing reciprocity, especially if based upon a modified version
of the old marxist maxim, 'between each according to their
means', would be integral to a manifold of levels of reciprocity.
The problem comes when we rely exclusively on the institutions of the
nation-state or quasi-governmental instrumentalities for managing this
exchange.
The possibilities of abstract reciprocity range across the various
levels of time-space extension, from local exchanges between
acquaintances and strangers to global regimes of exchange, cooperation
and support. The overriding issue is that in contemporary market-driven
cultures, abstract rather than embodied reciprocity dominates the public
sphere, while more concrete, embodied and particularized forms of
reciprocity have retreated to the private realm of family and immediate
friends. In the context of communications, the problem is that
disembodied communication through the media and Internet are more likely
to be the source of sentimental solidarity with far-flung national
liberation movements than the much more demanding kinds of communication
entailed in a relationship of embodied reciprocity.
The contrast being made here is not simply between instances of
mediated and face-to-face communication, that is, communication as mere
interaction. We are talking about the nature of the relationship in
terms of how it is bound by deeper levels of integration. By contrast
with abstract reciprocity, embodied reciprocity or reciprocity at the
level of the face-to-face involves producing, exchanging and
communicating with, and for, known others. It is where the act of
co-operation is part of a long-term, relatively unmediated relationship
of mutuality and interdependence. For obvious reasons, embodied
reciprocity is more easily conducted the closer one gets to home, but in
theory (and practice) it is possible across the reaches of social
extension from the immediate locale to the other side of the globe. In
the case of the current struggle in East Timor, for example, it means
being more than part of a solidarity group which writes notes of support
or puts pressure on politicians. Here it would ideally entail working
with East Timorese people both in Australia and in East Timor across a
range of activities, political, cultural and economic.
Expressed more generally, enriching the depth and range of such
co-operative relations of reciprocity would, on the one hand, entail the
individuals who participate choosing to make the activities of the
interconnected activities of the interconnected face-to-face groups more
central to their rounds of everyday life (under the qualified and
qualifying principle of autonomy-freedom). On the other hand, it would
involve setting up specific solidaristic relations for the interchange
of goods and visitors with groups from other places, particular places
in which people can be supported in working projects of participatory
self-help. This kind of reciprocity, drawing lines of connection within
the region or across the globe, all too obviously involves confronting
the obscenity that the abstract state system does little to alleviate
the deaths by malnutrition and bad water of one-tenth of the children
born on this planet. By contrast, billions of dollars can too easily be
spent on a war over Kosovo or Iraq when one's principles are based
on the abstract notions of transnational sovereignty and
'humanitarian intervention'. The optimal aim would be to
develop lines of co-operation based upon ongoing negotiation,
reflexively conducted in awareness of the tensions between the
principles of reciprocity, equality, solidarity and autonomy. Rather
than facilitating autonomous hybrid individuals keeping in touch with
others in moments of superficial reciprocity and solidarity, the kind of
politics being advocated here embraces long-term solidarity with
particular others, conducted as a way of life.
Conclusion
The twentieth century, more than any before it, has been marked by
the horrors of mass wars over territory and cultural integrity. It is
understandable then that the postmodern response is to put the burden of
blame upon attempts to stabilize relations to place and community. It is
just as understandable that the avant-garde late-modernist response is
to call for new forms of universalism based on non-exclusionary
cosmopolitan citizenship. The issues remain extraordinarily difficult.
Arjun Appadurai modestly admits his own vagueness on what happens next
in a postnational world. He writes:
The ethical question that I am often faced with is, if the
nation-state disappears, what mechanism will assure the
protection of minorities, the minimal distribution of
democratic rights, and the reasonable growth of civil
society? My answer is that I do not know ... the road
from various transnational movements to sustainable
forms of transnational governance is hardly clear. (48)
This, he says, is a better answer than 'defining some
nation-states as healthier than others', (49) and on that I agree
with him. However, this is exactly what he ends up doing when he singles
out postnational United State as potentially offering the light, the
truth and the way: 'America may be alone ...'; 'there
could be a special place for America in the new, postnational
order'. (50) There must be another way. Advocating a discussion of
the principles of community--reciprocity, autonomy, equality,
solidarity, and ecology--and critically assessing how they are lived
across extensions of space from the local to the global, is intended to
take us beyond those responses, linking the particularities and
differences of place and identity to the generalities and universalities
of ethical debate.
(1.) With thanks to Alan Chun of the Academica Sinica, Taipei, for
commissioning the first version of this article and generously providing
the setting for its first public presentation; to the two respondents,
Chen I-Chung and Chen Kuang-Hsing, who at the Academica Sinica
conference critically discussed the paper at length; to James Goodman,
who provided the venue for its second round of criticism and helped take
it to a further stage of completion; and to Peter Christoff, Sigrid
Baringhorst, Simon Cooper and Geoff Sharp, who, after all of that, still
found plenty to challenge.
(2.) The concept 'lifted out' is used here to indicate
that transcending the modernist meaning of exclusive territorial
attachment can take forms other than just physically crossing national
borders. It means that the definition incorporates quite different forms
of postnationalism, including those that derive, on the one hand, from
postcolonial diaspora cultures and, on the other hand, from dominant
nation-state cultures as they redefine themselves in terms of
(postmodern) multiculturalism and the imperative to globalize.
(3.) The emphasis here on 'subjectification' should not
be taken to imply that postnationalism is constituted through other than
quite material processes.
(4.) A. Appadurai, Modernity at Large: Cultural Dimensions of
Globalization, Minneapolis, University of Minnesota Press, 1996, p. 177.
For a variety of different takes on the same question see: M. Albrow,
The Global Age: Society and State Beyond Modernity, Cambridge, Polity
Press, 1996; H. K. Bhabha, The Location of Culture, London, Routledge,
1994; F. Buell, National Culture and the New Global System, Baltimore,
Johns Hopkins University Press, 1994; P. Cochrane and D. Goodman,
'The Great Australian Journey: Cultural Logic and Nationalism in
the Postmodern Era', in T. Bennett, P. Buckridge, D. Carter and
Colin Mercer (eds), Celebrating the Nation: A Critical Study of
Australia's Bicentenary, St Leonards, Allen & Unwin, 1992; M.
Featherstone, Undoing Culture: Globalization, Postmodernism and
Identity, London, Sage, 1995; R. Kearney, Postnationalist Ireland:
Politics, Culture, Philosophy, London, Routledge, 1997.
(5.) The 'we' here refers to the 'intellectually
trained', a grouping that partially through being trained in the
art and technique of analytical dismemberment, becomes
'instinctively' ambivalent about the classically conceived
closures of modern national community. Notwithstanding examples to the
contrary, in the late twentieth century this ambivalence has often moved
to acute discomfort. We have to be careful that our framing mode of
enquiry does not lead us to treat ideologies of openness, freedom and
autonomy as naturally good things.
(6.) The term 'banal nationalism', coined by Michael
Billig (Banal Nationalism, London, Sage, 1995), or what I would call the
'new civic nationalism', describes a kind of nationalism that
cannot see itself as such. It is the flagged patriotism of those whose
who naturalize their attachments to constitution and country as civic
loyalty rather than as intense embodied passion.
(7.) I. W. Zartman, (ed.), Collapsed States: The Disintegration and
Restoration of Legitimate Authority, Boulder, Lynne Reinner, 1995.
(8.) See L. Reinke's chapter in James Goodman's
anthology, Pluto Press, forthcoming.
(9.) G. Kitney and D. Lague, 'The Seeds of War', Age, 17
April 1999.
(10.) Appadurai, p. 166.
(11.) Appadurai, p. 166.
(12.) G. Deleuze and F. Guattari, A Thousand Plateaus: Capitalism
and Schizophrenia, Minneapolis, University of Minnesota Press, 1987. The
term is in fact not very satisfactory but it points to processes of the
abstraction of space, part of the more general trend towards the
abstraction of categories of social being including space, time and
embodiment. This does not mean that the nation-state is about to
disappear: it means that its 'classical' modern variant is
under challenge.
(13.) N. Malcolm, Kosovo: A Short History, London, Macmillan, 1998.
(14.) T. Judah, 'Kosovo's Road to War', Survival,
vol. 41, no. 2, 1999, pp. 5-18.
(15.) Appadurai, Chapter 8 'Patriotism and Its Futures'.
(16.) B. Robbins ('Actually Existing Cosmopolitanism', in
P. Cheah and B. Robbins (eds), Cosmopolitics: Thinking and Feeling
Beyond the Nation, Minneapolis, University of Minnesota Press, 1998, p.
3) represents a critical cosmopolitanism that largely avoids the
valorization of mobility and detachment endemic in postmodern
cosmopolitanisms, but in criticizing its critics he occasionally falls
off the balancing beam. Cheah's introductory chapter 'The
Cosmopolitical--Today' in the same volume turns the critique back
on the postnationalists, convincingly arguing that cosmopolitanism need
not be postnational.
(17.) Appadurai, p. 159.
(18.) The quote comes from Appadurai (p. 169), but the sentiment
ranges widely from postmodernists to radical liberals. For examples of
the latter group, see from the Left, J.-M. Guehenno, The End of the
Nation-State, Minneapolis, University of Minnesota Press, 1995; and from
the Right, K. Ohmae, The End of the Nation State: The Rise of Regional
Economies, London, Harper Collins, 1996.
(19.) Appadurai, p. 170.
(20.) I. M. Young, 'The Ideal of Community and the Politics of
Difference', in L. J. Nicholson, (ed.), Feminism/Postmodernism, New
York, Routledge, 1990.
(21.) J. Kristeva, Nations without Nationalism, New York, Columbia
University Press, 1993, p. 3.
(22.) Young, pp. 317, 318.
(23.) Robbins, p. 3.
(24.) Robbins, p. 3.
(25.) And even then, as Robbins writes in another essay in
Cosmopolitics ('Comparative Cosmopolitanism', p. 253),
'Hidden away in the miniaturizing precision of "locality"
with its associations of presence and uniqueness, empirical
concreteness, complex experience, and accessible subjectivity, has been
the nostalgia for a collective subject-in-action that is no longer so
easy to localize'. It should be said that in many ways I like the
approach taken by Robbins. In pointing to the (minor) slips and slides
in his position I am more concerned about them as indicative of more
general problems beyond the text. On the philosophical complexities of
'place', see E. S. Casey, The Fate of Place: A Philosophical
History, Berkeley, University of California Press, 1998. On the levels
of theoretical abstraction from which one can examine a particular local
place, see E. Probyn, 'Travels in the Postmodern: Making Sense of
the Local', in Nicholson.
(26.) W. Vitek and W. Jackson (eds), Rooted in the Land: Essays on
Community and Place, New Haven, Yale University Press, 1996; H. Hannum
(ed.), People, Land, and Community, New Haven, Yale University Press,
1997.
(27.) L. Greenfeld, Nationalism: Five Roads to Modernity,
Cambridge, MA, Harvard University Press, 1992, p. 11.
(28.) Kearney, p. 23.
(29.) T. Nairn, The Break-Up of Britain: Crisis and
Neo-Nationalism, [1973], London, Verso, 2nd edn., 1981, pp. 348-9.
(30.) Appiah's argument for 'rooted cosmopolitanism'
is based on the defence of the liberal freedom to have elective
affinities. It is, in his words, a 'distinctively American
tradition'. He writes: 'Those of us who are American not by
birth but by election ... love this country precisely for that freedom
of self-invention ...' ('Cosmopolitan Patriots', in Cheah
and Robbins, p. 106).
(31.) For Rorty's postnationalist patriotism, see his
Achieving Our Country, Cambridge, Mass., Harvard University Press, 1998.
As Michael Billig notes: 'Rorty directly associates himself with
Dewey's vision of America: "I see America pretty much as
Whitman and Dewey did, as opening up a prospect of illimitable
democratic vistas" (Banal Nationalism, London, Sage, 1995, p. 170).
Billig continues: 'In such writings it is possible to identify a
tone suited to the new Pax Americana. The philosophy distances itself
from the rhetoric of the Cold War ... [At the same time, the] American
way--the way of non-ideological pragmatism--is recommended for all'
(p. 172).
(32.) Appadurai, pp. 175-6.
(33.) See D. Harvey, The Condition of Postmodernity: An Enquiry
into the Origins of Cultural Change, Oxford, Basil Blackwell, 1989; and
also M. Castells, The Information Age: Economy, Society and Culture,
Vol. 1, The Rise of the Network Society, Cambridge, Mass., Basil
Blackwell, 1996.
(34.) Rocky IV, 1985, a United Artists film, written and directed
by Sylvester Stallone.
(35.) Criticism is reserved for those unethical individuals
perverting the system who fail to live up to the abstract ideals of
life, liberty and the American way. Usually these individuals and their
cronies are exposed by the Harrison Ford or Denzel Washington hero.
(36.) The term 'postnational nation', may sound
oxymoronic, but it is explicable in terms of a levels argument that
treats modernism (which frames the experience of bounded national
community) and postmodernism (which frames the experience of
heterogeneous multicultural society) as contradictory formations
overlaying each other and coexisting in the same 'world time'.
(37.) The term 'global nation' comes from J.
Wiseman's book of the same name: Global Nation?, Cambridge,
Cambridge University Press, 1998.
(38.) Bhabha, p. 172.
(39.) The editors of Arena Journal, including Geoff Sharp, John
Hinkson and Simon Cooper, work with a framework of understanding, the
constitutive abstraction approach, which puts the emphasis on the lived
process of intersecting levels of abstraction. As one way of giving this
approach more specificity, I have attempted in the past to distinguish
different levels of epistemological abstraction (from empirical
generalization through integrational analysis to categorical analysis)
and different levels of ontological abstraction (from the face-to-face
to the disembodied). It is not necessarily a way of working through the
constitutive abstraction approach with which all the editors are
comfortable. What I am attempting to do here is connected to my previous
work, however it is not possible here to elaborate these cross-cutting
connections. I'd prefer just to get the approach up and running to
the extent that it becomes useful. Another version of this article that
makes some of these connections will be published simultaneously in an
anthology edited by James Goodman for Pluto Press.
(40.) Ontological socialism is defined as a form of social
inter-relations that negotiates its practical expressions--cultural,
political and economic--across the full range of what it has
historically meant to be human from the level of procedural rights to
the much more basic questions of co-existence as mortal embodied beings
born of both nature and culture.
(41.) Here I am thinking of Rorty's, Contingency, Irony and
Solidarity, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 1989. When Rorty says
that ideally a new ethics should 'culminate in our no longer being
able to see any use for the notion that finite, mortal, contingently
existing human beings might derive the meanings of their lives from
anything except other finite, mortal, contingently existing human
beings', my response is, maybe, but if we care to look at the
ontological meaning of finitude and mortality in human
inter-relationship (however historically contingent and variable this
has been in practice) we are already in the realms of a foundational
ethics that take us far deeper than liberal pragmatics.
(42.) J. C. Tronto, Moral Boundaries: A Political Argument for an
Ethic of Care, New York, Routledge, 1993. There are lots of departures
from such writings in the present article, signalled by using
'ethics' in the plural.
(43.) It is 'foundational' in the sense that our various
ethical houses cannot stand up in the long term without such a basis;
not in the sense that foundations determine more than a couple of
dimensions of the shape of the house let alone how it is made, or its
aesthetics. It is 'conditionally foundational' in the sense
that categorical imperatives are always cultural rather than based on
human nature as immutable essence. Related to Max Weber's
injunction that 'we must create our ideals from within our chests
in the very age of subjectivist culture', it suggests that ethics
must be reflexively negotiated rather than treated as being delivered
from on high as absolutist edict.
(44.) T. Eagleton, 'Five Types of Identity and
Difference' in D. Bennett (ed.), Multicultural States: Rethinking
Difference and Identity, London, Routledge, 1998, p. 50.
(45.) C. Offe and R. G. Heinze, Beyond Employment: Time, Work and
the Informal Economy, Cambridge, Polity Press, 1992.
(46.) It was Geoff Sharp ('Constitutive Abstraction and Social
Practice', Arena 70, 1985, pp. 48-82) who first drew critical
attention to the concept of the ideology of autonomy. Under the rubric of the 'ideology of autonomy', market relations in fact set up
unacknowledged structures of authority (power) which limit the de facto freedoms of people in ways that close-knit communities could not
sustain.
(47.) Within the Arena circle of writers it is Nonie Sharp who has
done most to elaborate the concept of reciprocity--mostly in relation to
tribal society. See her book The Stars of Tagai, Canberra, Aboriginal
Studies Press, 1993. This paragraph and part of the next are a rewriting
of an earlier article of mine: 'Reconstituting Work', Arena
Journal, no. 10, 1998, pp. 85-111.
(48.) Appadurai, pp. 19-20.
(49.) Appadurai, pp. 19-20.
(50.) Appadurai, pp. 173, 174.