Must development economists watch Hamlet without the prince?
Naqvi, Syed Nawab Haider
..... To be, or not to be: that is the question"
Hamlet.
Development economics, according to the non-believers, has changed
hands in the last 30 years of its existence from the visible hand of the
State to the invisible hand of the market--and, a fortiori, from being
to nothingness. Correspondingly, the vision of an economic universe
beset by all-pervading market failures seems to have been replaced by
one of total government failure. In this revised vision, government
intervention only spoils the utility/profit-maximizing show by giving
rise to various activities of a rent-seeking type [Krueger (1974)]. The
development experience of the last four decades--especially of the
"Gang of Four", i.e., South Korea, Singapore, Taiwan, and Hong
Kong--has been cited to establish the superiority of the market-based
solutions to the dirigiste solutions of the development problem.
Notwithstanding the Hume's Law--which prohibits deducing
'prescriptive' statements from factual statements alone--the
agnostics have used these real-life happenings to prove the central
point that (neo-classical) economists have made all along: optimal
allocative efficiency is (best) guaranteed by following faithfully the
first-best rules of competitive efficiency, which free markets alone are
believed to satisfy. Citing the (glaring) contrast between free markets
and centrally-planned economies, and the recent disavowal of the
socialist economic philosophy by Eastern Europe, Haberler concludes:
"I still maintain my early belief in the validity of classical or
neo-classical theory and in the superiority of relying largely on
competitive markets and private enterprise." [Haberler (1988)]. In
the same vein, the ultra-conservative Economist (London) declares:
"After three decades the experience of these countries [shows that]
history chooses the invisible hand." [Crook (1989)].
Thus, it is claimed that development economics, born from the rib
of an interventionist government, has met its nemesis. What should then
be done? The standard prescription is: "Get the prices right"
and leave the rest to the safe hands of the atomistic utility/profit-maximizing invisible agents in the wonderland of pure and
perfect competition. And in this enthusiasm for the "right"
things, externalities of various kinds as well as considerations of
income distribution and unemployment are relegated to the background.
In my previous Addresses to the Society, especially in "A Tale
of Two Hands" (1986) and "For Morality's Sake!"
(1989), I have questioned the validity of these arguments. I have shown
that development economics as a discipline exists, though not
necessarily in splendid isolation; that its worldview of a "mixed
economy", run with the help of both the "visible" and the
"invisible" hands is essentially correct; and that its concern
with essentially macro problems of growth as well as equity is
well-placed. While considerations of (static) efficiency invite markets,
where they exist, the dictates of equity require government
intervention, especially where markets do not exist due to external
economies of various kinds. The latter is the case when institutional
constraints--those set by the locus of asset ownership and by the mode
of property relations--must be removed as a necessary condition to
achieve efficiency in resource allocation and to ensure equity.
In the present Address, I restate some of these arguments somewhat
differently in the light of the recent literature on the subject. I
maintain that the basic flaw in the anti-dirigiste argument flows from
the error of contraposing the government and the market as rivals, and
from considering the choice between the two as mutually exclusive. Such
contraposition may be justifiable in communist countries; but it does
not make much sense in developing countries. This is because a mixed
economy has been accepted from the very first 'day' as the
basic model. I show that the cult of unqualified anti-dirigisme, and the
expiatory mad rush to privatize, is ill-founded both in theory and
practice; and that its frequent appeals to the first-best rules of
market efficiency are out of place--and nothing more than what Findlay
(1988) calls "Pareto-optimality by inadvertence". But
efficiency-oriented Pareto-optimality, which has been shown to be linked
with competitive equilibrium, is not suitable at all to model
'reality' in the developing countries. This is because
considerations of growth and equity--indeed, of equality--are
inextricably bound with each other. To recognize this 'fact'
we pay attention not only to individual preferences but also to the
significant differences between these preferences; the intensity of
these preferences should be 'weighed', and interpersonal
comparisons between them should be made, too. In other words,
development economics should not fight shy of making normative
judgements.
But, first, let me look closely at the claim that the alleged
victory of the market over the government denotes the demise of
development economics, which is assumed to be incurably dirigiste in
disposition.
THE STUFF THAT DREAMS ARE MADE ON
The "State of Bliss"
The essence of the anti-dirigiste cure-all prescribed for
development economists is: "get the prices right"; and to do
that, unshackle the market forces by 'privatizing'
across-the-board. This is required to satisfy the first-best rules of
competitive efficiency, which entails ensuring the postulated equality
between the domestic marginal substitution (in consumption) and the
domestic marginal rate of transformation (in production), and that
between the domestic rate of transformation and the foreign rate of
transformation (through foreign trade), which in turn is equated to
international prices. The implication is that competitive equilibrium
will lead to an efficient allocation of domestic resources if the
solution is secured through the market rather than through state
intervention. Another remarkable result cited in support of such a
market-oriented efficient solution of the resource allocation problem is
that--by the Fundamental Theorem of Welfare Economics--"every
competitive equilibrium is Pareto-optimal, and every Pareto-optimal
state is characterized by a competitive equilibrium". This two-way
relationship between Pareto-optimality and competitive equilibrium rests
on the "duality" property of an efficient resource allocation
problem. Every maximum welfare problem has embedded in it a set of
(shadow) prices, which correspond to optimal input prices--wages, rents,
interest rates. But for that to happen, a perfect, self-policing
competition must obtain in all markets. This, in turn, requires that
(contingent) markets exist for all situations, and that these markets
'clear' at all times. The textbook world (of dreams) where all
this happens is referred to as the "state of bliss",
resplendent with all-round convexities and multi-market Walrasian
equilibria.
The Privatization Alchemy
Does it follow, then, that a policy of "getting the (relative)
prices right" will actually lead a real-world economy--made
supplicant to price signals by large-scale privatization--to the state
of bliss promised in the standard economics textbooks? As unbelievable
as such a claim may seem, this is exactly what some economists seriously
believe should, in fact, be the case. For instance, Lal (1983) thinks:
"The Utopian theoretical construct of perfect competition then
becomes relevant as a reference point by which to judge the health of an
economy, as well as the remedies suggested for its amelioration."
The proponents of the neo-classical political economy school consider
the Pareto-optimal state as a counterfactual, distortion-free state, by
reference to which the policy-induced (potential) waste of real
resources can be measured. Furthermore, the many generalizations drawn
from the development experience of the "Gang of Four" in
support of the superiority of the first-best rules also belong to this
category of arguments.
I think that this line of thinking is in error--theoretically and
empirically.
(i) It is generally forgotten that the existence of
Pareto-efficient configuration of product and input prices tells only
about rules which "sustain" such a bliss configuration, which
is already in place. As Bator (1958) points out, in the bliss situation
"we shall be concerned only with the prior problem whether a
price-market system which finds itself at the maximum welfare point will
or will not remain there". It does not tell us how to get there.
Thus, whether or not a policy of "getting the prices right"
will in fact land an economy with "wrong" prices in a state of
bliss with the "right" prices is not a sure thing--at least,
not theoretically.
(ii) Another point is whether obedience to the rules of allocative
efficiency must of necessity mean a shift from the government to the
free markets run by the invisible hand. The answer is: not necessarily.
This is because, again to quote Bator (1958), "the necessary
conditions of decentralized price-profit calculations [hold] both in
'laissez faire' and in a socialist setting of Lange-Lerner
civil servants". Also, the situations of failure of the basic
duality property--i.e., "failure by existence", "failure
by signal", "failure of incentive", and "failure by
enforcement"--apply as much to "laissez faire markets with
genuine profit and satisfaction seekers" as to the
"decentralized efficiency of a Lange-Lerner type of [socialist]
organization scheme". The only difference is that the conditions
relating to a "self-policing" competitive economy,
characterized by very many producers in every market, will not be
relevant in a socialist (market) economy. Whether the Pareto-optimal
solution, which is supposed to maximize social welfare, is attained by
the 'invisible hand' or calculated electronically by a
computer does not matter at this level of discussion. All that is
asserted is that "an appropriate price system is associated with an
efficient state", Malinvaud (1969); and that these prices are,
strictly speaking, Lagrangean multipliers, which are formally equated
with (shadow) profits, wages and rents. However, note that these shadow
prices may or may not equal market prices. Indeed, in all cases where
external economies obtain, this equality will not hold--not even
theoretically.
Thus the case for a unidirectional (quick) march from the
government to the market cannot rest only on the basis of the rules of
allocative efficiency, which are essentially neutral with respect to the
institutional or political nature of the economic set-up postulated.
On First-best Dreams in NICs
South Korea has been cited--e.g., by Little (1982)--as a showcase
of a state run according to the (Pareto-optimal) efficiency rules, and
as one which because of that has made it to the top. But many competent
observers--e.g., Jones and Sakong 0980) and Pack and Westphal (1986)--of
the South Korean miracle plead innocence of their Paretian proclivities.
Findlay (1988) points out that "the experience of all NICs has been
marked not only by a strong reliance on world market forces, but also by
very far-reaching and pervasive intervention and control in all segments
of the economy". Even the export-bias displayed by South Korea (and
also by Brazil) can hardly be cited as a model of liberalism; instead,
the practice of dumping through market segmentation--by making the
domestic consumer pay significantly more than what the foreign consumer
pays for the same product--is more an example of mercantilism than of
trade liberalism. As for the argument that this latter-day strong export
bias in some sense may have cancelled the early equally strong
import-substitution bias, thus creating conditions approaching the
first-best state of bliss promised by Pareto-optimality, is really
stretching Vilfredo Pareto's meaning a little too far. According to
Bardhan (1988), "it is by now well-known that the favourite
neo-classical showcase of South Korea is not predominantly one of market
liberalism but of aggressive and judiciously selective state
intervention. The Korean state has heavily used the illiberal compliance
mechanisms of selective command and administrative discretion,
restricting imports for industrial promotion, disciplining the private
sector through control over domestic credit and foreign exchange and
underwriting of foreign borrowing, and public enterprises leading the
way in many areas." In other words, South Korea, like other
developing countries (e.g., Pakistan, India), has rebelled against the
first-best rules of market efficiency (and Pareto-optimality) in every
possible way, with state intervention being used in its qualitative as
well as quantitative manifestations. Of course, one could still persist
with the anti-dirigiste thesis and maintain that "it is not
outlandish to believe that South Korea, especially, would have done even
better if its government had intervened less ..." [Crook (1989)].
But this is more an assertion of faith, based on a metaphysical belief
in the superiority of free markets, rather than a scientific statement.
The falsity of making generalizations about the benefits of
privatization from the South Korean case and those of the others in the
NICs group--even assuming that this is what the NICs have actually
done--becomes obvious by considering the opposite case, which pushed
privatization to its limits but has not done very well economically,
namely the case of Chile. Yotopoulos (1989) has observed that
privatization, especially of capital markets, has not led to higher
levels of savings and investment. Indeed, gross fixed capital investment
during 1974-82 was only 15 percent of GDP as compared with 21 percent of
GDP during the 1960s, when the privatization fever had not yet taken
hold of Chile. The so-called democratization of the ownership of
national assets--by making ownership more broad-based--also did not come
about. Indeed, the concentration of economic power in major banking
groups increased. To add insult to injury, industrial efficiency also
did not improve. Indeed, industrial profitability declined during the
period of the privatization ferment.
THE WORLD THAT NEVER WAS
Do Markets Always Deliver?
As noted above, a regime of competitive efficiency implies a set of
shadow prices--which have all the analytical characteristics of profits,
wages, and rents. If these prices are set equal to each factor's
marginal (revenue) product, then by the Euler's Theorem total
output will be exactly apportioned among the factors of production--in
cases where the production function is linear and homogeneous. As no
(Marxian) surplus output is left over, no exploitation of labour (or
capital) is ever possible--mathematically, that is. Also, as labour
markets eventually clear, no possibility of (involuntary) unemployment
emerges when bliss configurations of input and output (shadow) prices
prevail.
Another related train of thought is as follows: the fundamental
theorem of welfare economics asserts not only that every perfectly
competitive equilibrium is Pareto-optimal, but also that, for some
initial distribution of endowments, every Pareto-optimal state is also a
perfectly competitive equilibrium. The second part of the theorem is
important: does the market ensure that the initial distribution of
endowments among the economic agents is equitable? And how does it do
it, if at all it does it? The neo-classical answer is that if lump-sum,
or some other nondistortionary, transfers could be made by the gainers
to the losers from a change, and if still there is some leftover, then
the change in question is unequivocally efficient; and, even though it
is not always explicitly asserted, such a state is by the same token
regarded as equitable.
Another assurance about the alleged equity of the state of bliss
comes from economists like Coase (1960), Buchanan and Stubblebine
(1962), and others, who show that the market fails to (re)distribute
property rights not because of some inherent defect of the market
mechanism, but because such rights are not adequately defined. Hence, it
is shown that, in a game-theoretic framework, the outcome of a
bargaining process about property rights will be Pareto-optimal--and
efficient--if property rights are properly defined. The Pareto-optimal
situation, according to this line of thinking, will be attained by
moving on to a new "contract curve" through bilateral trading
between parties.
Let us examine these arguments. First, as to the Hicksian costless
lump-sum 'payments' by potential gainers to potential losers
from a change, it may be noted that such lump-sum transfers that
'could be made' are never in fact made--in the best tradition
of welfare economics! But this is neither here nor there. If the welfare
of the losers from the change is to be raised actually, then such
transfers should actually be made.
Second, it has been shown--e.g., Bowles (1985)--that market
equilibrium is characterized by (involuntary) unemployment because the
wage rate actually paid by the employer exceeds the market-clearing
wage. This may happen in the rural areas to avoid labour shortages in
the peak season [Bardhan (1988)], and in the urban areas to economise on-the-job training costs [Shapiro and Stiglitz 0984)]. Malinvaud (1984)
shows that most observed unemployment is of the involuntary
(disequilibrium) variety, mainly because of the non-existence of a
market-clearing wage rate. He, therefore, concludes that, in general,
"'permanent market clearing is an untenable hypothesis".
Also, in the Harris-Todaro model, the equality of (expected) wages fails
to clear the (urban) labour market, so that equilibrium in a segmented
labour market coexists with urban unemployment, which is fed by
continuing rural-urban migrations [Khan (1987)].
Third, for market efficiency to lead to an equitable redistribution
of the existing legally sanctioned private property rights, the
transaction costs are assumed to be zero. But, this assumption will
seldom be met; and, with positive transaction costs, the familiar
externality scenario--of a divergence between private and social
benefits--will arise, which the market will fail to cure. [Furubotn and
Pejovich (1972)]. But a more fundamental point is that in the
Cease-Buchanan type of solution (1960 and 1962, respectively), it is
essential that each individual makes available information about his
initial endowments to provide a basis for choice among various
Pareto-optimum states--to choose the "optimum optimorum". But
such information is hardly ever truthfully revealed, without violating
the ground-rules of a decentralized regime of free markets. One of these
ground rules is that: the utility (or the production) functions of the
individuals are not known to each other; and that there is no mechanism
available to the faceless market to make any individual reveal
information about his utility (production) functions to another
individual. That being the case, Arrow (1979) shows that "a
procedure which would achieve a Pareto-efficient allocation if each
agent knew the other's utility function will have a positive
probability of falling short of efficiency if this knowledge is
absent": And since such knowledge is indeed absent, it follows that
a Pareto-efficient solution secured through the bargaining process will
not necessarily be efficient!
This last result is also relevant for examining the question of
private property rights--whether market processes will lead to an
equitable distribution of (initial) property rights. Arrow (1979) shows
that such an outcome depends crucially on the (unstated) assumption that
players in a cooperative game "know every other player's
pay-off (utility, profit, whatever) as a function of the strategies
played". But, as shown above, the existence of such knowledge runs
contrary to the rules of the competitive markets.
Therefore, it follows that the state of bliss of the economics
textbook may not even be approximated, let alone actually achieved, in
the real world--for more than one reason: that the lump-sum transfers
from the gainers to the losers from a change are not actually made that
(involuntary) unemployment coexists with market equilibrium; and that an
equitable redistribution of property and asset holdings cannot be
brought about by the market.
Is Government Born to Fail?
In direct contrast to the assertions of market failure that Pigou
and Marshall first made, of late there have been statements about
(innate) government failure. The new-fangled "neo-classical
political economy" asserts that all-pervading government
intervention in economic processes has led to the creation of
rent-seeking activity Krueger (1974), and to unproductive profit-seeking
(DUP)activities Bhagwati (1984), thereby leading to a wastage of real
resources. Brock and Magee (1984) have conjured up an (inefficient)
"Invisible Foot" which tramples all over the (efficient)
'Invisible Hand'. This odd creature is another name for
government, which is seen as preventing the forces of free competition
from maximizing social welfare through the (unproductive) activities of
the profit-seekers--the 'profits', i.e., rents, which can be
eliminated by restoring the world to the joys of perfect competition.
According to this line of thought, since market processes are
assumed to be costless in terms of providing the necessary information
for making production decisions, a shift from the market to the
government imposes an avoidable deadweight loss on the economy. But this
point is not really worth much; because, as North (1984) points out,
"there is no meaningful standard of Pareto-efficiency possible,
since one cannot specify a least-cost structure of government for any
given level of output". Furthermore, such arguments also implicitly
equate competitive efficiency (and Pareto-optimality) with efficiency of
(private) markets in the real world; but, as I noted above, this
position is hard to defend. This is especially so because the
information provided by the market is also costly.
Becker (1983) believes that the government probably can help
achieve the social optimum but it would not do, because governments are
representatives of vested interests, whose interests they serve. But
this may be too narrow and cynical a view of governments. For
notwithstanding their penchant for underhand politicking, governments do
have a "conception of national interest" [Miliband (1983)].
Furthermore, such cynical neo-classical views of state do not explain
how different interventionist states over time become development states
in some cases though not in others. The explanation seems to lie in the
ability of the development states to insulate economic management from
wasteful rent-seeking activities. Even in cases where such insulation is
not achieved, it will be naive to suggest that leaving it to the market
will solve all problems; because, as Bardhan (1988) notes, "the
very reasons why insulation is infeasible are often also the ones which
will make first-best policies inoperative, and in the absence of
lump-sum redistribution, a policy of relative inaction may be
distributionally unacceptable".
The fact of the matter is that inherent (generalized) government
failure cannot be asserted in the same sense as the Marshal-Pigou type
of(selective)market failure, partly because government policies, for
better or worse, set the parameters within which the market
functions--efficiently, perhaps. There is always room for improvement
here, and all such avenues should be exhausted. But if government will
always fail to be efficient, no matter what, then there is no guarantee
that the markets will also not fail, no matter what. The
utility-maximizing calculus, based only on the consumption of the
(private) goods owned by the individual, cannot take him too far without
the availability of public goods, and without the constitutional
guarantees of the free consumption of the private goods, both of which
are provided by the state. At any rate, the process of growth, and the
attendant (painful) structural adjustment required for this process to
continue unhindered, cannot be propelled by the
utility/profit-maximizing economic agents alone. A sovereign state must
initiate "policy action and institutions are required [to minimize]
the costs of, and resistance to, the structural shifts implicit in, and
required for, a high rate of growth". [Kuznets (1971)].
THE PASSION CALLED PARETO-OPTIMALITY
As noted above, in the anti-dirigiste attacks made by the agnostics
on development economics, a reference is always made to
Pareto-optimality, which says that as between two alternative social
states x and y, if at least one person strictly prefers x to y, and for
every individual x is at least as good as y, then x is Pareto-superior
to y, and the society in such a case should also prefer x to y. (In its
weaker form, the Pareto-optimal rule says that if every individual
strictly prefers x to y, then the society should also prefer x toy.) In
simpler words, a social state qualifies as Pareto-optimal if in case of
a departure from such a state not everyone can be made better off, so
that the utility of an individual (say, A) cannot be raised without
lowering the utility of some other individual (say, B).
In recommending free markets for developing economies--and
development economics--to achieve efficiency (and growth), the
neo-classical advice is for the rational individuals and for the society
to go where the Pareto-optimality beckons them to go. Observance of this
rule is 'desirable' because it is allegedly 'fair':
since it reflects unanimity--i.e., the rule requires that preferences
held universally in a society should be reflected in any scheme of
social judgement. It is also liberal, because it preserves liberty,
which is the basic value to be cherished by all civilized societies.
Thus the passion for Pareto-optimality is not only rational, but it is
also the only civilized thing to do. Let us examine these claims a
little more carefully.
The Chinks in the Paretian Armour
Does Pareto-optimality preserve individual liberty? Believe it or
not, the answer is firmly in the negative! Sen (1970)shows the
incompatibility of the Pareto principle, both in its strong and weak
forms, with even a rudimentary kind of individual liberty. Assuming an
"unrestricted domain" (U), Pareto-optimality (P), and
"Liberalism" (L), Sen demonstrates that "there is no
social decision function that can simultaneously satisfy U, P, and
L". Here liberalism--or more accurately, libertarianism--is defined
in a very elementary sense of recognizing each individual's
privilege to have a minimum of what Hayek (1960) calls every
individual's "protected sphere". In other words, each
individual should have the freedom to make "at least one social
choice, for example, having his own walls painted pink rather than
white, other things remaining the same for him and the rest of the
society". The implication of this Impossibility Theorem, which
modifies the celebrated Arrow's Impossibility Theorem, is quite
disturbing: it shows that Pareto-optimality, given the assumption
U--i.e., every logically possible set of individual ordering is included
in the domain of the collective choice rule--cannot be combined with
even a minimum dose of liberalism. Hence, if Pareto-optimality is
followed to its logical (bitter) end, then "society cannot let more
than one individual be free to read what they like, sleep the way they
prefer, dress as they care to, etc., irrespective of the preferences of
others in the community". Surely, these consequences are "most
illiberal". Sen warns: "if someone takes the Pareto principle
seriously, as economists seem to do, then he has to face the problem of
consistency in cherishing liberal values, even very mild ones." It
may seem, therefore, that even to be able to breathe freely one may have
no option but to free himself from the smothering embrace of
Pareto-optimality!
Is the Pareto-optimality rule 'fair'? Alas, the answer is
again in the negative; and for the following reasons:
(a) The Pareto-optimality rule is distributionally neutral. Before
going any further, let us understand clearly the meaning of
"neutrality". Suppose there are two states x and y. The
neutrality property demands that if (x, y) is replaced by (a, b) in
everyone's preference ordering, then we must do the same in social
ordering as well. In other words, for making a social choice it does not
matter what the nature of x, y, a, b is; all that matters is the
existence of individual preferences over these states. The problem is
posed in the following manner: Suppose x = equal division of cake, and y
= nothing for person 1 and equal division for persons 2 and 3. According
to the neutrality property, it does not matter if x, y are replaced by
a, b. Let a = nothing for 2 and 3 and all for 1; and b =equal division.
Neutrality demands that x is socially preferred toy, if and only if a is
socially preferred to b. In other words, from the society's point
of view, the equal and the extremely unequal outcomes are equally
preferable! As Sen (1985) observes, "once we have got to neutrality
in this format, there is no real chance any more of making judgements
concerning income distribution". Thus a society rolling in the
luxury of a Pareto-optimal state may still be perfectly abominable.
(b) The Pareto-optimal rule is blind to whether a person is rich or
poor. This follows from the utilitarian (indeed, welfarist) character of
Pareto-optimality. As is well-known, Pareto-optimality--indeed, (new)
Welfare Economics--regards social welfare as an increasing function of
personal utility levels alone, denying admission rights once and for all
to any type of non-utility information; that individual utilities are
non-comparable; and that individual utilities are ranked ordinally, not
cardinally. But these very characteristics incapacitate Pareto-optimality to differentiate the rich from the poor, even in broad
daylight. To see this clearly, I can do no better than quote from Sen
(1979).
"Can we identify the rich through the observation that they
have more utility than the poor? Not in the Arrow framework, since
interpersonal comparisons are not admitted. Perhaps as those with a
lower marginal utility of income? No, of course not, since that will go
against both non-comparability and ordinalism. Can we then distinguish
the rich as those who happen to have more income, or more consumer goods (nothing about utility need be said), and bring this recognition to bear
in social judgements? No, not that either, since this will go against
welfarism (and against strict ranking-welfarism), since this
discrimination has to be based on nonutility information."
It follows from (a), Co), and (c)above that the Pareto-optimality
rule excludes economists, and especially development economists, from
paying any attention whatsoever to problems of liberty, income equality,
and poverty--perhaps to let them specialize completely on efficiency!
But if, according to Arthur Lewis (1984), development economics is a
study of the economic structure and behaviour of poor countries, then to
follow Pareto-optimality alone in making collective choice is indeed a
prescription for social disaster.
ENTER
THE PRINCE!
Another characteristic of Pareto-optimality is its alleged
"value-free" character, in line with the stand taken by
(neo-classical) economists against relying on normative judgements for
making social decisions. [Robbins (1932)]. But is this so? Insofar as
Pareto-optimality relies on unanimity about certain value
judgements--e.g., not disturbing the status quo with respect to income
distribution--this state of affairs is by no means without a value
judgement: it is certainly not value-free. Be that as it may; the fact
is that such a stance disqualifies Pareto-optimality as the bedrock of
development economics, which aims explicitly at socio-economic
change--indeed, a structural transformation of poor societies into
well-to-do societies.
How Equal is Equality?
In the poor countries a central value judgement, indeed an ethical
judgement, must be made: it is to push developing economies towards
greater equality of distribution of income and wealth between different
classes of the society--especially between the rich and the poor. An
explicit commitment to some such ideal is essential to ensure a
(voluntary) universal participation by all classes of society in the
process of economic development, so that both the costs and the benefits
of social change are equitably shared. If Pareto-optimality cannot see
the difference between the rich and the poor, so much the worse for it.
We then need some other social choice rule that does 'see'
this vital difference.
Let it be noted that equality between the rich and the poor does
not mean complete equality. Indeed, no one, including Karl Marx, has
ever meant this. All that equality is meant to imply is that economic
processes be directed to minimize, not necessarily to eliminate, the
inter-class distributional differences as far as it is economically and
socially permissible. A relevant consideration in this context is the
Rawlsian maxim: "inequalities are arbitrary unless it is reasonable
to expect that they will work out for everyone's advantage, and
provided only the position and offices to which they attach, or from
which they may be gained, are open to all." [Rawls, (1971)].
According to this rule, the creation and the existence of income
inequalities may be ethically justifiable provided only that the basic
institutions of the society are also restructured in such a manner that
the new economic and social possibilities opened up by economic progress
are equally accessible to all classes of the society.
The goal of equality, in fact, has been pursued by economists
explicitly since the days of Jeremy Bentham. But equality itself has
been defined differently by various schools of thought. Sen (1983)
distinguishes four main types of equality: there is the
"utilitarian equality", the "total equality", the
"Rawlsian equality", and the "basic capability
equality". Of these, the first two types of equalities are strictly
for the birds. Utilitarian equality requires the equality of marginal
utility of everyone. But to restrict the equalization process to the
utility space alone is really to prevent it from doing anything
worthwhile. As noted above, if looking at different persons'
marginal utility alone does not let the observer see the difference
between the rich and the poor--mainly because of the exclusion of
interpersonal comparisons--then not much social change can come about by
following this principle. In particular, once we come to the
distribution of utilities, utilitarianism offers no comfort to the poor;
for even the smallest gain in total utility sum would overbalance the
worst type of distributional inequality on this scale. This problem can
be avoided if it is assumed that everyone has the same utility function.
But that is really to trivialize the problem of inequality--which is
marked by the fact that different persons' utility functions are
not the same. Equalization of total utility is a more helpful
guide--particularly, its leximin version, according to which the
goodness of a state is judged by the utility level of the worst-off
individual. But it, too, is unsatisfactory because it, by definition,
ignores the intensity of the person's needs; and it is also
insensitive to the magnitude of the potential utility gains and losses.
The main problem with both these types of equality is their
insistence on using utility information only as an index of individual
and social welfare. This exclusive insistence on utility information,
marginal or total, can lead to a situation in which more income is given
to the less needy, simply because that is the hard-to-please type; and
the poor person, who is easily satisfied even with small mercies, will
have less income! But the most interesting information about a
person's welfare is of the non-utility type--e.g., the possession
of certain types of goods, or the possession of certain capabilities to
do some basic things essential for man's survival. Accordingly, I
shall now discuss the remaining two types of equality which explicitly
use such non-utility information: (i) The Rawlsian equality; and (ii)
Sen's basic capability equality.
(i) Rawlsian Equality: The central thrust of the Rawlsian
conception of equality is its focus on bringing about institutional
changes such as to "make the worst-off best-off'--that is,
such action as would raise the welfare level of the worst-off individual
in the society as far as it is possible to do so. [Rawls (1971)]. This
is the so-called Rawlsian Difference Principle, Rejecting utility as the
basis of individual welfare, Rawls, instead, defines welfare in terms of
a bundle of "primary goods", which are defined as "things
that every rational man is presumed to want". These things include
"rights, liberties and opportunities, income and wealth, and the
social bases of self-respect". Institutional arrangements which
guarantee the access of the worst-off individuals to these primary goods
are both efficient and equal. The Difference Principle is held to be
"just" because it is chosen "fairly" in the
"original position", which denotes (a mental) experiment of
passing through a "veil of ignorance" to make impartial
decisions about the structure of the society. Unlike the utilitarian
principle, Rawls allows interpersonal comparisons to judge the fairness
of the distribution of primary goods among individuals.
There are many problems with this principle of equality also,
especially because the needs (for primary goods) of a disadvantaged
person--say a cripple or a sick person--do not get registered at all in
the Rawlsian calculus; and there are other technical points that need
not be recounted here. But the emphasis of the Rawlsian equality on
institutional change, on the welfare of the least-privileged, on
"justice as fairness", and on the availability of
"primary goods" to all without discrimination of any kind, are
elements which should find an explicit expression in any sensible model
of development economics.
(ii) Basic Capability Equality. Sen (1984) goes a step--beyond the
Rawlsian emphasis on equality with respect to primary goods--towards
"what goods do to human beings". Equality is insisted on with
respect to such capabilities. Shifting attention from goods to
capabilities has the advantage of taking into account explicitly the
differences in people's "needs" and
requirements--something that the Rawlsian and the utilitarian concepts
of equality fail to do. Such differences, arising from the conversion of
goods into capabilities, are allowed in Sen's concept of equality,
as also the differences arising from the nature of different societies.
"The notion of the equality of basic capability is a very general
one, but any applications of it must be culture-dependent, especially in
the weighting of different capabilities."
FROM "NOT TO BE" TO "TO BE"
The observations made so far may be summarized as follows. The
claims made about the demise of development economics are exaggerated,
to say the least. The basis for these claims--namely, an unambiguous
superiority of the market over the government due to the latter's
pervasive failure--is ill-founded in logic because, as Pack and Westphal
(1986) point out, "the factors responsible for a government's
inability to intervene effectively may also preclude its following the
neoclassical prescription". Such claims are also incorrect
factually, because the NICs are no laissez-faire paradises. They are not
what they are because of following the neo-classical first-best road to
economic salvation. Indeed, they are what they are because they used, at
the right time and with speed, both the government and the market to
maximize social welfare--as the government saw it. The a priori reasoning employed to condemn all government intervention as
inefficient--that it entails wastage of real resources when measured
with reference to an imaginary economy run according to the first-best
rules of Pareto-optimality--is, by and large, empty of content. This
reasoning is also at fault because Pareto-optimality, which is seen as
an alter-ego of competitive efficiency, is not always efficient. And it
is certainly not equitable. Thus a scenario of generalized market
success is sheer neoclassical romanticism.
A guide-book up the road to economic progress, which contains
directions only about efficiency and nothing of substance about equity,
cannot be recommended for the development economist. Once the
development process is looked at, a la Rawls, as one that requires a
rearrangement of the basic structure of the society which is
"fair" and "just"--that which focuses on the needs
of the least-privileged in the society--the standard prescription of
"getting the prices right" and then letting nature (market)
take its course will not take us anywhere. Indeed, it may lead to social
anarchy. An exclusive reliance on the market mechanism cannot bring
about a structural transformation--especially in matters of
redistributing private property rights, for the simple reason that it
can neither initiate the growth process nor can it by itself adjust to a
clash of vested interests to create the space, so to speak, for the
post-transformation world. For this a development-oriented state is
required. To ensure growth with equity, development economics should
continue with its perception of a "mixed economy", whereby
both the government and the market are needed to help initiate and
sustain the development process. It follows that the recommendation to
privatize for the sake of privatization is ill-conceived.
The brief survey of the various concepts of equality presented in
the last section underscores four basic points, which are of fundamental
importance for development economics. First, normative judgements are
routinely made when it comes to the problems of personal or social
welfare. Second, these normative judgements are based on an ethical
perception of human beings, who are not only free but are also seen as
free--in being equally entitled to the most extensive basic amenities
and liberties that a society has to offer. Third, there is the emphasis
upon changing the status quo, on doing positive things to change the
basic structure of the society, and on bringing joy to the withered
lives of the countless millions by producing greater equality among
different human beings. Fourth, the emphasis is on justice and fairness
as well as efficiency. It is not one thing to the exclusion of the
other. All these points should be taken care of in our perception of the
process of economic development, which should aim both at growth and
equal distribution of the fruits of economic progress--things that a
blind adherence to the Pareto-optimal rule would not enable us to see,
much less do. Indeed, to be logically consistent and relevant,
development economics must leave the amoral world of
Pareto-optimality--and that of utilitarianism--for one which is
ethically motivated.
The challenge facing development economics is not one of devising
docking strategies to join the mothership--i.e., the neo-classical
economics; it is also not a matter of declaring development economics to
be 'independent' of neo-classical economics. What is required
is to evolve a synthetic view of economic processes requiring both macro
and micro insights, one which is also based on a social choice theory
that is not restricted to Pareto-optimality. Social action should be
made sensitive to the intensity of individual preferences, and not just
to individual preferences; interpersonal comparisons of the welfare
should be allowed to comprehend the differences in the social stations
of different individuals; and due account should be taken of the nature
of the societal structure with reference to the social choices made.
For once, the development economist cannot agree with his
great-grandfather, Alfred Marshall, who condescendingly allowed the
study of the ordinary business of life in the East to be made with the
help of a limited number of concepts. We now know that development
economics is a many-splendoured thing, involving above all a grand
synthesis of economics and ethics. It requires us to do something as
sensible and all-embracing as watching Hamlet, but not without the
Prince.
REFERENCES
Arrow, Kenneth, J. (1979) The Property Rights Doctrine and Demand
Revelation under Incomplete Information. Ch. 2 in Michael J. Boskin
(ed)Economics and Human Welfare. New York: Academic Press Inc. 23-39.
Bardhan, Pranab (1988) Alternative Approaches to Development
Economics. Ch. 3 in Hollis Chenery and T. N. Srinivasan (eds)Handbook of
Development Economics 1. Oxford: North-Holland 39-71.
Bator, Francis M. (1958) The Anatomy of Market Failure. The
Quarterly Journal of Economics 72 : 3 351-379.
Becker, Gary S. (1983) A Theory of Competition among Pressure
Groups for Political Influence. The Quarterly Journal of Economics 97 :
3 371-400.
Bhagwati, J. N., R. A. Brecher, and T. N. Srinivasan (1984) DUP
Activities and Economic Theory. In David C. Collander (ed) Neoclassical
Political Economy. Cambridge: Ballinger Publishing Co. 17-32.
Bowles, S. (1985) The Production Process in a Competitive Economy:
Walrasian, Neo-Hobbesian, and Marxian Models. American Economic'
Review. 71 : 1 16-36.
Brock, William, and Stephen P. Magee (1984) The Invisible Foot and
the Waste of Nations, Redistribution and Economic Growth. Ch. 12 in
David C. Collander (ed) Neoclassical Political Economy. Cambridge:
Ballinger Publishing Co. 177-186.
Buchanan, James, and W. C. Stubblebine (1962) Externality.
Economica 29 371-384.
Coase, R. H. (1960) The Problem of Social Cost. Journal of Law and
Economics 3 1-44.
Crook, Clive (1989) The Third World: Trial and Error; Poor
Man's Burden. The Economist 23-29 September.
Findlay, Ronald (1988) Trade, Development and the State. In G.
Ranis and Paul A. Schultz (eds) The State of Development Economics. New
York: Basil Blackwell. 78-95.
Furubotn, Eirik, and Svetozar Pejovich (1972) Property Rights and
Economic Theory: A Survey of Recent Literature. The Journal of Economic
Literature 10 : 4 1137-1162.
Haberler, Gottfried (1988) International Trade and Economic
Development (with a new Introduction). San Francisco: International
Center for Economic Growth.
Hayek, F. A. (1960) The Constitution of Liberty. London: Routledge
and Kegan Paul.
Jones, L. P., and I. Sakong (1980) Government, Business and
Entrepreneurship in Economic Development: The Korea Case. Cambridge, M
A: Harvard University Press.
Khan, Ali (1987) Harris-Todaro Model. The New Palgrave: A
Dictionary of Economics (2 : E to J). London: Macmillan Press Ltd.
592-594.
Krueger, A. (1974) The Political Economy of the Rent-seeking
Society. American Economic Review 64 : 3 291-303.
Kuznets, S. (1971) Economic Growth of Nations: Total Output and
Production Structure. Cambridge, M A: Harvard University Press.
Lal, Deepak (1983) The Poverty of Development Economics. Great
Britain: The Institute of Economic Affairs.
Lewis, W. Arthur (1984) The State of Development Theory. American
Economic Review 74 : 1 1-10.
Little, I. M. E. (1982) Economic Development: Theory, Policy and
International Relations. New York: Basic Books.
Malinvaud, Edmond (1969) Capital Accumulation and Efficient
Allocation of Resources. (Econometrica, 1953). Reprinted in Kenneth J.
Arrow and T. Scitovsky (eds) Readings in Welfare Economics. London:
George Allen and Unwin 645-681.
Malinvaud, Edmond (1984)Mass Unemployment. New York: Basil
Blackwell.
Miliband, R. (1983) State Power and Class Interests. New Left
Review 138.
Naqvi, Syed Nawab Haider (1986) A Tale of Two Hands. The Pakistan
Development Review (Papers and Proceedings) 25 : 3 225-245.
Naqvi, Syed Nawab Haider (1989) For Morality's Sake! The
Pakistan Development Review (Papers and Proceedings) 27 : 4 357-376.
North, D. (1984) Three Approaches to the Study of Institutions. In
David C. Collander (ed) Neoclassical Political Economy. Cambridge:
Ballinger Publishing Co. 33-40.
Pack, H., and L. E. Westphal (1986) Industrial Strategy and
Technological Change: Theory versus Reality. Journal of Development
Economics 22 : 1 87-128.
Rawls, J. (1971) A Theory of Justice. Cambridge, M A: Harvard
University Press. Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Robbins, L. (1932) An Essay on the Nature and Significance of
Economic Science. London: Macmillan.
Sen, A. K. (1970) The Impossibility of the Paretian Liberal.
Journal of Political Economy 78: 152-157. Reprinted in A. K. Sen (1983)
Choice, Welfare and Measurement. Oxford: Basil Blackwell 285-290.
Sen, A. K. (1979) Personal Utility and Public Judgement. Economic
Journal 89 : 355 537-558.
Sen, A. K. (1983) Equality of What? Ch. 16 in A. K. Sen Choice,
Welfare and Measurement. Oxford: Basil Blackwell 353-369.
Sen, A. K. (1984) Resources, Values and Development. Oxford : Basil
Blackwell.
Sen, A. K. (1985) Review of [Kenneth J.] Arrow's Social Choice
and Justice. Journal of Economic Literature 23 : 4 1764-1776.
Shapiro, C., and J. E. Stiglitz (1984) Equilibrium Unemployment as
a Worker Discipline Device. American Economic Review 74 : 3 433-444.
Yotopoulos, Pan A. (1989) The (Rip) Tide of Privatization: Lessons
from Chile. World Development 17:5 683-702.
SYED NAWAB HAIDER NAQVI, Professor Naqvi is President of the
Pakistan Society of Development Economists and Director, Pakistan
Institute of Development Economics, Islamabad.
This is a revised version of the Presidential Address which
Professor Naqvi delivered at the Sixth Annual General Meeting of the
Pakistan Society of Development Economists. Thanks are due to Prof.
Alamgir Hashmi for making useful editorial changes, and to Mr M. Aslam
for typing the manuscript of the Address.