Agenda for a South-South Philosophical Dialogue.
Dussel, Enrique
The intercultural dialogue that has been developing since the
beginning of the 21st century as a cultural and political priority
should have an inter-philosophical global dialogue as its
epistemological and ontological foundation. Nonetheless, given the
disproportionate concentration of cultural, political, economic, and
military power in the Global North and given the exercise of power
characterized by inequalities of race and gender, among other factors,
against the Global South--i.e., the former colonial world whose
configurations emerged in the 16th century and have intensified since
the Industrial Revolution in Latin America, Bantu Africa, the Arab and
Islamic world, Southeast Asia and India, including China which, although
it was not directly colonized, has borne the effects of Western power
since the 19th century--it is necessary that this process begin with an
inter-philosophical dialogue among the world's postcolonial
communities.
This is also necessary because modern Western philosophy decreed
the inexistence as philosophy, strictly speaking, of all of the
philosophical exercises undertaken in those countries which have borne
the effects of the colonialism imposed by the European metropolitan
powers. It is thus imperative that the philosophers of the South meet in
recognition of their existence as such--grounded in the traditions that
they have cultivated in the regional philosophies from which they have
emerged--in order to clarify our positions, develop working hypotheses,
and then, upon this basis, initiate a fertile North-South
inter-philosophical dialogue with a well-defined agenda that has been
previously developed by the philosophies based in the so-called
"underdeveloped" countries or nations of the global periphery
who have the material basis to affirm that they have been exploited by a
colonialist capitalism that today has become globalized and is in
crisis.
My approach to these issues is set forth here in the form of simple
theses that might contribute towards this dialogue, with the intention
that they be tested in forthcoming debates as bases for possible
consensus regarding central themes which must be ranked in the order of
their importance with a view towards more focused, specific dialogues at
later stages of this process. Those themes could then be explored in
greater detail as part of agreed frameworks that could be taught in high
schools, universities, and other institutes of learning, and help spark
new working hypotheses and innovative research projects, derived from
the new philosophical paradigm presented here.
1. THE SIGNIFICANCE OF AN AGENDA OF PHILOSOPHICAL THEMES TO BE
DISCUSSED WITHIN THE FRAMEWORK OF A SOUTH-SOUTH DIALOGUE
In the first instance, I believe that a necessary precondition for
a fertile overall dialogue in the future is the meeting of a group of
critical philosophers from the Global South (not those who simply teach
or comment on the philosophers of the North) in order to undertake deep
discussions, with sufficient time, to determine which are the problems,
themes, and hypotheses for reflection that they should focus on in the
future. These meetings would provide the participants the opportunity to
explore each of the most fundamental themes or hypotheses in order to
assess their deeper significance within a community of dialogue, and
arrive at the levels of consensus necessary in order to define minimum
ranges of agreement, that in turn could lay the basis for a truly
planetary philosophy (not just for the South, but for the Global North
as well).
Such a consensus (and its respective priorities) could only be
arrived at upon the basis of a determination of the most relevant
themes. This in turn presupposes a degree of critical philosophical
reflection necessary in order to initiate such a dialogue from a new
point of departure. It would not be necessary to discuss a specific
theme in this first encounter, but instead to undertake a reflection
regarding the significance and implications of the current situation of
contemporary postcolonial philosophy, the causes of its prostration, as
well as of its supposed inexistence, lack of fertility, and invisibility
in the eyes of our fellow philosophers in the so- called
"periphery." How did this situation come about? How can this
apparent inexistence of the regional philosophies be overcome? Which are
the themes that should be explored, and in what order? In some regions
of the South or postcolonial world, the histories of our regional
philosophies, some of which have ancient roots dating back for centuries
and even thousands of years, have begun to be written for the first time
and to be renovated with new criteria. It has been a long time since the
history of our philosophies ceased to be a central aspect of the
formation of our university students of philosophy. The prevailing
tendency has long been to simply transplant the curriculums developed in
European or U.S. universities (the latter, particularly, since the end
of the so-called "Second World War"). All of this reflects a
dismal state of affairs, which is one of the manifest fruits of a
cultural colonialism that must be confronted.
The discussion regarding the factors that impeded the development
of our regional philosophies in the South, and the order in which they
arose, ought to be the first item on the agenda that must be explored
upon the basis of a full awareness of its importance.
2. METROPOLITAN MODERNITY AND THE COLONIAL WORLDS
My point of departure is that all philosophies (Chinese, Indian,
Egyptian, Greek, Roman, Arab, Amerindian, etc.) have inevitably been
ethnocentric in character, since their origin lies in a certain
ontological ingenuousness which considers their own world (their
cultural totality assumed as a complete grasp of the meaning of human
existence) as the center around which the rest of humanity revolved.
This ethnocentrism, however, was empirically local and regional in
character. Even the immense Chinese empire, which always assumed itself
to be the "center" of the universe, never ceased to be
centered around its particularity, with only the most incipient
consciousness of its near and distant surroundings. It considered other
peoples if not inferior then as causes of disquiet within its apparent
imperturbability, because it suspected that its knowledge was inherently
limited, and that an immense unknown exteriority lingered in the shadows
of the unexplored and might erupt into visibility at any moment. The
accounts of sporadic travelers, which told of adventures in unknown
regions, were not given much credit but could in any case illuminate
that consciousness which was never clear about the phantoms, monstrous
beings, and bottomless depths that surrounded it, like those strewn
throughout the Atlantic in the equivalent representations imagined by
the Europeans under siege by the Arab and Islamic world in what they
referred to as the so-called "Middle Ages." (1)
But it was only in the European context that for the first time in
the history of humanity such traditional expressions of ethnocentrism
reached the most distant confines of the planet itself, and began to be
diffused around the Earth beginning in the 15th-century of the Common
Era. As a result of rapid technological development, Chinese,
Portuguese, and Spanish navigators for the first time achieved the
circumnavigation of the globe, which made it possible for the European
version of what was merely yet another particularist, localized
ethnocentrism to be transformed into an ethnocentrism on a global scale.
This included first the modern expansion of Mediterranean Europe, and
later that of Northern Europe, which together marked the inception of
what we describe today as globalization.
European modernity emerged simultaneously with this process, thanks
to the mercantile centrality of the North Atlantic (which displaced that
of the Mediterranean), leading to the emergence of capitalism as a
historical phenomenon, and to Eurocentrism and the scientific and
technological revolution which would result from the combination of all
of these factors. All of these were also the origin of a modern
philosophy, which would lay claim to the privilege of supposedly being
the sole vehicle for the deployment of human reason capable of
transcending the narratives of mythology, thus discrediting all of the
religions of the South. This philosophy did not only have the pretension
of being universal, planetary, and the expression of human reason as
such, but also categorized all other regional philosophies of the South
as "backward," naive, and particular. Once the process of the
Spanish conquest of the Americas began at the end of the 15th century in
the Caribbean (with all of the cultural conflicts that were inherent in
this process), all of its argumentation was focused on the demonstration
of the superiority of European civilization, and thus gradually that of
its philosophy. Europe's military conquests and the destruction of
pre-existent commercial routes would help impede the possibility that
other cultures might subsequently match European levels of development,
and would seek to prevent them from progressing upon the basis of a new
perspective on world history distinct from that which had been
inaugurated by the original world-system. The cultures which were
colonized sought to defend themselves by reiterating the value of their
past glories, but this was not a sufficient basis for them either to
resist the new developments which ensued or to formulate arguments that
were effective against the superiority assumed by their European
adversaries. In the end, they were largely swept away by events and were
not able to confront the new European philosophy for centuries.
This overall landscape should not be exaggerated, because in
reality there were significant moments of specific creativity in all the
regions of the South. But such moments were soon excluded from the
regional histories of these philosophies in favor of the prevalence of
the advances achieved by modern European philosophy beginning with
Descartes, which would attain a hegemony that is still unsurpassed among
the colonial elites.
A specific kind of historical judgment soon became diffused
throughout the periphery. It was true that a certain kind of
philosophical discourse was conducted with locally important figures,
but how could this be compared with the thought of Kant, Hegel,
Nietzsche, Heidegger, Sartre, or Carnap? This question was poorly
formulated and, as a result, the responses it inspired were incomplete
and complicit, serving only to blur and bury the historical truths at
issue. In Latin America, until recently, it was said, "There is no
Latin American philosophy!"--if by philosophy one understands the
practice of the same kind of theoretical discourse which had been
developed in the context of modern European philosophy. But certainly in
the Latin American context, there have been numerous philosophers and
philosophical currents which have helped lay the basis for cultural,
political, economic, or technological processes, and which interpreted
the meaning of life within the cultural contexts of our region. But
these efforts obtained regional, not global, recognition, as might be
expected within the framework of a peripheral culture.
One must therefore meditate in detail on the causes which produced
the eclipse of the philosophies of the South in order to be able to
clearly comprehend the negative factors which must be overcome to
undertake the process of developing the philosophies of the
postcolonial, peripheral, or dominated regions of the world, subjected
to the colonialism of the European metropolises, whose domination has
not only been military, economic, or political, but also ideological,
cultural, and at its roots philosophical.
3. THE COLONIAL DIMENSIONS OF ECONOMIC AND TECHNOLOGICAL EXPANSION
At the end of the 15th century, Europe was completely limited,
surrounded by the walls of the Ottoman Empire. The Muslims laid siege to
Vienna well into the 17th century, and did not cease to occupy Granada
(the last region representative of the splendor of the ancient Califate
of Cordoba) until January 1492. The Latino-Germanic region of Europe
(not that of the Byzantine or oriental Empire) was peripheral,
under-developed, and cornered by the Islamic world, and thus unable to
connect itself with the "Old World" envisioned by Adam Smith.
Its only path in that direction was through the ports of the Italian
cities, which dominated the traffic of the Eastern Mediterranean, and
from there to Fatimid Egypt or Syrian Antioch, which led eventually to
Baghdad, or to the caravans which reached China through the deserts of
the north, or India via Kabul. The other way was north of the Black Sea
all the way to Constantinople, or across the Red Sea or Persian Gulf
towards Hindustan and the China Sea. This Europe, which was dark (during
the so-called "Middle Ages"), could only break through its
isolation from the Northeast through the Principality of Moscow (which
would reach into Siberia and arrive at the Pacific at the beginning of
the 17th century), or via the West, through Portugal and Spain. The
discovery of the caravel in 1441, and the slow dominion of the
Oceans--thanks to the Chinese maps of the Atlantic and Pacific, the
compass, and other instruments of navigation equally of Chinese origin
(China had an advantage of more than 400 years with respect to the
technology, science, and astronomy characteristic of Medieval
Europe)--enabled it to discover and manage the Atlantic Ocean, which
would become the geopolitical center of European modernity. The
development of naval and military technology would enable Portugal to
take control of the maritime commercial routes of Africa, the Indian
Ocean, India, the Moluccas, and the coasts of China and Japan. And it
would be Spain which established the first European continental
colonialism in Latin America and imposed it upon the continent's
original inhabitants (Meso-Americans, Incas, Tupi-Guaranf, etc.) for
three hundred years (from the end of the 15th century until the
beginning of the 19th century, approximately).
This expansion, due to the greater levels of development of
military strategy and technology in comparison with the cultures of
native Latin America, would establish, in the first phase of Early
Modernity, (2) an economic system of mercantile and monetary capitalism
based upon the extraction of silver, gold, and colonial goods, founded
upon the inhuman domination of the continent's indigenous peoples
and the Atlantic slave trade, which would incorporate West Africa into a
triangle of death structured around the relationship between Africa,
Latin America, and Europe: Europe would transport arms to Africa; from
there slaves would be transported to the Americas (and later to the
English colonies in North America); the sale of these slaves would
permit silver and gold (money) and tropical products (sugar, cacao,
tobacco, etc.) to be sold in Europe or accumulated in its banks. This
was the period of capitalist "primitive accumulation." Later,
the Dutch, English, French, and Danes would land in India and the rest
of Asia, and capitalist commerce with its center in Europe would achieve
global dimensions.
The tragic component inherent in the process which produced the
configuration of a capitalist economic world-system is that the colonial
world would be interpreted as one which is inhabited by human beings who
are exploitable and are treated as if they belonged to a secondary class
of human beings in anthropological, ontological, and ethical-political
terms, as we shall see. The original inhabitants of the colonized
regions of the Global South were thus assumed to be sub-humans whose
domination by Europeans supposedly endows them at the same time with a
limited dosage of enhanced humanity. Coloniality was interpreted from
the European perspective as a kind of gift, the endowment of humanity.
This ideological core which underlies all the other modern ideologies
has prevailed up until the present.
4. THE POLITICAL AND MILITARY DIMENSIONS OF COLONIAL EXPANSION
Political and military forms of aggression always precede economic
expansion, as expressed within the context of the capitalist mercantile
system in Latin America in the form of big landed estates (haciendas)
and systems of forced miner community labor (the mita), the African
slave trade and slavery, and through unequal forms of commerce such as
the Opium Wars in the Far East. It was a Eurocentric "will to
power" which organized armies of occupation, whose strategic and
technological advantages were able to overcome the resistance of the
political structures of power (sometimes regional and sometimes local or
ethnic in character) they encountered in their path, first in Latin
America (beginning at the end of the 15th century) and then in Africa or
Asia (on a continental stage from the end of the 18th century). The
emerging modern states (in Spain, Portugal, the United Provinces of
Holland, England, France, Denmark, etc.) from their origins combined the
following characteristics, which developed together in an intertwined
manner: a) royal domination of state churches (Christendoms (3)), b)
coloniality, c) mercantilist versions of capitalism, and d)
Eurocentrism.
The coloniality of power (a concept clarified by the sociologist of
Peru, Anfbal Quijano) of the European colonial metropolises was
expressed in diverse forms of domination imposed upon their dependent
colonies. The European king at the head of each of the metropolitan
powers exercised an unquestioned monopoly of power over their colonial
subjects. The coloniality of the members of the colonial communities
impeded their participation as proper citizens; they were the subject
neither of political rights nor human rights equivalent to those of the
European metropolitan subjects. None of this was contradictory from the
European colonialist perspective, given the premises of the European
conception of law (which Carl Schmitt describes accurately, although he
is incapable of perceiving its Eurocentrism). This explains how it was
possible, within the constraints of this framework, for the French
Revolution to issue the Declaration of the Rights of Man and the Citizen
in August 1789 (the first list of its kind of ostensibly universal human
rights), (4) and at the same time to apply its Code Noir (Black Code),
which was the governing law in the French colony, to define the duties
and restrict the rights of the slaves it possessed in the Caribbean (in
Haiti, whose slave rebellion in 1791 finally led to the independence in
1804). These slaves evidently were not considered to be human or to be
the subject of the new universal human rights proclaimed by a bourgeois,
colonialist revolution in metropolitan France (which considered the
citizens of the metropolis to be equal, fraternal, and free, but
considered the non-humans of the South to be slaves who were inherently
unequal and thus the legitimate objects of domination). (5)
The European metropolitan countries had political institutions in
charge of administering matters related with their overseas territories,
beginning with the Spanish Council of the Indies established at the
beginning of the 16th century. These institutions combined political and
military dimensions in charge of vigilance and punishment, when
necessary (as suggested by Foucault's book Discipline and Punish),
related to the extraction of wealth from the colonial regions, without
any concern whatever for their reciprocal duties to colonial workers
(including indigenous peoples who worked for them for free, African
slaves, and exploited mestizos). The idea was never that of a
symmetrical commercial exchange (involving the payment of the value
equivalent to that of the commodity transported from the periphery to
the center); instead, the essence of the matter was a theft of the
exchange value which had been expropriated thanks to the presence of a
military power that impeded the colonial world from demanding a just
payment for the extraction of wealth from the South. Violent military
coercion guaranteed economic theft, which was not considered to obligate
the metropolitan center in terms of a debt owed to the colonies (and
which would involve a just payment of interest). Rather, what was at
issue was the direct appropriation of goods belonging to someone else
pursuant to a purported right of conquest, which always in fact implied
an imposition grounded in superior military force. Jurgen Habermas has
correctly emphasized that any consensus must be achieved as the result
of the symmetrical rational participation of all those affected; but the
political dimension of colonialism implied instead the asymmetrical
imposition by force, not of a rational consensus but of an irrational
will to power exercised by the center against the periphery.
Nonetheless, the philosophers of the center speak today of rights,
symmetry, and democracy (and do not criticize the wars conducted today
to "establish democracy" in the "backward" countries
of the South), without ever having acknowledged the last 500 years of
irrational, colonialist, and anti- democratic political and military
violence, in which they are implicated, and its negative effects.
The political philosophy of the South today must rethink all of the
philosophical tradition from Hobbes or Locke up until the Frankfurt
School, C. Schmitt, A. Badiou or G. Agamben, to name just a few, who
have not yet succeeded in overcoming the Eurocentrism which has always
accompanied the political expansion of Europe, and now that of the
United States as well.
5. THE ONTOLOGICAL-PHILOSOPHICAL JUSTIFICATION OF COLONIALISM
Colonial praxis has from the beginning relied upon a philosophical
justification as its foundation, and this is the point of departure for
modern European philosophy with its universality claim, which
unfortunately is accepted by most of the members of the philosophical
academies of the South. This justification also had an anthropological
character (expressed in the assumption of the superiority of European
human beings over those of the South, as reflected in the interpretation
of that superiority by Gines de Sepulveda in his re-reading of Aristotle
in the 16th century, or by Kant in the 18th century, based upon his
conception of the origins of such inequalities in the climates of the
Earth and its regions)--one aspect of which was historical (where Europe
was, for example, the "center and end of universal history"
for Hegel) and another which was ethical (in terms of the inclusion
within European culture of the peoples of the Americas, Africa, or Asia,
upon whom was imposed its vision of an ethics which is non-conventional,
individualist, founded upon rational argumentation, universal, and not
merely particular such as those characteristic of the cultures of the
South, etc.)--which served to demonstrate the legitimacy of colonialism.
But the ultimate foundation of colonial praxis was ontological in
character. The European "I" which had enunciated to the South
for over a century and a half, beginning in 1492, its formulation,
"I conquer the New World," now assumed itself as a universal
ontological foundation as "I." This central Ego (Ichheit in
German), around which everything revolved, was inadvertently European: a
European "I" with the pretension of discovering itself to be
universal and ultimate, which knows itself, and which can reconstruct
all of the world (including all of the worlds contained within the
South). It is within this context that Rene Descartes, during the second
phase of Early Modernity, in Amsterdam (a Spanish province until shortly
before his emergence), a student of the Jesuits (a Spanish religious
order) enunciates his ego cogito. This ego, this metropolitan European
"I" (6) is the ontological-philosophical foundation of what
Martin Heidegger will denominate as the "world" (Welt) in
Being and Time (1927). (7) In 1637, Descartes's Discourse on Method
serves as the manifesto of modern European philosophy, which assumes its
role as the supposed universal philosophy throughout the next 400 years.
(8) The need to overcome this Eurocentric vision must precisely be the
primary objective of a dialogue among the philosophers of the South,
among those of us from the post-colonial regions, who continue to be
treated as if we were still colonial subjects in epistemological and
philosophical terms, in the vast majority of our spaces for
philosophical and academic reflection within the universities of the
South. In large part, the function we fulfill and have assumed is as
mere commentators at the periphery of modern European philosophy, and
not as thinkers with reflections regarding our reality, which has been
negated and which has not been the object of thinking by that philosophy
which claims universality for itself.
Philosophical coloniality has dual aspects: a) in the center, Spain
of the 16th century, due to the universality claim of its European
metropolitan regional philosophy since the 16th century which at the
same time has negated and marginalized the contributions of the
pre-Cartesian ethical and political philosophy that flourished during
the period of the First Early Modernity and has disappeared from the
histories of modern philosophy; and b) in the periphery, the South,
because of the prevailing, unquestioning acceptance of the supposed
evidence that the said European philosophy is in fact the universal
philosophy, which has imposed itself throughout the last few centuries.
This latter aspect presupposes for its part: i) an ignorance of the
regional philosophies of the periphery from their origins (prior to and
together with that of European modernity); ii) the negative evaluation
of the significance of its own philosophies throughout the last 500
years; and iii) the definition of philosophy (in the colonial philosophy
of the South) as commentary regarding the European modern philosophy
(that has a universal claim) that denies even the very existence of the
South's own philosophies. In addition, there is a marked tendency
in these colonial philosophies of the South towards argumentation in
favor of their impossibility and as to their uselessness or superfluity.
The colonial philosophy of the South then, in a negative sense, is
that which is practiced in the periphery by those who act based on the
premises of Eurocentrism and deny their own regional and local
philosophy. From the perspective of the center, it is modern philosophy
which negates all other philosophies (from the South), and which
categorizes them as being equivalent to mythological, folkloric,
conventional, backward, particularist, and/or pseudo-philosophical
thinking.
6. THE ECONOMIC AND POLITICAL LIBERATION OF THE SOUTH
The concrete historical processes of national or regional
liberation in the face of European colonialism--which began in the South
with Tupac Amaru and Tupac Katari between 1780-1781, and then in Haiti
between 1791 and 1804 against France, in 1810 with Latin America against
Spain and Portugal, and in Africa and Asia following the Second World
War--laid the foundation for the emergence of a philosophy of liberation
from colonialism. These events determine a creative moment which should
be taken into account.
These political, economic, and cultural moments of liberation must
also be considered to be culminations of a philosophical process, as
well as the birth of a philosophy which is intertwined with praxis and
which lays the foundation for a justification of this age of
emancipation from colonialism. It will be necessary, therefore, to be
especially attentive to the historical reconstruction of the philosophy
of the South (in singular or plural, for it is also necessary to
highlight the "philosophies" of the South). It is simply
impossible to conceive of an autonomous, creative, truly free philosophy
in the South within the tortuous, suffocating limits of the political,
economic, and cultural horizons of a community which has been colonized,
subjugated, exploited, and oppressed. As Augusto Salazar Bondy wrote in
1969 in neocolonial Peru, it is very difficult to construct an authentic
philosophy in a colonial and dependent context. (9)
The post-colonial situation (which is not exempt from neoliberal or
other new economic, political, geopolitical, or epistemological variants
of colonialism) is the contemporary framework of conditions which make
liberation from colonial philosophy possible within the context of a new
stage of creativity. In my view, this is the current responsibility of
philosophers who have the pretension of being thinkers regarding the
reality that surrounds them, as European philosophers did in the context
of their reality, in their metropolitan and colonial context. This goes
much beyond merely being the commentators of philosophical works, from
which a great deal can be learned, but which must be understood as the
expression of thinking grounded in another reality. To confuse European
or U.S. reality with our own simply constitutes a fallacy of dislocation
(the fallacy of taking the space or world of another culture as
one's own, and thereby rendering invisible the distinct originality
inherent in the other reality and its very differences with one's
own). (10)
7. THE AFFIRMATION OF THE ANCESTRAL CULTURES OF THE SOUTH
Philosophy does not imply an isolated process of theoretical
production, but instead one that involves a commitment to the world
surrounding us. The pretension of such absolute autonomy is what
characterizes the efforts of a certain school of Anglo-Saxon analytical
philosophy, which nonetheless supposes all of the history of philosophy
from the Vienna Circle to the philosophy of language in the British
Isles, to be itself the history of philosophy as such, when in fact all
of this must be situated in specific cultural worlds, located in the
universities of certain countries in certain specific historical moments
with concrete characteristics that explain their emergence, development,
and current crisis. The Frankfurt School, French existentialism,
phenomenology, etc., all argued that a philosophy without historical
commitment (that is, one that is isolated from specific philosophical,
cultural, economic, and political moments within their historical
contexts) is impossible. Thomas Kuhn demonstrated that scientific
revolutions (and thus those of a philosophical character as well) depend
not only on intra-scientific events, but also on extra-scientific
factors which help determine their emergence.
For their part, Eurocentric philosophies in the South, in
post-colonial countries, equally seek to practice a universal philosophy
of the modern European type within their own cultural horizon, that of
the South in Latin America, Africa, or Asia. (11) This compels them to
accept certain apparent forms of evidence that constitute unquestionable
dogmas within modern European philosophy, such as the idea that
philosophy itself is of Greek origin marked by the transition from
mythos to logos. Both of these formulations--that is, philosophy's
Greek origin and the overcoming of mythos by logos--are unacceptable.
Today it is widely recognized that long before Greece, there was
philosophy in the Mesopotamian kingdoms dating back to the 4th century
BCE, and in Egypt. Thales of Miletus, the first recognized Greek
philosopher, came from a family of Phoenician origin. (12) And as to the
relationship between mythology and philosophy, Aristotle considered the
latter to be a form of mythopoiesis, and Greek philosophy as a whole
(beginning with the post-Socratics such as Plato or Plotinus) were
completely immersed in a world permeated by myth: What, for example, is
the psyche (soul) in Plato but a myth of Hindustani origin, which cannot
be demonstrated by means of empirical evidence (a myth which is handed
down all the way to Kant)? What are the Enneads of Plotinus but an
expression of the metaphysical cosmic mathematics characteristic of
Egyptian culture?
It is upon the basis of the allegedly irrational and
anti-philosophical character (according to the modern European
definition of philosophy) of myths and religious narratives (which,
according to Paul Ricoeur, one of my professors at the Sorbonne in
Paris, are rational philosophical narratives based on symbols), that
modernity denied any validity to the philosophical narratives (which
contained myths) of the cultures of the South, including those of China
and India which go back for millennia, as well as those of the
Iranian-Aristotelian tradition of scientific and empirical inquiry in
the Arab world.
In order to reconstruct the philosophies of the South, it is
necessary, as part of a pendulum swing in the inverse direction from
that imposed by the pretensions of modern European secularism (which
necessarily implied the negation of the ancestral cultures of the
South), to restore the validity and significance of the traditions of
these regions of the world, including those of a mythical character, and
to subject them to an adequate hermeneutical interpretation. It is the
methodology of interpretation (hermeneutics) which is philosophical;
although the text or narrative subjected to this process can be
mythical, poetic, or non-philosophical, the result of this
interpretation would thus be hermeneutically a work of philosophy.
It is thus necessary to recover the symbolic narratives of our
ancestral cultures in the South, regardless of whether they are
philosophical, mythical, or religious in character or not (even those
texts categorized as theophanic or revelatory), in order to subject them
to a philosophical labor within the overall framework of reconstructing
our traditions. The local reality of the South which I have alluded to
is enveloped in myth, as is that of modern philosophy, (13) and must be
considered a humanist, rational, and symbolic point of departure for a
history and philosophy of the South.
8. THE PHILOSOPHY OF THE SOUTH AS A CRITIQUE OF COLONIALITY
The philosophy of the South, as a front or philosophical consensus
consisting of many philosophies of the post-colonial, underdeveloped, or
exploited world (in some cases, only recently free of direct colonial
domination) (14)--with some sectors in the process of achieving greater
autonomy than others (15)--should in the first place take into
consideration the themes described above. The point of departure must be
an understanding of the epistemologically colonial character of its
methods, themes, use of sources, and manners of discourse; the reality
in which it is immersed and the community to which it is
directed--whether it be the philosophical community of the South, the
intellectual community, or peoples of the post-colonial world which is
in process of liberation--are unavoidable themes integral to the
philosophy of the South.
I also believe that there is a specific aspect which should be
prioritized; it is a question which we have analyzed in certain
dialogues between Arab and Latin American intellectuals, namely: What
were the causes which led to the virtual "disappearance" or
loss of overall creativity of the philosophies of the South since the
emergence of modern European philosophy? Here I am alluding, for
example, to the disconnection of the Islamic world (as I have suggested,
from Morocco to the Philippines, passing through Tunisia and Egypt,
through Iraq and its center in Baghdad, Afghanistan, the Mogul empire in
India, the commercial sultanates of Indochina, and the Moluccas or Spice
Islands) due in part to its disruption by Portuguese colonialism and to
the indifference of mercantilism and of Arab culture with regard to the
use of oceanic navigation (initiated in the context of modernity by
China, which discovered the Americas, Africa, and Australia beginning in
the early 14th century). All of these factors together produced the
absence of a joint reaction and effort to resist European expansion. The
Ottoman Empire itself, defeated at Lepanto in 1571 (due in part to the
flow of Latin American silver towards Spain), lost the capacity to
control its territory because of economic crises (which included the
devaluation of that same silver in the Islamic system due to the influx
of cheap silver from Latin America). The Arab world was impoverished
without losing money because of the devaluation of its currency. This is
how it ceased to be the necessary "center" capable of
connecting all of the cultures of Asia, Africa, and the Mediterranean;
thus began its long slide into peripheral coloniality.
Although global commerce was centered around relations between
China and Hindustan up until around 1800, the impact of the crisis in
its own first industrial revolution would lead China to retreat into
itself and thus lose the possibility of developing the potential of its
own technological inventions which it had achieved between the 7th and
18th centuries, (16) which in turn helped spark the Italian Renaissance
and the English Industrial Revolution.
Once this question has been fully explored (here I have only begun
to sketch an initial approach), a philosophical critique focused on the
destructive tendency of philosophical colonialism with regard to the
impact of European modern philosophy must be developed. In the absence
of the kind of critique of the coloniality of each of the national and
regional or continental philosophies of the cultural entities of the
South, it will not be possible to undertake the subsequent stage of
unleashing a moment of philosophical creativity and symmetry throughout
the South. When I refer to "symmetry" in this context, what I
am suggesting is the need to develop a psychological attitude and
approach representative of a certain normality that would make it
possible for those of us in the South to consider and treat academic
colleagues in Europe and the U.S as "equals." We should free
ourselves of false respect for a knowledge with universalist
pretensions. This false respect could be overcome by philosophers in the
South once they possess the historical, cultural, and philosophical
tools of the same quality as their colleagues in the metropolitan
centers, which at minimum would enable our peers in the South to uncover
the signs within us of an inadvertent Eurocentrism which has been
ignored. A well-founded accusation of Eurocentrism (expressed either as
an ignorance of the South or as an ignorance of one's own
Eurocentrism) places the colleague from the center or North in an
uncomfortable and unaccustomed situation (which destabilizes their
previously assured centrality and universality and ultimate superiority)
before the philosophers of the South. When a philosopher of the South
falls into the trap of formulating a Eurocentric judgment (for example,
due to their ignorance regarding the history of philosophy in the
South), they could exclaim: "What you are reflecting is the
expression of a Eurocentric philosophy that judges what is in fact
unknown to you." It is likely that the confident, secure professor
or academic from the center will lose their serenity or get angry, which
would only make things worse (intensifying the arguments deployed
against his or her positioning), or might begin to reflect and accept
the criticisms proffered. It is only at this stage that a slow dialogue
between the philosophy of the North and that of the South can truly
begin, which is both so necessary and virtually inexistent, within an
ethical framework of symmetry, respect, and openness to the truth.
9. THE UNFOLDING OF A PHILOSOPHY OF THE SOUTH
A key priority which should be included in the initial stages of
development of a network of philosophies of the South is to begin with
the study, debate, exposition, and publication of histories of
philosophy in each of our countries, continents, and regions. It is
notable that the first histories of the national philosophies of the
South are beginning to appear. (17) At the same time we must also
prioritize the publication (electronic and by other means) of the
classical works of the philosophies of the South, at least since the end
of the 15th century. It would be even better if all of the classic works
since the origins of these regional histories were included.
These publications should be the result of debates regarding the
corresponding periods of philosophical history in each context, their
significance and contents, and the works which should be taken into
account. It should be evident that this process of critical
reconstruction must be open to varying contents with wide-ranging
interpretations, including those which are philosophical in content but
not simply imitative of foreign philosophies, and which engage themes
emerging from the historical process of the peoples themselves. These
historical processes are the points of reference for the most important
philosophers who accompanied these processes, and sometimes, these
philosophers influenced such processes to a greater or lesser extent.
Undoubtedly Confucius or Lao Tse were key constituent factors in the
configuration of Chinese culture, Budhha or Sankara in Hindustan,
Al-Farabi or Ibn Sina (often referred to by his Latinized name as
Avicenna) in the Arab and Iranian contexts, or Bartolome de Las Casas in
the Latin American context of the 16th century.
But together with this dissemination of histories and reflection by
philosophers of the South--researchers, students, professors, and
intellectuals in general--upon the most valuable aspects of their own
philosophical traditions, it is also necessary to develop a creative
discourse which is properly philosophical in character, and which thus
goes beyond mere commentaries on either one's ancestral tradition
or that of Europe. This implies contributions that take the reality and
history of the treatment of key specific themes in the corresponding
regional or local philosophy of the South. Philosophical reflection
should enrich these realities critically with one's own tools, and
in dialogue with the best expressions of modern European philosophy
(which the philosophers of the South must know how to select and
incorporate into their own projects of distinct, autonomous thought).
All of this should be deployed with an emphasis on producing clear
thinking which is well-founded, coherent, and understandable by those
responsible for the concrete political, economic, aesthetic,
technological, and scientific realities of the countries of the South.
In sum, what is aimed at is a proper philosophy, which is both an
expression of the South and a useful contribution to its community of
reference.
In order to achieve these objectives it is also crucial to avoid a
kind of fundamentalism that would lead to the exclusion of other
philosophical currents (beyond those of the South, including those
rooted in European modernity), and mere commentaries on European
contributions. The exclusionary approach is disdainful of dialogue and
fails to have due regard for the best of European modernity. It has to
be noted, however, that the latter conceives of itself as modern but
does not serve the interests of the South as a community of reference;
at the same time, it is disdained by the philosophical community of the
European center for its lack of originality, and at best is perceived as
simply "registering" the latest intellectual productions from
Europe or the U.S., with commentaries which come too late and lack any
real importance either in the South (because of their culturally distant
character) or in the center (because they lack creativity and a vanguard
quality).
Those of us who are able to effectively combine proficiency in our
own regional tradition within the South (which is usually less well
known than that of our local traditions) with the necessary familiarity
with the latest achievements of European or U.S. philosophy, together
with a commitment to shed light on contemporary aspects of the regional
or local reality in the South, will be best positioned to contribute
creatively to the new philosophical reflections which are so necessary.
Contributions along these lines which address and describe relevant,
previously unknown themes, have the potential to spearhead philosophical
thinking that is both innovative and well-founded. The philosophers of
the South are uniquely situated to reflect critically regarding the
ethical, political, anthropological, ontological, and epistemological
dimensions of our realities in the context of examples such as China
(amid its hyper-industrial revolution), India (with its developments in
electronics), Latin America (given the contributions of its political
experiences of transformation in Bolivia, Venezuela, or Brazil), and the
Islamic world (in the wake of the "Arab Spring" or
"Jasmine Revolution"). All of these reflect relevant themes
which the philosophers of the South are ideally positioned to engage as
actors in such settings.
Precision, seriousness, well-founded argumentation, relevance to
one's own reality, beauty in the process of exposition, pedagogical
and explanatory quality, and a sense of conviction as to the positioning
one has elected, are all characteristics which should be reflected in
the contemporary philosophies of the South. In this manner the community
of philosophers of the center will learn about new themes, with new
methods, within the framework of a dialogue enriched by new
participants. Meanwhile, the philosophy of the South will revive the
creativity annihilated at the end of the 15th century, with the
inception of the coloniality of knowledge that extinguished the
philosophies of the South.
10. PREMONITIONS AS TO THE DAWNING OF A PLURIVERSAL TRANS-MODERN
AGE (18)
The decentering of the world-system (which is taking place before
our eyes towards countries with increased political, economic, and
military autonomy, including the emergence of BRICS, (19) among others),
the intensification of economic crises in Europe and Japan, and the
limits confronting U.S. militarism, have laid the foundation for the
following questions: a) What is modernity? b) Was there, is there, and
will there be one or several different modernities? c) Is it possible
for a new age to arise in the future, within the framework of a
different kind of culture that lies beyond modernity and thus might be
described as trans-modern in character? (20) d) And if this new world
age emerges, as Schelling might have imagined, will it be organized
according to the framework of a univocal universality--which assumes the
viability of one culture for humanity as a whole, reflected in one
language and one tradition, with the disappearance of cultures which
have been vanquished, including the negation of the diversity of other
cultures which have existed for millennia--or will it instead be an
analogical pluriverse of cultures flourishing through a process of
intercultural dialogue for centuries among different cultures engaged in
a permanent process of creative cross-fertilization?
Let me respond briefly in the form of short theses intended to
spark future discussions:
In the first place, modernity is not the Enlightenment, and
Kant's explanation of its character ("liberation from a state
of immaturity and self-imposed guilt" (21)) is not sufficient.
Modernity is an age of history inaugurated by Europe thanks to the
discovery and dominion of the Atlantic Ocean (as a new geopolitical
center) which enabled it to expand by sea and constitute commercial,
military, and cultural empires, with Europe as their core. The European
"I" (or ego) constituted other cultures as its colonies,
subjected to its Will to Power, which encompassed nature as an
exploitable set of objects that could serve as a form of mediation in
order to obtain greater quantities of exchange value. This is an age
characterized by huge technological advances, which reflected the
demands of securing advantages among competing sources of capital and by
scientific discoveries and the political organization of states in
systems of representative democracy. It was imposed on other cultures up
until the limits that we are seeing unfold today, which involve a
civilizational crisis revealing the negative effects of its vast scale:
the possibility that life on Earth might be extinguished.
Secondly, in the fullest sense, although there are historical
antecedents--namely, the separation of science from religious faith in
the philosophy of Cordoba reflected in thinkers such as Ibn Rush (often
known by his Latinized name as Averroes); great technological,
agricultural, and industrial discoveries in China; the invention of
modern mathematics and heliocentric astronomy in Baghdad;
etc.--modernity is European, unique, and is being imitated in part in
the process of globalization, which is underway in other regions of the
world. There are not several different modernities, although the extent
and ways in which it is implanted may vary in diverse cultural contexts.
If it was Calvinism which helped shape the initial development of
capitalism (as Max Weber argued), at present it is neo-Confucianism
which inspires the suigeneris versions of capitalism which have arisen
in Southeast Asia and in China itself. This is the same modernity
described above which has been imitated and expanded in certain
respects.
Thirdly, we stand at the threshold of a new age of history given
the exhaustion of the premises upon which modernity is founded. Ours is
not a postmodern situation, but instead a moment characterized by
radical transformations in the very cultural foundations of the modern
ethos. It is upon the basis of these assertions that I therefore propose
that trans-modernity, in the absence of another equivalent term, is the
adequate description for the horizon that is opening up before our eyes.
What is emerging is not a new stage of modernity but rather a new world
age that lies beyond the assumptions of modernity, capitalism,
Eurocentrism, and colonialism. A new age where the conditions necessary
to sustain human life on Earth demand a transformation in our
ontological attitudes regarding nature, work, property, and other
cultures.
Fourth, in the context of trans-modernity, humanity will not be
trapped in a univocal universality limited to a single culture, which
would in turn be imposed to all of the rest in order to extinguish them,
thereby producing a universality which is the fruit of an exclusionary
process of identity. It will instead be a pluriverse where each culture
will be in dialogue with all others from the perspective of a common
"similarity," enabling each to continuously recreate its own
analogical "distinction," and to diffuse itself within a
dialogical, reciprocally creative space. It will be, as I have suggested
here, an age which, as the result of new economic relations, will have
succeeded in overcoming capitalism, given the imperative character of
the demands of the environment and of the conditions necessary to make
life possible for the majority of the Earth's population, which
will have embraced a participatory form of democracy beyond the limits
of liberalism, and which will no longer consent to the perpetuation of a
system based upon the exploitation of those most vulnerable to the
impact of increases in the rate of profit and to the commensurate
increases in the poverty and inequality of citizens throughout the
world.
All of this is a reasonable prognosis which can be argued upon an
empirical basis, and which traces the outline of a future horizon which
will at least attempt to overcome the substantial dominations which can
be detected throughout our historical moment, because without this
attempt, it is impossible to imagine today how we are going to overcome
the inevitable dominations of the future, which will surely emerge
because of the nature of our human condition.
BIBLIOGRAPHY
Collins, Randall. The Sociology of Philosophies. Cambridge, MA:
Belknap/Harvard University Press, 1998.
Dussel, Enrique. "The Anti-Cartesian Meditations."
Poligrafi 41-42 (2006): 5-60. http:// www.enriquedussel.com.
Dussel, Enrique. Politics of Liberation. London: SCM Press, 2011.
Dussel, Enrique. "Transmodernity and Interculturality."
Unpublished paper, 2004. http://www.enriquedussel.com.
Dussel, Enrique, Eduardo Mendieta, and Carmen Bohorquez, eds. El
Pensamiento Filosofico Latinoamericano, del Caribe y "Latino"
(1300-2000): Historia, Corrientes, Temas y Filosofos. Mexico:
CREFAL/Siglo XXI Editores, 2009.
Hinkelammert, Franz. Critica de la Razon Mitica. San Jose, Costa
Rica: DEI, 2009.
Kant, Immanuel. "Beantwortung der Frage: Was ist
Aufklarung?" In Werke, vol. 9, 53-61. Darmstadt: Wiss. Buchges.,
1968. Originally published in Berlinische Monatsschrift (December 1784).
Loewith, Karl. Von Hegel zu Nietzsche. Stuttgart: Kohlhammer, 1964.
Needham, Joseph. Science and Civilisation in China. 7 vols.
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1956-2012.
Enrique Dussel
Universidad Autonoma Metropolitano, Mexico
dussamb@servidor.unam.mx
(1.) The name of a historical epoch that is only valid in the
European context. The Islamic world experienced a stage of urbanized and
mercantile splendor during the same period.
(2.) The second phase of Early Modernity would be characterized by
the hegemony of Holland (from 1630), and its third phase by that of
England (from 1688), which in turn laid the basis for Mature Modernity,
thanks to the Industrial Revolution, which began in China's Yellow
River Valley and flowered definitively in the United Kingdom at the end
of the 18th century.
(3.) See the concept of Christendom (Christlichkeit in German),
that is not Christianity, in the fifth chapter of the second part of
Karl Loewith, Von Hegel zu Nietzsche (Stuttgart: Kohlhammer, 1964); and
also in the fourth chapter of my Politics of Liberation (London: SCM
Press, 2011).
(4.) Which means that the "universality" of these rights
excluded colonial subjects; it was in fact a particularity imposed with
universalist pretensions, or an ideological universality which was
actually particular and exclusionary regarding the colonial sectors of
humanity, which is a theme within the political philosophy of the South
that was not addressed by Hobbes, Locke, or Hume, etc.
(5.) The non-humanity of the human beings of the South or
post-colonial regions of the world continues today. The deaths of the
civilian populations which have been the victims of aggression in Iraq
and Afghanistan count much less than those of the soldiers (boys) who
lose their life waging these wars.
(6.) I repeat: inadvertently. "European," and also male,
white, adult, metropolitan, etc.
(7.) Of course Heidegger seeks to demonstrate that this
"I" is founded upon a "being-in-the-world" which is
always presupposed.
(8.) See my article: "The Anti-Cartesian Meditations,"
Poligrafi 41-42 (2006): 5-60, http:// www.enriquedussel.com, (under
"work" and "philosophical articles").
(9.) Augusto Salazar Bondy, lExisteuna Filosofia en Nuestra
America? (Mexico: Siglo XXI Edi tores, 1969).
(10.) This fallacy encompasses many additional errors: not to
recognize that the other's reality is different from one's
own; therefore, not to know that it is impossible to assume reality as a
given as it is lived in Europe or the U.S., because one is not
existentially, originally part of that other-world (which one might
fictitiously live as if it were one's own, as a colonial person
with a metropolitan soul, a ghost or phantom); to negate the knowledge
of the evolving historical identity of one's own reality and not
differentiate it from that of others; to thus think of that which is
alien falsely as one's own, and therefore to define as philosophy
what is in essence commentary, and not to aspire to create something
different; and in, ethical terms, to be responsible for rendering
invisible, for hiding, for making disappear, or for failing to perceive
what is one's own, etc.
(11.) I should be more specific here: the South which I have been
referring to includes at minimum: a) Latin America (and its indigenous
peoples); b) the Islamic world (from Morocco to Mindanao in the
Philippines); c) Sub-Saharan Bantu Africa and its diaspora; d) India; e)
Southeast Asia (in part Hindustani, such as Burma, Nepal, etc., and also
countries linked to China, such as Korea, Vietnam, etc.); and (f) China.
(12.) See the third section of the first chapter of my book,
Politics of Liberation.
(13.) See Franz Hinkelammert, Critica de la Razon Mitica (San Jose,
Costa Rica: DEI, 2009). The "myth of progress," for example,
is at the foundation of all of modern science, and cannot be proven
empirically; it is in fact a transcendental postulate and supposition
(which is also dangerously false, as Walter Benjamin argued).
(14.) And I say "only recently" advisedly, because since
the beginning of the 21st century, the failure of the U.S. to impose its
military domination throughout the world (as the result of its defeats
in the wars in Iraq and Afghanistan) and the emergence as new global
powers--namely, China (with 1.3 billion inhabitants and an average
growth rate in its production of 9% over the last few years), India,
Russia (in an intensified process of reorganization), and Brazil
(gauging from a distance its implications as a nation of 200 million
inhabitants)--the geopolitics of the world has moved away from a
unipolarity of the North (centered around the U.S., Europe, and Japan,
today in crisis). The philosophy of the South, therefore, includes these
new powers in the South (China and Russia were never colonies, but were
definitely underdeveloped and exploited for a long time), which in turn
define the need for a new nomenclature, since there are new powers
emerging that no longer fit into the category of the North as it was
developed in the 20th century, and the South itself is no longer what it
was in that same century.
(15.) The situation of South America (as differentiated from that
of "Latin" America as a whole) in particular, and that of the
"Arab Spring" or "Jasmine Revolution" are key
indicators of deep processes of political renewal, that also demand
correspondingly new levels of philosophical production.
(16.) Regarding science and technology in China, seeJoseph Needham,
Science and Civilisation in China, 7 vols. (Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press, 1956-2012).
(17.) The most recent World Congress of Philosophy in Seoul, Korea,
organized by FISP included the presentation of the first history of the
philosophy of Korea. In Latin America we have published, as I noted
above, a large-format initial overview of Latin American, Caribbean, and
Latino philosophy from an integral perspective; see Enrique Dussel,
Eduardo Mendieta, and Carmen Boh orquez, eds., El Pensamiento Filosofico
Latinoamericano, del Caribe y "Latino" (1300-2000): Historia,
Corrientes, Temas y Filosofos (Mexico: CREFAL/Siglo XXI Editores, 2009).
There is not a single sentence dedicated to Latin America in the
brilliant book by Randall Collins, The Sociology of Philosophies
(Cambridge, MA: Belknap/ Harvard University Press, 1998), although it
does include a good description of the philosophies of China, India, the
Islamic world, and Bantu Africa.
(18.) Both the concept of "trans-modernity" and that of
"pluriversality" are explained in this last section of the
essay.
(19.) Brasil, India, Rusia, China, and South Africa.
(20.) In my essay "Transmodernity and Interculturality"
(unpublished paper, 2004, http:// www.enriquedussel.com), I explain the
difference between this position and that of those who embrace the
notion of "post-modernity." The prefix "post" refers
to the final critical stage of European modernity, and thus implies a
Eurocentric hypothesis rooted in the Global North. It is a particularism
with an unfounded pretense of universality; the South is not and will
never be "post-modern." "Trans" by contrast has as
its referent a point lying beyond modernity, a different world Age,
which is no longer Eurocentric, and which emerges from the Global South
and includes the Global North and is thus truly planetary in character.
(21.) Immanuel Kant, "Beantwortung der Frage: Was ist
Aufklarung?" (Berlinische Monatsschrift [December 1784]), in Werke,
vol. 9 (Darmstadt: Wiss. Buchges., 1968), 53-61.
Enrique Dussel was born December 24, 1934, in the town of La Paz,
in the region of Mendoza, Argentina. He first came to Mexico in 1975 as
a political exile and is currently a Mexican citizen, Professor in the
Department of Philosophy at the Iztapalapa campus of the Universidad
Autonoma Metropolitana (Autonomous Metropolitan University, UAM) and
also teaches courses at the Universidad Nacional Autonoma de Mexico
(National Autonomous University of Mexico, UNAM). He has an
undergraduate degree in Philosophy (from the Universidad Nacional de
Cuyo/National University of Cuyo in Mendoza, Argentina), a Doctorate
from the Complutense University of Madrid, a Doctorate in History from
the Sorbonne in Paris, and an undergraduate degree in Theology obtained
through studies in Paris and Munster. He has been awarded Doctorates
Honoris Causa from the University of Friburg in Switzerland, the
University of San Andres in Bolivia and the University of Buenos Aires
in Argentina. He is the founder with others of the movement referred to
as the Philosophy of Liberation, and his work is concentrated in the
field of Ethics and Political Philosophy. This paper was presented at
the first South-South Philosophical Dialogue organized by UNESCO in
Marrakech, Morocco, June 2012. It was originally published in Budhi: A
Journal of Ideas and Culture 17.1 (2013): 1-27. We are grateful for
permission by the editors of Budhi to republish it here.