On determinatives and the category-function distinction: a reply to Brett Reynolds.
Lenchuk, Iryna ; Ahmed, Amer
This article is a critical analysis of "Determiners, Feline
Marsupials, and the Category-Function Distinction: A Critique of ELT
Grammars" by Reynolds (2013). We examine the author's claims,
and demonstrate that they are not supported by theoretical or empirical
evidence.
The author makes the following claims:
1. The information that can be found in ESL textbooks,
dictionaries, and reference materials with regards to words such as the,
this, some, many, either, each is confusing. The confusion is due to the
fact that the abovementioned materials do not differentiate between the
concept of a syntactic category (i.e., determinatives) and that of a
syntactic function (i.e., specifier, head, modifier). Reynolds then
claims that, first, words such as my, your, his, her, our, their do not
belong to the category of determinatives; they are pronouns. Second, he
claims that words such as few, little, many are determinatives rather
than pronouns.
2. The author cautions that a failure to make a clear distinction
between a category and a function raises serious concerns about the core
values of ELT. He asks: "What does it matter that we in ELT might
call my a determinative and many a pronoun, or that we hew to frameworks
largely left behind by linguists?" (p. 12), and responds by saying,
"One simple answer is accuracy, academic integrity, and
professionalism" (p. 12).
Discussion
Conceptual Problems with the Author's Proposal
There is a conceptual problem with the author's categorization
of determinatives (p. 7). Three properties generally characterize the
determinative category (D): (a) D cannot combine with the or a or with
each other; (b) D can combine with a singular count noun to form a
grammatical noun phrase (NP); (c) D can occur as a head in the partitive
construction (i.e., HEAD + of + DEFINITE NP) (p. 7). Lexical items
qualify as determinatives if they have one, two, or all of the three
properties required (see Reynolds, 2013, Tables 1-2, pp. 8-9). (1) The
question immediately arises as to how to evaluate these properties. The
properties do not meet the standard rigid categorization adopted in
formal linguistics (see, e.g., Tallerman, 2011). (2) Reynolds does not
base his categorization of determinatives on any linguistic framework,
as he does not cite any references when providing these properties (see
p. 7). However, we can still draw some very close parallels between
Reynolds and others. For example, Huddleston & Pullum (2002, p.
539), in a section called "Criteria for determinatives,"
provide the following three properties of determinatives:
1. "Mutual exclusiveness with the articles." They add
that "[t]his criterion admits the following items as
determinatives: [31] another, much, we [as a determinative], any,
neither, what [as interrogative/relative] , each, no, whatever, either,
some, which, enough, that, whichever, every, this, you [as a
determinative]."
Huddleston and Pullum (2002, p. 539) then add the following:
"Also admitted by this criterion are the complex forms a few and a
little." Interestingly, Reynolds (2013, Table 1, p. 8) has the
following words: a, each, neither, this/ these, a few, either, no,
we/us, a little, enough, some, what(ever), another, every, that/ those,
which(ever), any, much, the, you. Reynolds also argues that these words
pass his first property of determinatives, namely, their inability to
combine with a or the or with each other except in coordination (p. 7).
2. "Admissibility of count singular NPs" (Huddleston
& Pullum, 2002, p. 539). Interestingly, Reynolds (2013) also has as
his second property of determinatives the fact that they "can
combine with a singular count noun to form a grammatical noun
phrase" (p. 7).
3. "The partitive construction." Here Huddleston and
Pullum (2002, p. 539) state the following: "Words not included in
[31] [i.e., the words in (a) above] that are admitted to the
determinative category on the basis of this criterion are: [33] all,
several, both, sufficient, certain, various, few, little, many, cardinal
numerals." Reynolds (2013, p. 7) also has as his third property of
determinatives the following: "They can occur as heads in the
partitive construction (i.e., in NPs with the form: HEAD + of + DEFINITE
NP)." Reynolds then adds the following: "Words admitted into
the determinative category by this test but not already covered by the
first two tests are shown in Table 2" (p. 8). Table 2 in Reynolds
(p. 9) has the following words: all, many, two, three, four, etc. (the
cardinal numerals), both, more/most, certain, several, few, sufficient,
little, various.
The very close parallels above serve to show that Reynolds'
three properties of determinatives as a syntactic category, together
with the words that meet those properties, look strikingly similar to
those of Huddleston and Pullum (2002, p. 539). At any rate, because
Reynolds does not ground his properties of determinatives as a category
in any linguistic framework, we assume that these are his own. Given
that no linguistic framework of categorization is offered in Reynolds
(2013), we can do nothing but speculate. For example, one way of
thinking about these properties is in terms of the family resemblances
approach of Ludwig Wittgenstein to word meanings (see, e.g., Kearns,
2000, pp. 13-15). However, as Reynolds does not mention this approach,
we assume that this is not the approach he follows. Another way of
thinking about these properties is in terms of the dynamic construal
approach used to assign meanings to words in cognitive linguistics
(Croft & Cruse, 2004). However, the author does not mention that
approach either. In fact, the properties above do not fit into the
dynamic construal approach, in which there should be no specific
distinction drawn between any two categories out of context. Applied to
the present discussion, this would mean that lexical items can be
pronouns in some contexts, but determinatives in others (see Cruse,
2004, pp. 262-272, on conceptual categories). However, this would be the
same position held by ELT textbook writers and applied linguists, one
that the author dedicates his article to argue against. Having said the
above, we believe that the author's way of categorization is
problematic from the perspective of the standard rigid categorization
applied in formal linguistics, where each property is necessary and all
properties jointly define a category (see, e.g., Tallerman, 2011, p.
36).
Empirical Problems with the Author's Proposal
Are the words included in the my set pronouns by the author's
criteria?
Reynolds (2013, pp. 9-11) argues that words belonging to the my set
are pronouns, not determinatives. In this section, we apply the
linguistic tests offered in Reynolds (2013) to show that the words that
belong to the my set are determinatives rather than pronouns.
In the analysis of determinatives as a syntactic category and their
function as a specifier, the author uses the following tests summarized
in Table 1.
The data presented below demonstrate the tests applied to the my
set.
Test 1
(1) a. *The my/your/his/her car is expensive.
b. *A my car is fast.
c. *My this car has been sold.
The ungrammaticality of examples (1a-c) shows that my cannot
combine with a and the, or with other members of the determinatives
category with the specifier function.
Test 2
(2) My car, your dress, his umbrella, her cake, our paper, their
child
The grammatically of the NPs in (2) shows that possessives can
combine with a singular count noun to form a grammatical NP.
Test 3
(3) *[My] of [the bags] are old.
As shown in (3), my cannot be used in a partitive construction, and
therefore cannot pass the partitive test.
The above shows that the words in the my set meet two of the three
properties of determinatives as a syntactic category (i.e., Property 1
and Property 2); therefore, they are determinatives.
Now consider the specifier function tests:
Test 1
(4) a. [[sub.NP] My/your/his/her/our/their car] is red.
b. * [[sub.VP] my go]
c. * [[sub.ADVP] my quickly]
d. * [[sub.AP] my beautiful]
The grammaticality of example (4a) and the ungrammaticality of
examples (4b-d) show that my functions as a specifier according to the
definition of Huddleston and Pullum (2002, pp. 354-355), in that this
function occurs only with NPs.
Test 2
(5) [My car] is red.
In example (5), my specifies the NP as definite.
Test 3
(6) *Car is expensive.
Example (6) is ungrammatical because car is a singular common noun
and obligatorily requires a specifier that can make it either
indefinite, or definite, as in (7).
(7) My car is expensive.
The above shows that the words in the my set meet all three
properties of determinatives with the specifier function; therefore,
they are determinatives. Reynolds (2013) also argues that
the my set has a function that is never performed by
determinatives. She would object to my taking it (Huddleston &
Pullum, 2002) [no page numbers]). Uncontroversial determinatives do
not appear in this construction, but genitive NPs do [emphasis
added]. So we can replace my taking it with Jean's taking it or the
children's taking it, but not with * the taking it, * nearly every
taking it, or * no taking it. (p. 11)
Unfortunately, this is not true. There are words in Reynolds'
list of determinatives (Table 1, p. 8) that appear in this construction
(e.g., She would object to us/you taking it). It is interesting to note
here that the author states "We/us and you are determinatives
[i.e., a category] in expression[s] such as we teachers, you students;
elsewhere, of course, they are pronouns [i.e., a category]" (p. 8).
Compare this to the following statement: "It would be ridiculous
and confusing to be told that a saint, clearly an NP [i.e., a category],
is at the same time an adjective [i.e., a category].Yet this is
analogous to what happens in ELT when it comes to determiners" (p.
6). But if we/us and you are determinatives in certain expressions, but
pronouns elsewhere, then surely we/us and you are members of two
categories at the same time, namely pronouns and determinatives, and
Reynolds' goal of having determinatives as one category with
multiple functions falls apart here. It is worth noting in this regard
that such a paradox is resolved in X-bar theory, for pronouns in this
framework are determiners (X) and determiner phrases (XP) at the same
time (see, e.g., Hornstein, Nunes, & Grohmann, 2005).
Based on the data presented above, the my set passes two of the
three tests of the determinative category, and all three tests of the
specifier function; given that no one property is necessary according to
the author, then the my set satisfies all the properties of the
determinative category and the specifier function. It is crucial for our
purpose to note here that there could, in principle, be other criteria
that would suggest a pronominal analysis of the my set rather than the
determinative analysis that we argue for here. For example, one might
say, as Reynolds (2013, p. 10) and Huddleston and Pullum (2002) do, that
the my set inflects for person, number, and gender in a way similar to
other pronouns (he, she, they, etc.); therefore, the words in the my set
are pronouns. The point we make here is that the my set meets all the
criteria of the determinatives as a category and their function as a
specifier.
Are the words in Table 2 (p. 9) determinatives by the author's
criteria?
The author provides a list of lexical items (Reynolds, 2013, Table
2, p. 9) that he classifies as having the determinative category and the
head function on the grounds that they meet the third property of
determinatives, namely the partitive test (Test 3), which says that
these words can be used in the construction (HEAD + of + a definite NP).
To see how this test works, consider the following examples with some of
the lexical items that Reynolds lists (Table 2, p. 9) as items that pass
this test:
(8) [Many/both/several/three/few] of [the children] are playing in
the garden.
The example above shows that these lexical items pass the partitive
construction test, as they can be used in this construction to form a
grammatical sentence.
While the above is true, the property also allows the following:
(9) *[Many/*both/*several/*three/*few] of [the child] is/are
playing in the garden.
As the above example demonstrates, none of the above sentences is
grammatical even though each of the lexical items meets the third
property. Note that the source of ungrammaticality in (9) has nothing to
do with a mismatch in subject-verb agreement. The ungrammaticality
remains regardless of the form of the copular be (i.e., is/are).
Instead, the source of ungrammaticality is within the NP itself, as none
of the above lexical items can be used with singular count NPs.
The above example shows that the third property is not empirically
supported by the evidence.
Consider now another set of examples:
(10) a. [All/ most] of [the sugar/milk/salt/pepper] is on the
table.
b. [*Many/*both/*several/*three/*few] of [the
sugar/milk/salt/pepper] is/are on the table.
The example in (10a) shows that all and most are grammatical in the
partitive construction with a mass (or noncount) NP. However, none of
the other lexical items is grammatical with a mass NP, even though they
all meet the third property. This means that the property fails the
empirical test and has to be reconsidered so as to allow all and most,
but rule out the rest with mass NPs. It is worth noting here that in
modern linguistics, it is quite natural for all and most to show a
behaviour distinct from that of the others. To explain the difference,
we can borrow the notion of number transparency from Huddleston and
Pullum (2002, p. 349). We can say that in NPs with all and most, the
number feature of the head noun in the partitive oblique percolates up
to the determiners; therefore, these determiners acquire whatever number
feature the head noun has. The other determiners show the mirror image
of this. Thus, in NPs with few, many, several, three, it is the number
feature of the determiners that percolates down to the head noun of the
partitive oblique; therefore, the head noun acquires whatever number
feature the determiner has.
Consider now another problem that can be illustrated with the
following contrasting pair:
(11) a. [Sufficient people] arrived.
b. #[Sufficient] of [the three people] arrived.
The example in (11a) is grammatical because sufficient selects
plural heads in addition to selecting noncount heads (Huddleston &
Pullum, 2002, p. 396). The example in (11b), on the other hand, meets
Reynolds' third property; yet it is semantically anomalous (hence
the # notation). The source of the anomaly has to do with the fact that
words like sufficient "express imprecise quantification"
(Huddleston & Pullum, 2002, p. 396); therefore, they are
incompatible with definite NPs of the precise quantification expressed
in the definite NP, the three people. Something similar happens with the
following example:
(12) #[Both] of [the three people] arrived.
Here the NP meets Reynolds' third property; yet the example is
anomalous because both denotes a set of two, and this is incompatible
with the precise quantification given in the definite NP, the three
people.
Yet another problem can be found with little, as can be illustrated
by the following example:
(13) *[Little] of [the facts] is/are available.
The example in (13) meets Reynolds' third property of
determinative heads; yet, the sentence is ungrammatical. The
ungrammaticality in (13) stems from the fact that little is only
compatible with singular noncount NPs (see Huddleston & Pullum,
2002, p. 393).
In summary, the data in this section provide evidence that the
properties provided by the author to test the category of determinatives
are not supported empirically.
Do ESL learners need to know about determinatives and specifiers?
This section raises another question: What are the pedagogical
implications of Reynolds' (2013) article? It seems that the author
is not quite sure. At one point, he tells his readers that an
understanding of determinatives can help explain mistakes made by the
students. For example, why is it possible to say the Schramm model,
Schramm's model but not *Schramm model or *the Schramm's
model? He states that "[b]etter explanations and selection of
examples better to exemplify categorically similar items may help
students avoid or overcome such mistakes" (p. 14). However, in the
next paragraph, he states that the analysis he develops is quite complex
and "students need not be burdened with the type of analysis
presented here" (p. 14). The answer lies in referring the students
to "a list of determinatives or to a dictionary that labels them
correctly" (p. 14). It is no doubt helpful for ESL learners to have
access to reference materials and good grammar books. However, it is
well known from research in applied linguistics (see, e.g., Cook, 2001,
pp. 37-39; VanPatten, 2011) that there is a big gap between knowing
about an L2 grammar and putting it to use in actual communication. In
other words, explicit grammar instruction does not always lead to
successful second language acquisition (for a comprehensive discussion
of the role of grammar in the ESL classroom, see Ellis, 2006;
Larsen-Freeman, 2003). Today's methodology tells us that teaching
grammar is not only about referring learners to reference materials or
about explicit teaching of grammatical rules. Rather, it is about
providing "grammar instruction within a meaning-based context that
takes into account what learners need to know [italics added] in order
to complete communicative activities" (Centre for Canadian Language
Benchmarks, 2012, p. 53).
Conclusion
This article provides a critical review of Reynolds' article
(2013). We demonstrate that the claims made by the author are not
supported by theoretical or empirical evidence. To conclude, we
emphasize that we welcome the following by Huddleston and Pullum (2002):
(a) introducing the determinative category and determiner function (see
especially pp. 354-356) and noting that the determiner function is
called a specifier in other approaches (footnote 10, p. 25); (b)
proposing that determinatives can be thought of as one category with
various syntactic functions (p. 421); (c) introducing heads, modifiers,
and determiners as functions in the internal structure of the NP (p.
421, and the discussion throughout Chapter 5, pp. 323-523); (d) aiming
to bridge the gap between traditional grammar and advances in modern
linguistics (p. xv). We believe that these ideas should all be
incorporated into the field of ESL.
We agree with the author that it is essential to use the tools of
modern linguistics to categorize properly and to apply them to the field
of second language education; it is, however, the author's version
of determinatives that we reject in this article.
Acknowledgements
We would like to thank the two anonymous reviewers for many
insightful comments and suggestions on a previous draft of this article.
Their suggestions have greatly improved both the form and the content of
the article. We would also like to thank the participants at the 11th
Annual Graduate Student Forum, Department of Languages, Literatures and
Linguistics, York University, for their feedback on a previous draft of
the article. Any remaining errors are our own.
References
Centre for Canadian Language Benchmarks (CCLB). (2012).
Incorporating grammar in a CLB-based program. CLB support kit. Retrieved
from http://www.language.ca/documents/ clb_support_kit_1.pdf
Cook, V. (2001). Second language learning and language teaching
(3rd ed.). London, UK: Arnold.
Croft, W., & Cruse, D. A. (2004). Cognitive linguistics.
Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.
Cruse, A. (2004). Meaning in language: An introduction to semantics
and pragmatics (2nd ed.). Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press.
Ellis, R. (2006). Current issues in the teaching of grammar: An SLA
perspective. TESOL Quarterly, 40(1), 83-108.
Hornstein, N., Nunes, J., & Grohmann, K. K. (2005).
Understanding minimalism. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.
Huddleston, R., & Pullum, G. K. (2002). The Cambridge grammar
of the English language. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.
Kearns, K. (2000). Semantics. New York, NY: Palgrave Macmillan.
Larsen-Freeman, D. (2003). Teaching language: From grammar to
grammaring. Boston, MA: Heinle.
Reynolds, B. (2013). Determiners, feline marsupials, and the
category-function distinction: A critique of ELT grammars. TESL Canada
Journal, 30(2), 1-17.
Tallerman, M. (2011). Understanding syntax (3rd ed.). London, UK:
Hodder Education.
VanPatten, B. (2011). Stubborn syntax: How it resists explicit
teaching and learning. In C. Sanz & R. P. Leow (Eds.), Implicit and
explicit language learning: Conditions, processes and knowledge in SLA
and bilingualism (pp. 9-21). Washington, DC: Georgetown University
Press.
Notes
(1.) It should be noted that the determinatives presented by
Reynolds in Tables 1 and 2 (2013, pp. 8-9) are almost identical to those
compiled by Huddleston and Pullum (2002, pp. 356, 361). However, the
author does not provide a direct reference to their lists. Throughout
the article, the work of Huddleston and Pullum is cited without page
referencing. This makes it difficult to refer to the cited source,
especially given the fact that the book by Huddleston and Pullum is
1,764 pages long, excluding a section on further reading, references,
and indices.
(2.) A note should be made here on the linguistic criteria (i.e.,
morphosyntactic, distributional, and functional) that are used in modern
linguistic theory to classify words into grammatical categories. Thus,
words are classified into different grammatical categories not only
because "they are grammatically alike in the language system"
(Reynolds, p. 4), as stated (but not clarified) by the author. Rather,
they have to have similar morphosyntactic, distributional, and
functional properties. For example, the word poet is categorized as a
noun because (a) it can be pluralized, as in two poets (morphosyntactic
property); (b) it occupies a specific syntactic position in the NP a
poet, that is, it is preceded by a determiner (distribution); (c) it has
a specific function in the clause, that is, it can function as the
subject of a finite clause in English, as in A poet won a competition
(for a more detailed description of the linguistic criteria, see, e.g.,
Tallerman, 2011, p. 36).
The Authors
Iryna Lenchuk is a PhD candidate in the Linguistics and Applied
Linguistics program at the Department of Languages, Literatures and
Linguistics at York University, Toronto, Ontario. She is also a
part-time TESL instructor at the Faculty of Continuing Education and
Training, Seneca College, Toronto, Ontario.
Amer Ahmed is a PhD candidate in the Linguistics and Applied
Linguistics program at the Department of Languages, Literatures and
Linguistics at York University, Toronto, Ontario.
Table 1
Linguistic Tests Used by Reynolds (2013)
The Determinative Category The Specifier Function
Tests (see p. 7) Tests (see p. 6)
If X is a determinative (as a If X is a specifier
category), then generally ... (as a function), then ...
1. X cannot combine with the 1. X occurs only in NPs.
or a or with each other
(except in coordination).
2. X can combine with a 2. X typically specifies the
singular count noun NP as definite
to form a grammatical NP. or indefinite.
3. X can occur as a head in 3. If the head of an NP is a
the partitive construction singular countable common
(i.e., HEAD + of + DEFINITE noun, X (definite or
NP) (p. 7). indefinite) is typically
obligatory.
(The source of the tests is (These tests are based on the
not identified by the author. properties identified by
We therefore assume that these Huddleston and Pullum (2002,
are his.) pp. 354-355), who call this
function a determiner
function.