Monetary neutrality under evolutionary dominance of bounded rationality.
Lima, Gilberto Tadeu ; Silveira, Jaylson Jair
I. INTRODUCTION
A key property of the dynamic relationship between money and output
is that due to price stickiness monetary shocks have persistent,
although not permanent, impacts on the real output (see, e.g.,
Christiano, Eichenbaum, and Evans 1999). The nominal adjustment of the
aggregate price level in response to a monetary shock is, therefore,
temporarily incomplete, and considerable supporting empirical evidence
for price rigidity has been found in several microprice studies (see,
e.g., Nakamura and Steinsson 2013, and Klenow and Malin 2011, for
comprehensive discussions of these studies).
Mankiw and Reis (2002) develop a novel model of temporarily
incomplete nominal adjustment based on the assumption that costly
information disseminates slowly. In each period, a random fraction of
the price setters updates itself on the state of the economy so as to
compute and set the optimal price, while the remaining fraction keeps
setting prices based on outdated information. They admit that
micro-foundations for price stickiness may require a better
understanding of bounded rationality, and that information processing is
more complex than the time-contingent adjustment assumed in their paper.
In fact, as added in Mankiw and Reis (2011), while the cost of acquiring
information may be small, and may even have fallen in this information
age, the costs of absorbing and processing information may be rather
large and actually higher today than those in the past.
This paper contributes to the intuition on price setting under
bounded rationality by developing a model in which the share of firms
that have up-to-date information on relative prices to establish the
optimal price follows evolutionary dynamics (with and without mutation),
and not a random dynamics a la Calvo (1983), as in Mankiw and Reis
(2002), and the related literature. Our aim is to devise evolutionary
game-theoretic dynamics to provide alternative microfoundations for a
temporarily incomplete nominal adjustment following a monetary shock. We
investigate the behavior of the general price level in an economy in
which an individual firm can either pay a cost (featuring a random
component) to update its information set and establish the optimal price
(Nash strategy) or freely use full information from the previous period
and set a one-period lagged optimal price (bounded rationality
strategy). Indeed, detailed empirical studies such as the investigation
for the Euro zone by Alvarez et al. (2006) have found persistent
coexistence of forward looking and backward looking price-setting
behavior, and there is also robust empirical evidence showing persistent
and time-varying heterogeneity both in the frequency and in the extent
of information updating (see, e.g., Branch 2007; Coibion and
Gorodnichenko 2012). We then devise evolutionary game-theoretic
microdynamics in discrete time that, by interacting with the dynamics of
the macroeconomic variables, affects the coevolution of the frequency
distribution of information-updating strategies across firms and the
completeness of the nominal adjustment of the general price level to a
monetary shock.
Our model economy is composed of monopolistically competitive firms
whose individual optimal price depends positively upon the prices set by
others, implying the existence of strategic complementarity. In a given
period, there is a fraction of firms that set prices without perfect
knowledge of the structure of relative prices, and hence of the prices
that other firms will be setting, as they decide not to pay the
information cost involved in knowing it. We refer to these firms as
boundedly rational firms. The remaining fraction is composed of firms
that decide to incur the information-updating cost to obtain that
perfect knowledge, and we follow Droste, Hommes, and Tuinstra (2002) in
referring to them as Nash firms, as they become perfect foresight firms.
Meanwhile, the optimal price is assumed to be given as in Ball and Romer
(1991), varying positively with the actual general price level and
nominal stock of money, which is publicly known. Therefore, drawing
again on Droste, Hommes, and Tuinstra (2002), the price-setting strategy
of Nash firms is conceived of as like a Nash equilibrium in a game
contaminated with boundedly rational firms.
While the distribution of information-updating strategies is
predetermined in a given period, it varies over time according to an
evolutionary dynamics. Firms' choice between the two available
information-updating strategies is based on expected payoffs, with a
loss (having a random component to it) being faced by firms that do not
carry out the updating of the information set required to establish the
optimal price. The flows of firms between the two strategies are driven
by expected payoffs through an evolutionary dynamics (with and without
mutation), and are derived following Weibull (1995) and Samuelson
(1997). This evolutionary approach to information updating is indeed
fitting given the robust empirical evidence that fluctuations in the
degree of (in)attention to new information are persistent and not purely
random (see, e.g., Andrade and Le Bihan 2013). As it turns out in the
model developed herein, in the unique evolutionary equilibrium that
emerges in the long run, and which features either most or all firms
playing the boundedly rational strategy as local attractor, monetary
shocks have nonetheless only temporary real effects. Besides, the extent
of the temporary output response to a monetary shock depends both on the
frequency distribution of information-updating strategies across firms
and on the heterogeneity in the cognitive abilities of the firms playing
a given information-updating strategy.
The remainder of this paper is organized as follows. The next
section presents the motivating issues and briefly discusses some
related literature, while Section III lays out the structure of the
model. Meanwhile, Section IV evaluates the existence and stability of an
evolutionary equilibrium and discusses the corresponding implications
for the response of the general price level and real output to a
monetary shock. A final section with concluding remarks closes this
paper.
II. RELATED LITERATURE AND CONTRIBUTION OF THIS PAPER
Contributions by Sims (1998, 2003) and Mankiw and Reis (2002)
recently revived the interest in the importance of information
imperfections for price and output dynamics, giving rise to a now
voluminous literature (see, e.g., Mankiw and Reis 2011, and Sims 2011,
for surveys of this literature, and Veldkamp 2011, for a book-length
discussion of other recent applications of models with information
frictions). This literature is related one way or another to the early
research on price decisions under imperfect information dating back to
the prominent work of Phelps (1969) and Lucas (1972).
Mankiw and Reis (2011) describe the recent literature as being
split between partial and delayed information models, with some
contributions combining elements of both. Drawing on Sims (1998, 2003),
in partial information models, firms observe economic conditions
continuously but subject to a noise. Following Mankiw and Reis (2002),
meanwhile, delayed information models describe firms as observing
conditions perfectly but subject to a lag, as a result of fixed costs to
information updating. Nonetheless, both families of models assume that
agents form expectations optimally but under some form of incomplete
information. Delayed information models usually assume that only a
proportion of firms have up-to-date information, with the remaining
having old information from previous periods. Meanwhile, partial
information models typically assume that firms observe a noisy signal
with some relative precision. Essentially, both families of models
introduce just one new parameter, measuring either the proportion of
firms with up-to-date information or the relative precision with which a
noisy signal is observed, which can be interpreted as an index of
informational rigidities. While the notion of rational inattention as
originally developed by Sims (1998) has been used to justify the
assumption of partial information, models of rational inattentiveness as
pioneered by Reis (2006) have provided micro-foundations for delayed
information models.
In the delayed information model of Mankiw and Reis (2002), firms
update their information set infrequently, but nonetheless acquire
full-information rational expectations when the update is performed. As
information disseminates slowly, in every period, only a fraction of
firms obtains perfect information concerning all current conditions,
while all other firms continue to set prices using old information.
While the probability of updating information is taken to be exogenously
given in Mankiw and Reis (2002), Reis (2006) considers instead the
endogenous determination of the time interval between information
updates, finding that a time-dependent schedule a la Calvo (1983) is
optimal: the firm rationally chooses to be inattentive to news, only
sporadically updating its information set.
Meanwhile, Sims (1998) argues that continuous-time optimizing
behavior with adjustment costs may sometimes, and under some specific
conditions, approximate well behavior that is actually based on limited
information-processing capacity. In fact, Sims (2003) elaborates on the
intuition about the relevance of information-processing constraints by
showing that a capacity constraint can substitute for adjustment costs
in a dynamic optimization problem. Woodford (2003) builds on Sims'
(1998, 2003) suggestion to model firms as having a limited capacity for
absorbing and processing information. Given that price setters learn
about monetary policy via a limited-information channel, it is as if
they observe monetary policy with a random error and hence have to solve
a signal-extraction problem. As a result, real effects of monetary
policy may be persistent. Mackowiack and Wiederholt (2009) also model
firms as continuously updating their information set but never fully
observing the true state, having to form and update beliefs about the
underlying fundamentals through a signal-extraction problem. Meanwhile,
Woodford (2009) assumes that firms can pay a fixed information cost at
discrete times to perform a price review, and when they do so, they
obtain complete information about the current state of the economy, just
as in delayed information models. The model also assumes that between
these adjustment dates, firms obtain imperfect signals as in partial
information models.
In the model of this paper, just as in the delayed information
model of Mankiw and Reis (2002), in a given period, only a share of
firms have up-to-date information, but this share is not an exogenously
given constant. As in the canonical delayed information model, all
information-updating firms obtain perfect information and hence derive
the same optimal price. However, as we assume that there is
heterogeneity in the cognitive abilities of firms, individual
information-updating costs differ across firms. In fact, it is also
because of the same heterogeneity that firms not paying the
information-updating cost to compute the optimal price have imperfect
perception of the resulting losses. Besides, while Reis (2006) derives
an optimal frequency of information updating for a representative
producer making optimal output and price decisions, we devise
evolutionary microdynamics that interact with the macrodynamics of the
price level and output to explore the coevolution of the frequency
distribution of information-updating strategies across firms and the
adjustment of the general price level to a one-time monetary shock. As
it turns out, we contribute to the research on temporary real effects of
monetary shocks by offering an alternative imperfect information model
based on a novel analytical notion that we refer to as boundedly
rational inattentiveness.
Nonetheless, our contribution differs from Carroll's (2006)
apparently similarly motivated one mostly in that we do not use
epidemiological models of spread of disease to provide a microfoundation
to the assumption of slow dissemination of information adopted in Mankiw
and Reis (2002). Carroll (2006) proposes an approach to expectations
formation where only a small set of agents (professional forecasters)
form their own expectations, which spread through the population via the
news media in a way analogous to the spread of a disease. The paper
provides an epidemiological micro-foundation for a simple, aggregate
expectations model that is mathematically very similar to that proposed
by Mankiw and Reis (2002). Carroll's (2006) baseline model is
indeed mathematically very similar to the Calvo (1983) model in which
firms change their prices with a given probability. While in the model
of Mankiw and Reis (2002), the updating agents construct their own
rational forecast of the future course of the economy, in the Carroll
(2006) model, the updating agents learn about the experts' forecast
from the news media.
Our contribution also differs from Saint-Paul's (2005)
interesting evolutionary microfoundation to nominal adjustment first in
that we do not assume from the outset that there are only imperfectly
rational strategies being played, although we consider only one of these
coexisting with a fully rational one. Second, while in Saint-Paul
(2005), the rational expectations equilibrium is characterized by a
simple pricing rule that firms can easily adopt, although there is no
convergence to that equilibrium for all parameter values, in our model,
an individual firm has to pay an information-updating cost to establish
the optimal price. In our model, however, evolutionary learning dynamics
take the information-updating process to a long-run equilibrium where,
albeit either most or even all firms do not pay the information-updating
cost, the general price level is the symmetric Nash equilibrium price.
Third, in Saint-Paul (2005), firms' payoffs depend on aggregate
demand, their own price, and their neighbor's price; while in our
model, the local interaction coming through the latter is absent, but
individual payoffs feature a random component. Fourth, in both models,
firms drop a rule either because it yields a lower payoff than an
alternative rule or simply because they want to experiment with another
rule; but Saint-Paul (2005) considers a more complex experimentation
process, which even includes the adoption of an entirely new rule.
Our contribution is also related to the model set forth in Sethi
and Franke (1995), in which firms make output decisions in a stochastic
environment (because of shocks to costs of production) featuring
strategic complementarity. While naive firms follow a costless adaptive
rule to form expectations about returns of production projects,
sophisticated firms incur a common (and deterministic) optimization cost
(treated as both fixed and varying with the share of sophisticated
firms) to form rational expectations. The composition of the population
of firms then evolves over time under pressure of differential payoffs,
with sophisticated agents being favored if optimization is cheap or the
stochastic environment highly variable, but naive agents usually
survive. In fact, with positive optimization cost in the special case of
a macroeconomic deterministic environment, sophisticated firms do not
survive in the long run and naive expectations converge to rational
expectations.
Our contribution differs from the interesting one proposed in Sethi
and Franke (1995) in several respects. First, our underlying economic
model is a different one, featuring firms that make interdependent price
and output decisions in a deterministic macroeconomic environment.
However, in our model, firms' individual payoffs have a random
component, a feature that plays an important role both in the
evolutionary dynamics of strategy revision and in the convergence
dynamics of the macroeconomic variables. Second, in our model,
firms' behavior differs regarding whether or not to update the
information set (at a cost) to establish the optimal price. Third,
although we also consider that firms choose to behave as either fully
rational at a cost or boundedly rational at no similar cost, in our
model, the individual cost of full rationality features a random
component (but the average cost of full rationality is fixed) and
boundedly rational firms' adaptive behavior (which yields losses
differing across firms) is faster than that in the model by Sethi and
Franke (1995). In fact, while in the latter, naive firms revise their
expected return by less than the discrepancy between the expected and
the actual return, in our model, boundedly rational firms revise their
price by the full discrepancy between their price and the optimal one,
and therefore set a one-period lagged optimal price. Although the
evolutionary dynamics driving the composition of the population of firms
is to some extent similar in both models, the fact that adopted
strategies are also assumed to be revised every period in both models
implies that the faster adaptive behavior assumed in this paper is more
reasonable.
Fourth, our evolutionary dynamics of strategy revision feature an
asymmetry implied by a key assumption about information possessed by
firms. While a firm that pays the information-updating cost is able to
both establish the optimal price and compute the average payoff of firms
that do not pay such cost, a firm of the latter type has to rely on a
random pairwise matching process to know the payoff of a firm of the
former type. Moreover, in our model, firms' heterogeneous cognitive
abilities, by creating heterogeneity in individual payoffs, have
important implications for the evolutionary dynamics. Fifth, the
evolutionary dynamics set forth herein can operate subject to a
perturbation analogous to mutation in natural environments. As a result,
and in contrast to Sethi and Franke's (1995) special case of a
positive optimization cost in a deterministic macroeconomic context, in
the continuous presence of mutant firms, the boundedly rational strategy
is not the only survivor in the long-run equilibrium (albeit it is the
most played strategy).
This paper is also related to the literature on predictor choice
following the discrete-decision, multinomial logit model elaborated in
Brock and Honimes (1997). It is worth pointing out several similarities
and differences between the two models. First, as in Brock and Flommes
(1997), in the model herein, firms choose a predictor from a set of
alternative predictors whose cost ordering increases in a
predictor's precision, while the share of firms in the population
using a certain predictor varies positively with its relative net
benefit. In our model, however, there is heterogeneity in the cognitive
abilities of firms, so that both the individual cost paid to have a
perfect foresight and the individual loss associated with forming
costless adaptive foresight vary across firms. As in Brock and Flommes
(1997), perfect foresight firms also have perfect knowledge about the
frequency distribution of all other foresight strategies. However,
unlike in Brock and Hommes (1997), in our model, the individual (and
hence average) performance of each preditor is not publicly available to
all firms. While firms which pay the cost to have perfect foresight know
the average payoff of the adaptive foresight strategy, and hence know
the relative net benefit of playing the perfect foresight strategy,
firms which play the adaptive foresight strategy have to rely on a
pairwise random matching process to learn the relative net benefit of so
playing. In fact, while the predictor switching mechanism in Brock and
Hommes (1997) is derived from a random utility model under very specific
assumptions about the underlying stochastic process, the strategy
switching in our paper is driven by an asymmetric evolutionary mechanism
(only firms with adaptive foresight rely on pairwise comparisons of
losses) without and with mutation (some firms choose a predictor
refraining from comparing payoffs and rather change predictor at
random). Second, Brock and Hommes (1997) assume that predictors'
costs are exogenously determined, and although we assume that the
average cost of the perfect foresight strategy is exogenously given,
individual costs are assumed to be normally distributed around such
average. However, the main qualitative results found in our paper are
robust to the consideration of the average cost of the perfect foresight
strategy as varying with the frequency distribution of foresight
strategies rather than fixed. Third, in Brock and Hommes (1997), firms
use a discrete choice model to pick a predictor where the deterministic
part of the utility of the predictor is the performance measure. While
the standard discrete choice model features deterministic and random
individual-specific characteristics, in our model, the payoff of
individual firms playing each available foresight strategy features both
a deterministic component and random firm-specific cognitive abilities.
In our model, such a random component does not, therefore, correspond to
random shocks experienced by the firm, but to random firm-specific
cognitive abilities, although in both cases, the random component
influences the payoff of each of the possible choices.
Fourth, as in Brock and Hommes (1997), firms base decisions upon
predictions of future values of endogenous variables whose actual values
are determined by equilibrium equations. In both models, there is a
dynamics across predictor choice which is coupled to the equilibrium
dynamics of the endogenous variables. In the cobweb model in Brock and
Hommes (1997), the predictor choice feeds into the market equilibrium
dynamics, which in turn feeds into predictor choice, whereas in our
model, the predictor choice feeds into the equilibrium dynamics of the
general price level and real output, which in turn feeds into predictor
choice. Fifth, while the selection model in Brock and Hommes (1997), for
a finite intensity of choice (or intensity with which firms react to
increases in relative net benefit) and information cost, yields a
strictly positive share of firms using the strictly dominated perfect
foresight strategy even in the long-run equilibrium, in our model,
without mutation, strictly dominated foresight strategies vanish
asymptotically. In our model, the long-run, evolutionary equilibrium is
characterized either by all firms playing the adaptive foresight
strategy (in the absence of mutation) or by most firms playing such
strategy (in the presence of mutation). In our model, therefore, it
takes an exogenous perturbation in the form of mutation for the perfect
foresight strategy to survive asymptotically, whereas Brock and Hommes
(1997) obtain coexistence of both foresight strategies in the long-run
equilibrium by devising a predictor dynamics whose underlying selection
mechanism is based on a random utility model. When there is mutation,
the long-run equilibrium share of firms playing the perfect foresight
strategy in our model depends, among other parameters, on the
distribution of cognitive abilities across firms, which is random. (1)
III. STRUCTURE OF THE MODEL
Ball and Romer (1991) explore price stickiness arising from
coordination failures (because of strategic complementarities in price
setting) in a monopolistically competitive economy populated by a
continuum of producers. This setting is borrowed from Ball and Romer
(1989), in which there is a finite population of producers. Even though
these two contributions are based on Blanchard and Kiyotaki (1987), they
differ from the latter by abstracting from the labor market (the economy
is populated by "yeoman farmers" who sell differentiated goods
produced with their own labor and purchase the products of all other
farmers). We draw on the model developed in Ball and Romer (1991)
because of not only its focus on the goods market but also its
assumption of a continuum of producers, which is a more convenient
structure for our evolutionary game-theoretic modeling. As we clarify
shortly, however, there are significant differences between our modeling
strategy and that adopted in Ball and Romer (1989, 1991).
As in Ball and Romer (1991), in a given period t. each farmer i
[member of] [0, 1] [subset] R produces [Y.sub.i], units of a
differentiated good i by employing L, units of his own labor. The
respective production function is given by:
(1) [Y.sub.i] = [L.sub.i].
Farmer i sets the unit price [P.sub.i] of his product and sells it
taking other farmers' prices as given, thus obtaining an amount of
nominal income [I.sub.i]. Meanwhile, this nominal income is allocated to
the purchase of a continuum of differentiated goods whose associated
utility is given by the following constant elasticity of substitution
consumption index:
(2) [MATHEMATICAL EXPRESSION NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII],
where [C.sub.ij] stands for farmer z's consumption of the
product of farmer j and [epsilon] > 1 is the elasticity of
substitution between any two goods. As it turns out, farmer z's
utility function is given by:
(3) [U.sub.i] = [C.sub.i] - [[epsilon] - 1/[lambda][epsilon]] -
[L.sub.[lambda].sub.i],
where [lambda] > 1 is a parameter measuring the extent of
increasing marginal disutility of labor, and the coefficient on
[L.sub.[lambda].sub.i] in (3) is chosen for convenience. (2)
Farmer i's decision problem can be solved in two stages. The
first stage consists in computing the consumption basket that maximizes
his consumption index [C.sub.i], taking as given his nominal income, the
price of his product, and the other farmers' prices. The second
stage, in turn, consists in finding the price of product i that
maximizes farmer i's utility and, by extension, gives the
production of good i, given the vector of prices of the other goods.
Therefore, farmer i first solves the following constrained maximization
problem:
(4) [MATHEMATICAL EXPRESSION NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII]
The solution to this constrained maximization problem yields the
following Marshallian demand function for each good j [member of] [0, 1]
[subset] R by farmer i's:
(5) [C.sub.ij] = (P/[[P.sub.j].sup.[epsilon]]) [[I.sup.i]/p],
where P is the general price level given by (3):
(6) [MATHEMATICAL EXPRESSION NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII].
Plugging the Marshallian demand function in
(5) into (2), we obtain the optimal consumption index (indirect
utility function):
(7) [C.sub.i] = [[I.sub.i]/P].
Let us now turn to the second stage of farmer i's decision
problem, which consists in finding the price of product i that maximizes
his utility, given the vector of prices of the other goods. First, let
us compute the aggregate demand for good which is defined by
[MATHEMATICAL EXPRESSION NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII] dj. Using (5) and
(7), aggregate demand for good i can be expressed as follows:
(8) [Y.sup.D.sub.i] = C ([[P.sup.i]/P]).sup.-[epsilon]]).
3. Given that farmer i must spend P to obtain one unit of
[C.sub.i], (Ball and Romer 1989, 510), (2) implies that the minimum
expenditure to obtain C, = 1 is given by the following expenditure
minimization problem:
[MATHEMATICAL EXPRESSION NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII]
In fact, the solution to this problem is the Hicksian demand
function for each good j = 1,2, ..., N, which is given by [MATHEMATICAL
EXPRESSION NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII]. Plugging this Hicksian demand
function into the objective function of the expenditure minimization
problem above, we obtain the expression for the general price level in
(6).
where [MATHEMATICAL EXPRESSION NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII] is
aggregate consumption.
Farmer i's nominal income is given by [I.sub.i] =
[P.sub.i][Y.sub.i]. Assuming equality between supply and demand,
[Y.sub.i], = [Y.sup.D.sub.i], for all goods I [member of] [0,1] [subset]
R, it follows from (7) and (8) that:
(9) Ci = C ([[P.sub.i]/P).sup.1-[epsilon]]).
As in Ball and Romer (1991), money is introduced in the model by
assuming that it is required for transactions, which conveniently allows
taking the nominal money supply, M, as a proxy for the nominal aggregate
demand. Therefore, aggregate nominal spending equals the money stock:
(10) PC = M.
The production function in (1) and the assumption of market
clearing for all goods jointly imply that [L.sub.i], = [Y.sub.i] =
[Y.sup.D.sub.i]. As it turns out, the utility function in (3) can be
expressed as [U.sub.i] = [C.sub.i] - [([epsilon] -
1)/([epsilon][lambda])] [([Y.sup.D.sub.i]).sup.[lambda]]. Plugging (10)
into (9) and (8) and then the resulting expressions into the utility
function just reexpressed, we obtain the maximum utility of farmer i as
a function of the nominal aggregate demand, the price of good i, and the
general price level resulting from the simultaneous decisions of all
farmers (and hence farmer i's relative price, [P.sub.i]/P) (see
Equation (10) in Ball and Romer 1991, 541):
(11) [U.sub.i] = M/P ([P.sub.i]/P).sup.1-[epsilon]] - [[epsilon] -
1/[lambda][epsilon] [([M/P).sup.[lambda]]
(([P.sub.i]/P).sup.[lambda][epsilon]]).
Therefore, farmer i's optimal price is the maximizer of (11),
which is given by:
(12) [P.sup.*.sub.i] = [P.sup.phi][M.sup.1-[phi]],
where [phi] = 1 -([lambda] - 1)/([lambda][epsilon] - [[epsilon] -
1) [member of] (0, 1) [subset] R is a constant denoting the elasticity
of each individual price with respect to the observed general price
level. Therefore, from profit maximization, farmer i chooses a relative
price that varies positively with the real stock of money. The reason is
that an increase in the real stock of money, by increasing aggregate
demand, shifts out the demand faced by farmer i and hence leads him to
increase his relative price.
The symmetric Nash equilibrium of this price-setting game occurs
when [P.sub.i] = P for all i [subset] [0,1][subset] R, in which case it
follows that P = M and Y [equivalent to] C = 1. Unlike in Ball and Romer
(1991), however, in this paper, the general price level is not common
knowledge. More precisely, at each period t e {0, 1, 2, ...}, there is a
fraction [[lambda].sub.t] of the population of firms (as we refer to
farmers from now on) that pay a cost to update its information set and
establish the optimal price, and we refer to them as Nash firms.
Meanwhile, the remaining fraction of firms, 1 - [[lambda].sub.t], set
their price without fully knowing the structure of relative prices, as
they decide not to pay the cost to update the relevant information set
(we refer to these firms as bounded rationality firms). This
heterogeneity in price setting can be alternatively interpreted as a
result of firms having to form expectations about the general price
level. (4) In this alternative interpretation, while Nash firms pay an
information cost to form rational expectations about the general price
level, boundedly rational firms forecast the latter using a non-updated
information set. (5)
Based on the best-reply response in (12), the optimal price
established by Nash firms in a given period t is given by (6):
(13) [P.sub.n,t] = [P.sup.[phi].sub.t][M.sup.1-[phi].sub.t].
Boundedly rational firms, meanwhile, having decided not to pay the
cost to update their information set, establish the following price:
(14) [p.sub.b,t] = [p.sup.[phi].sub.t-1] [M.sup.1-[phi].sub.t]
Therefore, the price set at each period t by Nash firms, [P.sub.n,t], is
the standard optimal price, that is, the optimal price choice given the
current general price level, [P.sub.t]. The price set at each period t
by boundedly rational firms, [P.sub.bt], in turn, is the suboptimal
price formed using the one-period lagged general price level,
[P.sub.t-1]. Note that at each period t, all firms know the current
nominal stock of money, that is, we assume that [M.sub.t] is publicly
known for all t [member of] {0, 1, 2, ...}. The reason for this specific
assumption about the nominal stock of money is our purpose to
investigate the implications of boundedly rational inattentiveness in a
context of strategic complementarity where the optimal price varies
positively with the general price level, which in turn depends on the
frequency distribution of information-updating strategies across firms.
We, therefore, assume that M, is publicly known in order to focus
attention on the interplay between the evolutionary dynamics of the
distribution of information-updating strategies and the adjustment
dynamics of the general price level and real output to a monetary shock.
We approximate the current general price level by the geometric
average between the current prices set by Nash firms and bounded
rationality firms (7):
(15)[MATHEMATICAL EXPRESSION NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII].
Given (13)--(15), we can express the general price level and the
price set by Nash firms as:
(16) [MATHEMATICAL EXPRESSION NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII],
7. As in a given period t there is a fraction X, of Nash firms and
a fraction 1 - X, of bounded rationality firms, Equation (6) can be used
to express the general price level as follows:
[MATHEMATICAL EXPRESSION NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII]
For e sufficiently close to one, which we assume, it follows that
[MATHEMATICAL EXPRESSION NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII]. A similar
approximation is rather assumed in Blanchard and Fischer (1989, section
8.2) in a simplified version of the monopolistically competitive model
set forth in Blanchard and Kiyotaki (1987) then extended to incorporate
staggered price decisions in the spirit of Fischer (1977).
(17) [MATHEMATICAL EXPRESSION NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII],
where [xi][([[lambda].sub.t]) = 1/(1 -[psi] [[lambda].sub.t]). For
a given distribution of information-updating strategies at period t,
that is, for a given [[lambda].sub.t] the price set by each type of firm
and the general price level are determined by (14), (16), and (17).
Hence (17) can be seen as the best-reply function of Nash firms in a
repeated game in which a fraction 1 - [[lambda].sub.t], of bounded
rationality firms contaminates the game (in the sense used by Droste,
Hommes, and Tuinstra 2002, 244) by not updating their information set.
In fact, Nash firms not only best reply to other firms, but also take
into account that other firms do likewise. Therefore, between
themselves, the Nash firms coordinate on a Nash equilibrium.
Firms not setting the optimal price face losses whose average value
at each period t, [L.sub.bt], is given by a quadratic function of the
discrepancy between the price [P.sub.b,t] and the optimal price
[P.sub.n,t]. As shown in Appendix A, this loss function can be obtained
as a second-order Taylor approximation around the point [P.sub.b,t] =
[P.sub.n,t]. Using (14) and (17), the average loss of bounded
rationality firms can then be expressed as follows:
(18) [MATHEMATICAL EXPRESSION NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII],
Appendix A. To facilitate later usage of the average loss given by
(18), it is convenient to reexpress it as a function of [P.sub.t] rather
than [P.sub.t-1]. This can be done by isolating the latter in (16) and
substituting the resulting expression in (18), which yields:
(18a) [MATHEMATICAL EXPRESSION NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII].
We assume that the actual losses of bounded rationality firms are
normally distributed around the average value given by (18a), so that
the loss of the kth boundedly rational firm can be expressed as:
(19) [L.sup.k.sub.b,t] = [L.sub.b] ([[lambda].sub.t], [P.sup.t])+
[[mu].sup.k.sub.t],
where [[mu].sup.k.sub.t] denotes a random variable having a normal
probability distribution with mean zero and variance [[sigma].sup.2],
that is, [[mu].sup.k.sub.t] ~ N (0, [[sigma].sup.2]). This random
variable captures the dispersion in the cognitive abilities of firms
when playing the boundedly rational strategy. These cognitive
idiosyncrasies are assumed to be independent across firms and time, and
from the variables in (18a). (8) Given that E [[mu].sup.k.sub.t]] = 0,
it follows that E [[L.sup.k.sub.b,t] = [L.sub.b] ([lambda].sub.t],
[P.sub.t]) at every t [member of] {0, 1, 2, ...}. Therefore, using (A4)
in Appendix A, the average payoff of the subpopulation of firms adopting
the strategy of not updating the relevant information set (to set the
current optimal price) at period t can be written as E [U.sup.k.sub.b,t]
= [U.sup.k *.sub.b,t] + [L.sub.b] ([[lambda].sub.t], [P.sub.t], where
[MATHEMATICAL EXPRESSION NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII].
Meanwhile, Nash firms, by always setting the current optimal price,
do not face the loss given by (18a), although they face an
information-updating cost. As this perfect foresight requires knowing
the distribution of information-updating strategies in the population of
firms, firms' potentially heterogeneous information-updating
behavior imposes an information cost on the subpopulation of Nash firms.
We suppose that the average value of such information cost associated
with computing the current optimal price is an exogenously given
strictly positive constant, c > 0. As a result, such information cost
can be interpreted as representing the average loss of Nash firms at a
given period t, with the corresponding individual losses being normally
distributed around it. Formally, the loss of the lth Nash firm can then
be expressed as:
(20) [L.sup.l.sub.n,t] = -c + [[mu].sup.l.sub.t].
where [[mu].sup.l.sub.t] if denotes a random variable having a
normal probability distribution with mean zero and variance
[[sigma].sup.2], that is, [[mu].sup.l.sub.t] ~ N (0, [[sigma].sup.2]).
This random variable captures the dispersion in the cognitive abilities
of firms when playing the Nash information-updating strategy.
Analogously to the case where firms are playing the boundedly rational
strategy, these cognitive idiosyncrasies are independent across firms
and time, and from the variables in (18a). (9) As we assume that
[[mu].sup.l.sub.t] N (0, [[sigma].sup.2]), it follows that for any t
[member of] {0, 1, 2, ...}, the expected loss of a (randomly chosen)
firm playing the costly strategy of updating its relevant information
set is given by E [L.sup.l.sub.t] = -c. Using (A4) in Appendix A, the
average payoff of the subpopulation of firms adopting the strategy of
updating the relevant information set (to establish the optimal price)
at period t can, therefore, be written as [MATHEMATICAL EXPRESSION NOT
REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII], where [MATHEMATICAL EXPRESSION NOT REPRODUCIBLE
IN ASCII]
The flows of firms between the two information-updating strategies
depend on the rate of strategy revision per period and the corresponding
choice probabilities (Weibull 1995, 152). We assume that all firms
reevaluate their information-updating strategy in the transition between
any two contiguous periods, so that the rate of strategy revision per
period for all firms is equal to one. However, while the rate of
strategy revision is time dependent, the probability and the rate of
individual information-updating (and hence price change) are state
dependent, as described in what follows.
Let us assume that in every period, each boundedly rational firm
compares its own loss with the loss incurred by a randomly chosen firm.
As the probability that the loss of a boundedly rational firm is
compared with the loss of a Nash firm is then equal to the number
(measure) of boundedly rational firms that can potentially switch to the
Nash strategy at period t + 1 is given by (1 -
[[lambda].sub.t])[[lambda].sub.t].
Now, a k boundedly rational firm randomly comparing its actual
payoff [U.sup.k.sub.b,t] = [U.sup.k *.sub.b,t]
[L.sub.b]([[lambda].sub.t], [P.sub.t]) + [[mu].sup.k.sub.t] with the
payoff of a l Nash firm [U.sup.l.sub.n,t] = [U.sup.l *.sub.n,t] - c +
[[mu].sup.l.sub.t] will switch to the information-updating strategy (and
hence ultimately to the price strategy) of the latter if, and only if,
[U.sup.l.sub.n,t] > [U.sup.k.sub.b,t] As [U.sup.l *.sub.n,t] =
[U.sup.k *.sub.n,t] for any k and l, the inequality [U.sup.l.sub.n,t]
> [U.sup.k.sub.b,t] (will hold if, and only if, [L.sup.k.sub.b,t] =
[L.sub.b] + ([lambda].sub.t], [P.sup.t]) + [[mu].sup.k.sub.b,t] < - c
+ [[mu].sup.l.sub.t] = [L.sup.l.sub.n,t], which is equivalent to
[[mu].sup.k.sub.t] - [[mu].sup.l.sub.t] < - c - [L.sub.b]
([lambda].sub.t], [P.sub.t]). As [[mu].sup.k.sub.t] - [[mu].sup.k.sub.t]
and [[mu].sup.l.sub.t] are independent and identically normally
distributed random variables with zero mean and constant variance, the
random variable [[mu].sup.k.sub.t] - [[mu].sup.l.sub.t] is also normally
distributed with zero mean and constant variance: [[[mu].sup.k.sub.t] -
[[mu].sup.l.sub.t]] ~ N (0, 2 [[sigma].sup.2]). Let G: R [right arrow]
[0,1] [subset] R be the cumulative distribution function of the random
variable [[mu].sup.k.sub.t] - [[mu].sup.l.sub.t]. The probability with
which a k boundedly rational firm will switch to the alternative
information-updating strategy (and hence ultimately to the Nash price
strategy) is then given by G (-c - [L.sub.b] ([[lambda].sub.t],
[P.sub.t])).
Therefore, while the probability with which a boundedly rational
firm becomes a potentially revising firm is given by [[lambda].sub.t]
the probability with which a potentially revising boundedly rational
firm switches to the Nash price strategy is given by
G{-c-[L.sub.b]([lambda].sub.t], [P.sub.t])}. Assuming that these two
events are statistically independent, the product of their respective
probabilities yields the probability with which a boundedly rational
firm becomes a Nash firm, namely, [[lambda].sub.t]G(-c
-[L.sub.b]([[lambda].sub.t], [P.sub.t])). As there are 1 -
[[lambda].sub.t], boundedly rational firms at period t, the expected
number (measure) of boundedly rational firms becoming Nash firm at
period t + 1 is then given by:
(21) (1 - [lambda].sub.t]) ([lambda].sub.t])G (-c - [L.sub.b]
([lambda].sub.t], [P.sub.t])).
Unlike a boundedly rational firm, a Nash firm comes to know (at a
cost) the average loss of the alternative information-updating strategy
at any period t, so that it does not have to rely on a random pairwise
comparison of losses. Consequently, a l Nash firm switches to the
alternative strategy of refraining to pay the information-updating cost
in the next period if, and only if, [L.sup.l.sub.n,t] = -c +
[[mu].sup.l.sub.t] < [L.sub.b] ([[lambda].sub.t], [P.sub.t]), which
is equivalent to [[mu].sup.k.sub.t] < [subset] + [L.sup.b]
([lambda].sub.t], [P.sub.t]. Meanwhile, let F: R [right arrow] [0,1]
[subset] R be the cumulative distribution function of the random
variable [[mu].sup.l.sub.t]). It follows that the probability of a
strategy switch of a l Nash firm is then given by F(c + [L.sub.b]
([[lambda].sub.t], [P.sub.t])). As all Nash firms are potentially
revising players in every period, the number (measure) of Nash firms
that decide not to pay the information-updating cost in the next period
is simply:
(22) [[lambda].sub.t]F (c + [[L.sub.b]([lambda].sub.t],
[[P.sub.t])).
Therefore, note that Nash firms are not intertemporally rational.
(10) In fact, Nash firms will immediately switch to being boundedly
rational in the next period if the average payoffs for playing the
boundedly rational strategy are higher than payoffs for playing the Nash
strategy in the current period. Yet, such strategy choice is not
necessarily intertemporally rational, for in the next period, Nash firms
may perform better than bounded rationality firms. Thus, as regards
strategy choice, Nash firms are also boundedly rational.
The difference between the influx described by (21) and the efflux
described by (22) yields the rate of change of the proportion of Nash
firms in the population between periods t and t + 1:
(23) [[lambda].sub.t+1] - [[lambda].sub.t] = [[lambda].sub.t] [(1 -
[[lambda].sub.t] G (-c - [L.sub.b] ([[lambda].sub.t], [P.sub.t])) - F (c
+ [L.sub.b] ([[lambda].sub.t], [P.sup.t]))].
As Appendix B shows, [[lambda].sub.t+1] [epsilon](0, 1) [subset] R
for all states ([lambda].sub.t], [P.sub.t]) [member of][THETA] =
{[R.sup.2.sub.+]: 0 [less than or equal to] [[lambda].sub.t] < 1,
[P.sup.t] > 0}, vector of parameters (M, c, [sigma]) [epsilon]
[R.sup.3.sub.++] and ([phi] [epsilon] (0,1) [subset] R. The intuition
for why our model is not defined for [lambda] = 1 is that, given the
nature of the information imperfection embedded in it, [lambda] = 1
means that all firms are paying the cost to learn the measure of the
heterogeneity in the choice of information-updating strategy when there
is no such cost to be paid.
To gain in generality, we consider the possibility that the
evolutionary dynamics in (23) operates in the presence of a noise term,
analogous to mutation in natural environments. In a biological setting,
mutation is interpreted literally as consisting of random changes in
genetic codes. In economic settings, as pointed out by Samuelson (1997,
ch. 7), mutation refers to a situation in which a player refrains from
comparing payoffs and changes strategy at random. Therefore, the present
extension features mutation as exogenous noise in the evolutionary
dynamics (23) leading some firms to choose a price setting strategy
(Nash or bounded rationality) at random. This disturbance component is
intended to capture the possibility, as sugested by Kandori, Mailath,
and Rob (1993), either that a firm exits the economy with some (fixed)
probability and is replaced with a new firm who knows nothing about (or
is inexperienced in) the respective decision-making process or that each
firm simply "experiments" occasionally with exogenously fixed
probability.
Drawing on Gale, Binmore, and Samuelson (1995), mutation can be
incorporated into (23) as follows. Let [theta][epsilon] (0,1) [subset] R
be the measure of mutant firms that choose an information-updating
strategy in a given revision period independently of the respective
payoffs. Consequently, there are [theta][[lambda].sub.t], Nash firms and
[theta](1 - [[lambda].sub.t]) bounded rationality firms behaving as
mutants. We assume that mutant firms choose either one or the other of
the two information-updating strategies with equal probability, so that
there are [[lambda].sub.t],(l/2) Nash mutant firms and [theta](1 -
[[lambda].sub.t])(l/2) boundedly rational mutant firms changing
information-updating strategy. The net flow of mutant firms becoming
Nash firms in a given revision period, which can be either positive or
negative, is then the following:
(24) [theta](l - [[lambda].sub.t])1/2 - [theta][[lambda].sub.t] 1/2
= [theta](1/2 - [[lambda].sub.t]).
Following Gale, Binmore, and Samuelson (1995), this perturbation
can be added to the evolutionary dynamics (23) to yield the following
noisy evolutionary dynamics'.
(25) [MATHEMATICAL EXPRESSION NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII],
or, in a compact form,
(25a) [[lambda].sub.t + 1] = [psi] > {[[lambda].sub.t],
[P.sub.t]},
where [MATHEMATICAL EXPRESSION NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII]. As shown
in Appendix B, [[lambda].sub.t+1][epsilon](0,1) [subset] R for all state
([[lambda].sub.t+1], [P.sup.t] [epsilon] [THETA] = {R.sup.2.sub.+] : 0
[less than or equal to] [[lambda].sub.t] < 1, [P.sub.t] > 0},
vector of parameters (M, c, [sigma]) [epsilon] [R.sup.3.sub.++], [psi]
[epsilon](0, 1) [subset] R and [theta] [epsilon] [0, 1) [subset] R.
Meanwhile, we can use (16) and (25a) to obtain the difference
equation associated with the general price level:
(26) = [MATHEMATICAL EXPRESSION NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII].
The state transition of the economy is, therefore, determined by
the system (25a)-(26), whose state space is defined by [THETA] =
{([[lambda].sub.t], [P.sub.t]) [epsilon] [[R.sup.2.sub.+]: 0 [less than
or equal to] [[lambda].sub.t] < 1, [P.sup.t], > 0}.
IV. EXISTENCE AND STABILITY OF AN EVOLUTIONARY EQUILIBRIUM
Throughout the ensuing analysis, we suppose that [M.sup.t] = M >
0 for all t [epsilon] {0,1,2, ...}. In the following proposition, we
establish the existence and uniqueness of an evolutionary equilibrium.
PROPOSITION 1. For a given constant nominal stock of money, the
dynamic system (25a) - (26) has a unique evolutionary equilibrium given
by ([[lambda].sub.*], M) [member of] [THETA], with [[lambda].sub.*]
[member of] (0,1/2) [subset] R if [theta][epsilon] (0,l) [subset] R and
[[lambda].sup.*] = 0 if [theta] = 0.
Proof. See Appendix C.
Note that the general price level in the long-run equilibrium is
the symmetric Nash equilibrium price. This general price level is
nonetheless achieved in a long-run equilibrium configuration in which
the boundedly rational information-updating strategy is played either by
all firms (when mutation is absent) or by the majority of the firms
(when there is mutation).
Now, a question arises regarding whether the evolutionary dynamics
in (25a)-(26) takes the economy to the long-run equilibrium
configuration whose existence is established in Proposition 1. Or, to
phrase it differently, do boundedly rational firms come to learn to play
the Nash strategy without ever having to pay the information-updating
cost? The answer is yes, as formally established in the following
proposition.
PROPOSITION 2. (i) The evolutionary equilibrium ([[lambda].sub.*],
M) [member of] [THETA] of the dynamic system (25a) - (26) is locally
asymptotically stable; (ii) For any initial condition given by
([[lambda].sub.0], [P.sub.0]) [member of] [THETA], the set [MATHEMATICAL
EXPRESSION NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII] is positively invariant; (iii) For
any initial condition given by ([[lambda].sub.0], [P.sub.0]) [epsilon]
[THETA], the general price level converges monotonically toward a given
constant nominal stock of money M; and (iv) If the economy is initially
at any state (0, [P.sup.0]) [member of] [THETA], the proportion of Nash
firms rises. Meanwhile, for any [[lambda].sub.t] sufficiently close to
one, the proportion of Nash firms falls.
Proof. See Appendix D.
Therefore, the bounded rationality information-updating strategy is
either the only or the most played strategy in the long-run equilibrium
despite the asymmetric nature of the evolutionary mechanism of strategy
revision.
In fact, in the long-run equilibrium, the Nash strategy is either
extinct or played by the minority of firms even though all firms playing
it are potentially revising firms at each period, while the probability
that a bounded rationality firm becomes a potentially revising firm at
each period, given by [[lambda].sub.t] < 1 (cf. Appendix B), is
decreasing in the proportion of bounded rationality firms. As noted
earlier, given the nature of the information imperfection embedded in
our model, X - 1 is not admissible because it means that all firms are
paying the cost to learn the measure of a heterogeneity that does not
exist. Meanwhile, when there is no mutation, X -- 0 is an equilibrium
because it means that no firm is paying the cost of an inexistent
heterogeneity, and when there is mutation, X* e [0,1/2) is an
equilibrium because there is a heterogeneity cost to be paid.
Furthermore, it is shown in Appendix E that, when there is
mutation, so that the two information-updating strategies survive in the
evolutionary equilibrium (yet the boundedly rational strategy
predominates), such long-run equilibrium heterogeneity varies expectedly
with some parameters. Intuitively, the long-run equilibrium proportion
of firms playing the Nash strategy varies negatively with the average
information-updating cost (see Equation (A27)) and positively with the
rate of mutation (see Equation (A26), and recall that mutant firms
choose either one or the other of the two information-updating
strategies with equal probability). Meanwhile, the long-run equilibrium
proportion of firms that play the bounded rationality strategy varies
negatively with the standard deviation of the cognitive abilities of
firms. To grasp the intuition for this result, recall that the
evolutionary mechanism of strategy revision is asymmetric (bounded
rationality firms have to rely on random pairwise comparisons of losses,
while Nash firms do not). Hence, a more dispersed distribution of
cognitive abilities across firms, with everything else constant,
including a strictly positive mutation rate (recall again that mutant
firms select one or the other of the two available strategies with equal
probability), lowers the probability with which a firm playing the
bounded rationality strategy switches to the Nash strategy, which is
given by G(x) in (21). Interestingly, then, when there is mutation, the
rate of survival of the Nash information-updating strategy in the
evolutionary equilibrium varies positively with the dispersion in the
cognitive abilities of firms.
Hence, while the model in Brock and Homines (1997) can exhibit
local instability of the long-run equilibrium and complicated global
equilibrium dynamics, in our model (with and without mutation), the
long-run, evolutionary equilibrium is unique and locally stable. In a
binary prediction choice setting, Brock and Hommes (1997) show that a
rational choice between a cheap destabilizing (adaptive foresight)
predictor and a costly (perfect foresight) stabilizing one does lead to
the existence of a very complicated dynamics when the intensity of
choice to switch predictors is high. In other words, such a model shows
that with information costs it may be rational for firms to select
methods other than perfect foresight, with the conflict between cheap
free riding and costly sophisticated prediction being a potential source
of instability and complicated global dynamics. In our model, meanwhile,
the conflict between free riding and costly sophisticated prediction is
rather an actual source of stability even if there is mutation, so that
the assertion by Brock and Hommes (1997) that instability is inherent in
such situations when more sophisticated prediction methods are more
expensive is not confirmed in our model.
In fact, the information-updating game investigated in this paper
is subject to evolutionary social learning dynamics, which takes it to a
long-run equilibrium in which, albeit either the majority or even all of
the firms play the boundedly rational information-updating strategy, the
general price level is the symmetric Nash equilibrium price (and
therefore the nominal adjustment of the general price level to a
monetary shock is only temporarily incomplete). In response to a
one-time permanent monetary shock, temporarily incomplete nominal
adjustment (and hence monetary non-neutrality) obtains not only if all
firms are boundedly rational, but also if both information-updating
strategies coexist as a long-run equilibrium configuration. In both
cases, a permanent rise (fall) in the nominal stock of money, by
temporarily leading to a less than one-to-one increase (decrease) in the
general price level, causes a temporary rise (fall) in real output. As a
result, there is long-run monetary neutrality even if either the
majority or all of the firms playing the boundedly rational
information-updating strategy are the only (and stable) evolutionary
equilibrium.
In fact, it follows from (16) that the elasticity of the general
price level with respect to the nominal money stock is (d ln [P.sup.t]/d
ln [M.sup.t]) = (1 - [psi])) [xi] ([[lambda].sub.t]), from which it
follows that [MATHEMATICAL EXPRESSION NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII].
Moreover, as such elasticity is strictly increasing in [[lambda].sub.t],
the extent of the incomplete nominal adjustment of the general price
level varies positively with the proportion of boundedly rational firms.
Or, using the novel notion introduced in this paper, the real impact of
a one-time permanent monetary shock varies positively with the
proportion of firms behaving as boundedly rational inattentive.
Therefore, as aptly argued by Samuelson (1997), an equilibrium
configuration may be reached through an evolutionary dynamics when
decision making is guided by adaptive behavior rather than by unbounded
rationality. As Samuelson (1997, 3) describes an equilibrium
configuration emerging from rule-of-thumb behavior through an
evolutionary dynamics: "The behavior that persists in equilibrium
then looks as if it is rational, even though the motivations behind it
may be quite different. An equilibrium does not appear because agents
are rational, but rather agents appear rational because an equilibrium
has been reached." In the present model, in which either only the
bounded rationality strategy (when mutation is absent) or both
strategies (in the presence of mutation) survive in the evolutionary
equilibrium, we can say that the symmetric Nash equilibrium price
emerges (and the nominal adjustment of the general price level to a
monetary shock is only temporarily incomplete) not because all firms
play the Nash strategy, but rather firms appear unboundedly rational
because an evolutionary equilibrium has been reached.
It is also worth analyzing the dynamics of the convergence to the
evolutionary equilibrium. Per the Jacobian matrix (A29) in Appendix D,
around the evolutionary equilibrium represented by ([[lambda].sub.*],
[P.sup.*]), the trajectories of the state variables defined by the
nonlinear system (25a)--(26a) can be approximated by:
(27) [MATHEMATICAL EXPRESSION NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII],
(28) [P.sub.t] = [P.sub.0] [[[THETA](1 - [[lambda].sub.*])/1 -
[theta] [[lambda].sub.*]].sup.t].
Equation (27) shows that without mutation ([theta] = 0), in which
case [[lambda].sub.t] = 0, the pace of extinction of the Nash strategy
around the evolutionary equilibrium depends essentially on the
dispersion in the cognitive abilities of firms. Meanwhile, still without
mutation, per (28), the dynamics of the incomplete nominal adjustment of
the general price level sufficiently near the long-run equilibrium
depends essentially on the elasticity of the individual prices with
respect to the general price level, given by [phi]). The higher this
parameter, the higher the strategic complementarity involved and the
larger the real impact of a monetary shock. When there is mutation
([theta] > 0), (27) reveals that the pace of convergence around the
evolutionary equilibrium given by [[lambda].sub.*] [member of] (0,1/2) R
depends also on the mutation rate and hence on the specific value of
[[lambda].sup.*]. Besides, still with mutation, per (28), the extent of
the incomplete nominal adjustment sufficiently near the long-run
equilibrium depends on the specific value of [[lambda].sub.*] as well.
(11)
In order to gain further intuition about the main qualitative
results derived along the way, and some resulting implications for the
conduct of monetary policy, we report results from several simulation
exercises. (12)
Figure 1 presents simulation results for a situation where mutation
is absent ([theta] = 0) and the evolutionary equilibrium is, therefore,
characterized by the survival only of the bounded rationality
information-updating strategy ([[lambda].sub.*] = 0). In period 1, the
general price level and output are in the long-run equilibrium
([P.sub.1] = [P.sub.*] = [M.sup.1] = 1 and [Y.sub.1], = [Y.sub.*] =
[M.sub.1]/[P.sub.1] = 1), while the frequency distribution of
information-updating strategies is in one of two possible disequilibrium
positions, [[lambda].sub.1], = 0.01 (left column) and [[lambda].sub.1] =
0.99 (right column). Moreover, two different values for the degree of
strategic complementarity are considered, [psi] = 0.3 and [psi] = 0.7.
In period 2, the economy is hit by a one-time permanent monetary shock
that raises the nominal money stock by 5% permanently, so that the
long-run equilibrium value of the general price level rises by the same
proportion.
Several features of this first set of simulations are worth noting.
First, the monotonic convergence of [lambda] to the evolutionary
equilibrium ([[lambda].sup.*] = 0) obtains for the two levels of
strategic complementarity even if the initial evolutionary
disequilibrium is quite substantial (as shown in the first line of
panels; see also (27)) and in the very next period, the monetary shock
generates a disequilibrium in the macroeconomic variables as well (as
shown in the second and third lines of panels). Second, the model
replicates the hump-shaped temporary response of real output (and
inflation, as it can be easily checked) to such a monetary shock, which
is a well-established stylized fact. In fact, a large literature in
monetary macroeconomics has produced a considerable body of evidence
supporting the notion that demand shocks have sizeable and persistent
(although not permanent) effects on real output. One strand of this
large literature has focused on the effects of monetary shocks,
documenting evidence for substantial monetary non-neutrality in the
short run (see, e.g., Christiano, Eichenbaum, and Evans 1999; Romer and
Romer 2004). Third, as shown in the second and third lines of panels, a
higher strategic complementarity generates a larger (smaller) temporary
output (price level) response to such a nominal shock. As the model
features heterogeneity in information updating, there are some firms
that are better informed than others. The higher the degree of strategic
complementarity, therefore, the less willing are the better-informed
firms to change their prices by much to keep them in line with the
less-informed firms, and hence the more significant is the temporary
monetary non-neutrality.
Fourth, and as also shown in the second and third lines of panels,
the larger initial disequilibrium in [lambda] intuitively generates the
smaller (larger) temporary output (price level) response to such a
nominal shock. The reason is that the immediate impact on the general
price level of such a monetary stock varies positively with the
proportion of Nash firms. Fifth, the monotonic convergence of the
general price level and real output is faster than the convergence of
the frequency distribution of information-updating strategies. This
means that a (falling) proportion of firms will keep playing the
(costly) Nash strategy even after the general price level has achieved
its new long-run equilibrium level (which is equal to new nominal stock
of money) and the average loss of the (costless) bounded rationality
strategy has, therefore, become zero (see Equation (18a)). Bear in mind,
though, that the loss of an individual boundedly rational firm is
normally distributed around the respective average loss (see Equation
(19)), and that the loss of an individual Nash firm is normally
distributed around the positive average cost c (see Equation (20)).
Recall, further, that the evolutionary mechanism of strategy revision is
asymmetric (boundedly rational firms have to rely on random pairwise
comparisons of losses, whereas Nash firms do not), and the intuition for
the sluggish extinction of the Nash strategy (even from a very low
initial measure of firms playing it, as in the left column of Figure 1)
will become clear (see Equation (23)). Sixth, the boundedly rational
information-updating strategy is the only survivor in the long-run
equilibrium despite the asymmetry in the mechanism of strategy revision.
In other words, the long-run equilibrium is characterized by extinction
of the Nash strategy even though all firms playing it are potentially
revising firms at each period, while the probability that a bounded
rationality firm becomes a potentially revising firm at each period,
given by [[lambda].sub.t], is therefore decreasing in the proportion of
bounded rationality firms.
[FIGURE 1 OMITTED]
Figure 2 reports simulations for a situation where there are mutant
firms and the evolutionary equilibrium is, therefore, characterized by
the survival of both information-updating strategies, with dominance of
the boundedly rational strategy (per Proposition 1). This mixed-strategy
evolutionary equilibrium is consistent with robust empirical evidence
showing persistent and time-varying heterogeneity in both the frequency
and the extent of information updating (see, e.g., Andrade and Le Bihan
2013; Branch 2007; Coibion and Gorodnichenko 2012). In period 1, the
general price level and the real output are both in the long-run
equilibrium ([P.sub.1] = [P.sup.*] = [M.sub.1] = 1 and [Y.sub.1] =
[Y.sub.*] = [M.sub.1]/[P.sub.1] - 1), whereas the distribution of
information-updating strategies is in one of two possible long-run
equilibrium positions, each one corresponding to a given mutation rate,
Ql = l% (left column) and [[theta].sub.1] = 5% (right column). These
initial values for the proportion of information-updating firms are
indeed empirically plausible. (13) In the empirical literature, the
frequency of updating an inflation (and sometimes output) forecast is
seen as providing a reasonable measure of the extent with which agents
are (in)attentive to new information by incorporating it in their
forecasts. As noted earlier, the present model can be alternatively
interpreted as assuming that firms form expectations about the current
general price level (and hence current inflation) at the beginning of
the current period (or in the very end of the previous one). (14)
[FIGURE 2 OMITTED]
In period 2, a one-time monetary shock raises the nominal money
supply by 5% permanently, so that the long-run equilibrium value of the
general price level rises in the same proportion. Several features of
this second set of simulations are worthy of highlight. First, the
temporary response of real output (and inflation, as it is easy to
check) to such a monetary shock is hump-shaped, a robust stylized fact.
Second, convergence to the new long-run equilibrium (which features the
same frequency distribution of information-updating strategies, real
output, and inflation rate as those of the initial ones, but a higher
general price level) is accompanied by a temporary (and slight)
hump-shaped response of both the modulus of the loss of bounded
rationality firms (as shown in the first line of panels) and the
proportion of Nash firms (as shown in the second line of panels). Third,
while the response of both the modulus of the loss of bounded
rationality firms and the real output peak right at period 2, the
response of the proportion of Nash firms peaks a few periods later. In
fact, given the evolutionary dynamics in (25), the temporary fall in the
proportion of bounded rationality firms could not start
contemporaneously with the occurrence of the monetary shock. Fourth, the
mutation rate, and then the corresponding long-run equilibrium level of
the distribution of information-updating strategies, matters for the
disequilibrium dynamics of the latter (as shown in the second line of
panels; see also Equation (27)). As it turns out, given the hypothesized
parameter values, the higher the mutation rate, the greater the height
of (but closer in time relatively to the monetary shock) the peak of the
temporary increase in the proportion of Nash firms. In fact, and
relatedly, the higher the mutation rate, the greater the height of the
peak of the temporary rise in the modulus of the loss of boundedly
rational firms. Fifth, the mutation rate also matters for the
disequilibrium dynamics of the macroeconomic variables, even if less
significantly than it matters for the disequilibrium dynamics of k (as
shown in the third line of panels; but see Equation (28)). Meanwhile, as
in the simulations reported in Figure 1, and for the same qualitative
reasons, the convergence of the general price level and real output is,
however, faster than the convergence of the frequency distribution of
information-updating strategies. Sixth, the bounded rationality strategy
is played by most firms in the long-run equilibrium in spite of the
asymmetric nature of the evolutionary mechanism of strategy revision.
Meanwhile, Figure 3 presents simulations for a context where there
are mutant firms and the long-run equilibrium is characterized by the
survival of both information-updating strategies with dominance of the
boundedly rational strategy. In period 1, the general price level and
output are in long-run equilibrium ([P.sub.1] = [P.sup.*] - [M.sub.1] =
1 and [Y.sub.1] = [Y.sup.*] = [M.sup.1]/[P.sub.1] = 1), whereas the
frequency distribution of information-updating strategies is in one of
three possible positions, namely, one long-run equilibrium position
[[lambda].sub.*] = 0.18 corresponding to a mutation rate of 5% and two
disequilibrium positions, [[lambda].sub.1], = 0.01 and [[lambda].sub.1]
=0.99.
In period 2, a one-time contractionary monetary shock lowers the
nominal stock of money by 10% permanently, which leads the long-run
equilibrium value of the general price level to fall proportionately.
Several interesting qualitative results stand out. First, the fall of
real output is only temporary. Second, convergence to the corresponding
new long-run equilibrium (featuring the same distribution of
information-updating strategies and real output as the initial ones, but
a lower general price level) is accompanied by a temporary rise in the
proportion of Nash firms only if the latter is initially in the long-run
equilibrium. In this case, however, the negative response of the real
output peaks contemporaneously with the occurrence of the contractionary
monetary shock, whereas the positive response of the proportion of Nash
firms intuitively peaks a couple of periods later.
Third, whether the frequency distribution of information-updating
strategies is initially in the long-run equilibrium does matter for the
convergence dynamics of the general price level and real output. In
fact, if the frequency distribution of information-updating strategies
is initially in disequilibrium, how large is such disequilibrium
similarly matters for the convergence dynamics of the macroeconomic
variables. Intuitively, the temporary output cost of disinflation is
lower for the higher the initial proportion of Nash firms. The output
cost of disinflation is thus minimized when the distribution of
information-updating strategies is in the largest possible
disequilibrium between the hypothesized initial values. Note that this
result shows that whether the evolutionary dynamics operates in the
presence of mutation matters for whether a larger initial disequilibrium
in [lambda] yields a more complete or less complete nominal adjustment
of the price level after a monetary shock. The reason is that both in
Figure 1 (where there is no mutation) and in Figure 3 (where mutation is
present), the temporary output (price level) response to a permanent
monetary shock is smaller (larger) for the larger disequilibrium in
[lambda]. The intuition is clear: in both sets of simulations, the
larger disequilibrium is characterized by a huge dominance of Nash
firms. Fourth, as in the two preceding sets of simulations, and for the
same qualitative reasons, the convergence of the general price level and
real output is faster than the convergence of the distribution of
information-updating strategies.
[FIGURE 3 OMITTED]
Finally, Figure 4 reports other simulations for a situation where
there is mutation. In period 1, the price level and real output are both
in the long-run equilibrium (Pl=P*=Ml = 1 and [Y.sub.1] = [Y.sup.*] =
[M.sub.1]/[P.sub.1] =1), while the distribution of information-updating
strategies is in a disequilibrium position [[lambda].sub.1] = 0.99.
Meanwhile, two different values for the heterogeneity in the cognitive
abilities of firms ([sigma] = 1 and [sigma] = 0.01) and three different
values for the average information-updating cost (c = 0.05, c = 0.005
and c = 0.0005) are considered. Recall from Appendix E that, when there
is mutation, the long-run equilibrium proportion of Nash firms varies
negatively with the average information-updating cost and positively
with the rate of mutation and the standard deviation of the cognitive
abilities of firms. Consequently, given the rate of mutation, each pair
of standard deviation and average cost formed with the values above
yields a given long-run equilibrium value for the distribution of
information-updating strategies.
In period 2, a one-time contractionary monetary shock lowers the
nominal money stock by 10% permanently, so that the long-run equilibrium
general price level falls in the same proportion. Several other
interesting qualitative results stand out. First, the average
information-updating cost matters for the convergence dynamics of the
proportion of Nash firms. Given the dispersion in the cognitive
abilities of firms, the long-run equilibrium distribution of strategies
and the respective disequilibrium dynamics vary with such cost; and,
given the considered parameter values, they vary more for the lower
dispersion in the cognitive abilities of firms, as shown in the first
line of panels. Intuitively, the initial drop in the share of Nash firms
occurring in period 2 is larger (and it is large enough to ensure
immediate convergence to the evolutionary equilibrium) for the higher
average information cost and the lower heterogeneity in the cognitive
abilities of firms. Second, and relatedly, the average
information-updating cost also matters for the convergence dynamics of
the general price level, mattering more for the lower dispersion in the
cognitive abilities of firms. In fact, for the lower dispersion in the
cognitive abilities, the initial drop in the general price level in
period 2 is larger (but not as larger as the accompanying fall in the
proportion of Nash firms) for the lower average information cost. Third,
and consequently, the average information-updating cost also matters for
the convergence dynamics of the real output; and it also matters more
for the lower dispersion in the cognitive abilities of firms.
Intuitively, given the large initial disequilibrium in [lambda], the
output cost of disinflation is minimized for a combination of lower
information-updating cost and lower heterogeneity in the cognitive
abilities of firms. In fact, the output cost of disinflation is larger
when the hypothesized parameter values are such that the initial drop in
the proportion of Nash firms is large enough to ensure immediate
convergence of such proportion to the evolutionary equilibrium. Fourth,
and relatedly, while in the preceding simulations, the convergence of
the general price level and real output is faster than the convergence
of the distribution of information-updating strategies, the converse is
obtained when the dispersion in the cognitive abilities of firms is
sufficiently low.
[FIGURE 4 OMITTED]
V. CONCLUDING REMARKS
This paper provides evolutionary game-theoretic microfoundations to
the adjustment dynamics of the general price level and real output in
response to a monetary shock. We investigate the behavior of the general
price level in an economy in which an individual firm can either pay a
cost (featuring a random component) to update its information set and
establish the current optimal price or freely use information from the
previous period and set a lagged optimal price. We devise evolutionary
social learning dynamics that, by interacting with the dynamics of the
macroeconomic variables, determine the coevolution of the distribution
of information-updating strategies across firms and the adjustment of
the general price level and real output to a monetary shock.
Interestingly, although either the bounded rationality
information-updating strategy is the only survivor (when mutation is
absent) or both information-updating strategies survive with
predominance of the bounded rationality strategy (when there is
mutation) in the evolutionary equilibrium, monetary non-neutrality is
only temporary. In fact, the evolutionary social learning dynamics
succeed in taking the information-updating process to a long-run
equilibrium configuration where, despite either the majority or even all
of the firms playing the bounded rationality information-updating
strategy, the general price level is the symmetric Nash equilibrium
price. Further, the extent to which monetary shocks have persistent,
although not permanent, impacts on real output depends both on the
frequency distribution of information-updating strategies across firms
and on the dispersion in the cognitive abilities of firms playing a
given information-updating strategy. As regards the conduct of monetary
policy, therefore, a fundamental implication of our analysis is that
there are two different (albeit interlinked) ways through which
heterogeneity in firms' cognitive abilities and boundedly rational
inattentiveness matter. Indeed, as the management of expectations has
become a central element of the theory of monetary policy, a better
understanding of the persistent and endogenously time-varying
heterogeneity in expectations about macroeconomic variables is
essential.
Consequently, we contribute to the research on real effects of
monetary shocks by developing an alternative approach based on a novel
analytical notion to which we refer as boundedly rational
inattentiveness. Although we introduce this notion in the context of a
given macroeconomic model and apply it to the exploration of a specific,
even if perennial, issue (i.e., how the general price level reacts to a
monetary shock), the seemingly likely prospect that other kinds of
behavior are also subject to boundedly rational inattentiveness deserves
future investigation.
doi: 10.1111/ecin.12195
APPENDIX A: THE AVERAGE LOSS OF BOUNDED RATIONALITY FIRMS
Using (12), the relative price established by farmer i can be
expressed as follows:
(A1) [MATHEMATICAL EXPRESSION NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII]
Using (A1), the utility function in (11) can be re-expressed in the
following way:
(A2) [MATHEMATICAL EXPRESSION NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII]
Given that [phi] = 1 -([lambda] - 1)/([lambda][epsilon] - [epsilon]
+ 1), it follows that [lambda][1 - (1 - [phi])[epsilon]] = 1 + (1 -
[psi]))(1 - [psi]) = [lambda]/([lambda][epsilon] - [epsilon] + 1). As a
result, (A2) becomes (see Equation (12) in Ball and Romer 1991):
(A3) [MATHEMATICAL EXPRESSION NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII]
For a given macroeconomic state (Af, P), a Nash-type farmer i will
establish the optimal price, thus obtaining the maximum utility
[U.sup.*.sub.n,i], which can be computed by applying [P.sub.i] =
[P.sup.*.sub.i] in (A3):
(A4) [MATHEMATICAL EXPRESSION NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII]
Meanwhile, a boundedly rational farmer i, by establishing Pi [not
equal to] [P.sup.*.sub.i], will incur in a welfare loss given by
[U.sub.i] - [U.sup.*.sub.i]. For analytical convenience, in this paper,
we work with an approximation of this welfare loss (recall the quadratic
loss function in (17)) resulting from a second-order Taylor
approximation of (A3) around the point [P.sub.i] = [P.sup.*.sub.i]. This
approximation can be obtained as follows.
First, let us compute the first derivative of (A3) with respect to
the price of good i:
(A5) [MATHEMATICAL EXPRESSION NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII].
Of course, there are no first-order impacts, given that: dU:
(A6) [MATHEMATICAL EXPRESSION NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII].
Moreover, the second derivative of (A3) with respect to the price
of good i is given by:
(A7) [MATHEMATICAL EXPRESSION NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII].
Evaluating this derivative at [P.sub.i] = [P.sup.*.sub.i], we
obtain:
(A8) [MATHEMATICAL EXPRESSION NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII],
where the negative sign in (18) is obtained because [epsilon] >
1 and [lambda] > 1. The second-order Taylor approximation around
[P.sub.i] = [P.sup.*.sub.i] is, therefore, given by:
(A9) [MATHEMATICAL EXPRESSION NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII].
Finally, given (A6) and (A8), the welfare loss of farmer i
resulting from establishing a price which differs from the optimal one
can be approximated by:
(A10) [MATHEMATICAL EXPRESSION NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII],
where [MATHEMATICAL EXPRESSION NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII].
Recall the distinction made in this paper between Nash firms and
boundedly rational firms, with only the former establishing the optimal
price. Therefore, the welfare loss in (A10) is incurred solely by
boundedly rational firms and can be rewritten (adding the subscript t as
well) as [L.sup.b,t] = [U.sup.b,t] - [U.sup.N,t] [congruent to] - [beta]
([[P.sub.bt] - [P.sub.n,t]).sup.2], from which it follows the expression
for the loss in (18), where [MATHEMATICAL EXPRESSION NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN
ASCII].
APPENDIX B: PROOF THAT [[lambda].sub.t + 1] [member of] [0, 1)
[subset] R FOR ALL STATE ([[lambda].sub.t], [P.sub.t]) [member of]
[THETA], VECTOR (M, c, [sigma]) [member of] [R.sup.3.sub.++], [psi]
[member of] (0, 1) [subset] R, AND [theta] [[O, 1) [subset] R
First, let us shown that X,+ ]>0 if 0 < A., <l. Given that
F(-) is a cumulative distribution function, we have F(c + [L.sup.b]
(X,,P,))< l, which implies that:
(A11) [MATHEMATICAL EXPRESSION NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII]
Given that 1 - [[lambda].sub.t] > 0 and G (-c- [L.sup.b]
([[lambda].sub.t], [P.sub.t])) [greater than or equal to] 0, and because
G(x) is a cumulative distribution function, it follows that:
(A12) (1 - [[lambda].sub.t]) G (-c-[L.sup.b] ([[lambda].sub.t],
[P.sub.t])) [greater than or equal to] 0.
Given (All) and (A 12), it follows that:
(A13) [MATHEMATICAL EXPRESSION NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII]
By multiplying both sides of (A 13) by [[lambda].sub.t] > 0 we
obtain:
(A 14) [MATHEMATICAL EXPRESSION NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII].
Because [theta] [member of] [0,1) [subset] R, we can use (A14) to
write:
(A15) [MATHEMATICAL EXPRESSION NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII].
We can add 0/2 to the left-hand side of the above expression to
obtain:
(A16) [MATHEMATICAL EXPRESSION NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII]
Therefore, given (A16) and (25), we can establish that
[[lambda].sub.t + 1] - [[lambda].sub.t], [greater than or equal to] -
[[lambda].sub.t], from which it follows that [[lambda].sub.t + 1]
[greater than or equal to] 0 for all state ([[lambda].sub.t] [P.sub.t])
[member of] [THETA], vector (M, c, [sigma]) [member of]
[R.sup.3.sub.++], [psi] [member of] (0, 1) [subset] R, and [THETA]
[member of] (0, 1) [subset] R.
Let us now show that [[lambda].sub.t + 1] < 1 if 0 [less than or
equal to] [[lambda].sub.t + 1] < 1. Given that G(x) is a cumulative
distribution function, it follows that:
(A17) (-c - [[L.sub.b]([[lambda].sub.t], [[P.sub.t]) [less than or
equal to] 1.
Given that 1 - [[lambda].sub.t] > 0, it follows from (A17) that:
(A18) (1 - [[lambda].sub.t] G (-c - [[L.sub.b] ([lambda].sub.t],
[[P.sub.t])) [less than or equal to] 1 - [[lambda].sub.t].
Meanwhile, given that F(c + [L.sup.b] (Pt)) > 0, and because
F(-) is a cumulative distribution function, it follows from (A 18) that:
(A 19) (1 - [[lambda].sub.t] G (-c - [L.sub.b] ([lambda].sub.t],
[[P.sub.t])) [less than or equal to] 1 - [[lambda].sub.t]
Because [theta] [epsilon] [0,1) [epsilon] R, we can use (A19) to
write:
(A20) [MATHEMATICAL EXPRESSION NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII]
We can subtract 0/2 from the left-hand side of the above expression
to obtain:
(A21) [MATHEMATICAL EXPRESSION NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII].
Given that 0 [less than or equal to] [[lambda].sub.t + 1] < 1,
we can use (A21) to establish that:
(A22) [MATHEMATICAL EXPRESSION NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII].
Consequently, given (A21), (A22), and (25), we can establish that
[[lambda].sub.t + 1] - [[lambda].sub.t] < 1 [[lambda].sub.t], from
which it follows that [[lambda].sub.t + 1] < 1 for all state
([[lambda].sub.t], [[P.sup.t]) [member of] [THETA], vector (M, c,
[sigma]) [epsilon] [R.sup.3.sub.++] [psi] [member of] (0, 1) [subset] R,
and [theta][member of][0,1) [subset] R.
APPENDIX C: PROOF OF PROPOSITION 1
Suppose that [M.sub.t] = M > 0 for all t [member of] {0, 1, 2,
...}. Let [[lambda].sub.t + 1] = [[lambda].sub.t] = [[lambda].sub.* and
[P.sub.t + 1] = [P.sup.t] = [P.sup.*] for any re {0, 1, 2, ...}. It then
follows from (25a) that [[lambda].sub.*] = [psi] ([[lambda].sub.*],
[P.sup.*]). Substituting the previous identities in (26), we find that
[P.sup.*] = M, which is the symmetric Nash equilibrium price. As in the
long-run equilibrium with [P.sup.*] = M (18a) yields [L.sub.b]
([[lambda].sub.*], [P.sup.*]) = [L.sup.b] {[[lambda].sub.*], M) = 0, the
condition [[lambda].sub.*] = [psi]([[lambda].sub.*], M) is satisfied if:
(A23)
(1 - [theta]) [[lambda].sup.*] [(l-[[lambda].sup.*]) G (-c)-F(c)] +
[theta] (1/2 - [[lambda].sup.*]) =0.
After some algebraic manipulation, this condition can be rewritten
as a quadratic equation:
(A24) [MATHEMATICAL EXPRESSION NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII]
This equation has two distinct real roots given by:
(A25) [MATHEMATICAL EXPRESSION NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII]
(A26) [MATHEMATICAL EXPRESSION NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII]
Let us show that ([[lambda].sup.*.sub.1], M) is not a long-run
equilibrium in the economically relevant state space. As c>0, we have
F(c) > G(-c) > 0. For all [theta] [member of] [0,1) [subset] R,
therefore, the numerator in (A25) is strictly positive and the
denominator in (A25) is strictly negative. Hence, the root X* < 0 is
such that ([[lambda].sup.*.sub.1], M) [??] [THETA].
Let us now prove that ([[lambda].sup.*.sub.2], M) is the
economically relevant long-run equilibrium for all [THETA] [member of]
[0,1) [subset] R. Firstly, let us assume that [theta] = 0 (there is no
mutation). In this case, based on (A26), we obtain
[[lambda].sup.*.sub.2] = 0, that is, the Nash information-updating
strategy "becomes extinct when mutation is absent.
Now we will assume that there is mutation, that is, [theta][member
of](0, 1) [subset] R. First, let us prove that [[lambda].sup.*.sub.2]
> 0 for all
[theta] [epsilon] (0, 1) [subset] R. Based on (A14), this will be
true if the following condition holds:
(A27) [MATHEMATICAL EXPRESSION NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII].
As F(c) > G(-c), we have (1 - [theta])(F(c) - G(-c)) + 0 > 0.
Therefore, we can square both sides of (A27) and simplify the resulting
expression to obtain the equivalent condition:
(A27a) 2[theta] (1 - [theta])G(-c) > 0.
Because [theta] [epsilon] (0, 1) [subset] R and G(-c)>0, the
inequality (A27a) holds, so that the condition (A27) is also satisfied.
It follows from (A27) that the numerator in (A26) is strictly negative.
As the denominator in (A26) is strictly negative, it then follows that
[[lambda].sup.*.sub.2] > 0 for all [theta] [member of] (0, 1)
[subset] R.
Finally, we will show that [[lambda].sup.*.sub.2] < 1 /2 for all
[theta] [member of] (0, 1) [subset] R. Using (A26), this will be true if
the following condition holds:
(A28) [MATHEMATICAL EXPRESSION NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII].
We can rewrite this inequality as follows:
(A28a) [[(1 - [theta]) F (c) + 0].sup.2] > [[(1 - [theta]) (F
(c) - G (-c)) + [theta]].sup.2] + 2[theta] (1 - [theta])G(-c).
Finally, after some algebraic simplification, we obtain the
following equivalent inequality:
(A28b) (1 - [theta])G(-c)[1/2 - F(c)] < 0.
This inequality holds given that c > 0, G(-c) > 0, and F (c)
> F (0) = 1/2. As a result, it follows that [[lambda].sup.*.sub.2]
< 1/2 for all [theta] [member of] (0, 1) [subset] R.
Therefore, we have shown that there is one, and only one,
economically relevant long-run equilibrium (X*, M) G 0, with
[[lambda].sup.*] = [[lambda].sup.*.sub.2] [theta] [member of] (0, 1)
[subset] R
APPENDIX D: PROOF OF PROPOSITION 2
Throughout the ensuing demonstrations, we suppose that [M.sub.1] =
M > 0 for all t [member of] (0,1,2, ...). Unless specified otherwise,
these demonstrations are valid for any point in the parameter space
[OMEGA] = ([psi] [member of] R: 0 < [psi] < 1} x {(M, c, [sigma])
[member of] [R.sup.3.sub.++]} x {[theta] [member of] R : 0 [less than or
equal to] [theta] < 1).
(i) The equilibrium ([[lambda].sup.*], M) [member of] [theta] of
the system (25a) - (26) is locally asymptotically stable.
Consider the Jacobian matrix of the linearization around the
long-run equilibrium of the system (25a)--(26), which is given by
([[lambda].sup.*], A/):
(A29) [MATHEMATICAL EXPRESSION NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII]
whose eigenvalues are [[alpha].sub.1] = (1 - [theta])[1 - F(c) + (1
-2[[lambda].sup.*])G(-c)] and [[alpha].sub.1] = [psi] (1 -
[[lambda].sup.*]/(1 - [psi] [[lambda].sup.*]). Given that F(c)<l, it
follows that 1-F(c)>0. Moreover, given that [[lambda].sup.*] [member
of] (0, 1/2) [subset] R (per Proposition 1) and G(-c)> 0, it follows
that 1 - F(c) + (1 - 2[[lambda].sup.*])G(-c) > 0. Therefore, because
[theta] [member of] (0, 1) [subset] R, we obtain [[alpha].sup.1] > 0.
Furthermore, given that c > 0, it follows that G(-c) < F(c).
Therefore, it follows that (1 - 2[[lambda].sup.*]))G(-c) < F(c) for
any [[lambda].sup.*] [theta] [member of] (0, 1/2) [subset] R. From the
preceding inequality, meanwhile, we obtain 1 -F(c) + (1
-2[[lambda].sup.*])G(-c)< 1. As a result, because [theta] [member of]
(0, 1) [subset] R, it follows that [[alpha].sup.1] < 1.
Now, as [theta] [member of] (0, 1) [subset] R and [[lambda].sup.*]
[theta] [member of] (0, 1/2) [subset] R, we obtain [psi] (1 -
[[lambda].sup.*]) > 0 and 1 - [psi] [[lambda].sup.*] > 0, so that
[[alpha].sup.2] > 0. Besides, we obtain [psi](1 -[[lambda].sup.*]) -
(1 -[psi] [[lambda].sup.*]) = [psi] - 1 < 0, so that [[alpha].sup.2]
< 1.
Therefore, as we have shown that [[alpha].sup.1]] [member of] (0,
1/2) [subset] R and [theta] [member of] (0, 1) [subset] R, it then
follows that the long-run equilibrium configuration given by
([[lambda].sup.*], M) is a local attractor.
(ii) The set {([[lambda].sup.t], [P.sub.t]) [member of]
[R.sup.2.sub.+] : 0 [less than or equal to] [[lambda].sup.t] < 1, Min
{[P.sub.0], M} [less than or equal to] [P.sub.t] [less than or equal to]
Max {[P.sub.0], M}} [subset] [subset] R is positively invariant for any
initial condition ([[lambda].sup.0], [P.sup.0]) [epsilon] [THETA].
We show in Appendix B that [[lambda].sup.t+1] = [psi] [member of]
(0, 1) [subset] R for all state ([[lambda].sup.0], [P.sub.t]) [member
of][theta]. Given that such result holds for any [[lambda].sup.0]
[member of] (0, 1) [subset] R, it follows by induction that
[[lambda].sup.1] [member of] (0, 1) [subset] R for all r [member of]
{0,1,2, ... and initial condition ([[lambda].sup.0], [P.sup.0]) [member
of] [THETA].
We still have to show that [P.sup.t], [member of] [Min {[P.sup.0],
M}, Max {{[P.sup.0], M})] [subset]R for all t [member of] (0, 1, 2, ...
1 and initial condition (Xq,Po)G0. By dividing both sides in (26) by M
and applying the logarithmic operator to the resulting expression, we
can rewrite (26) as follows:
(A30) [MATHEMATICAL EXPRESSION NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII]
Given that [[lambda].sup.t+1] = [[psi] ([[lambda].sup.t],
[P.sub.t]) [member of] (0, 1) [subset] R for all state
([[lambda].sup.t], [P.sub.t]) [member of][THETA]
X(+1 =t|/(X,, P,) [theta] [member of] (0, 1) [subset] R for all
state (X,, P,) E 0, it follows that:
(A31) [[[phi][1 - [psi] ([[lambda].sup.t], [P.sub.t])]/ 1 -
[phi][psi] ([[lambda].sup.t] [P.sub.t])]/ [member of] (0, 1) [subset] R
Equation (A30) in conjunction with (A31) implies that lln
([P.sub.t+1]/M) < lln ([P.sup.t]/M)| for all t [member of] (0,1,2,
...} and initial condition (([[lambda].sup.t], [P.sub.0]) [member of]
[THETA].
(iii) For any initial condition ([[lambda].sup.0], [P.sub.0])
[member of] [THETA], the general price level converges monotonically
toward a given constant nominal stock of money M.
If [P.sub.t] [member of] (M, [infinity]) [subset] R, it follows
that ln ([P.sub.1]/M) > 0. Given (A30) and (A31), it follows that 0
< ln (([P.sub.t]/M)) < ln([P.sub.t+l]/M) < ln ([P.sub.t+1,/M)
<0 for all r [member of] {0,1,2, ...). Consequently, the general
price level converges monotonically toward M for any [P.sub.0] [member
of] (M, [infinity]) [subset] R.
If [P.sub.t] [member of] (M, [infinity]) [subset] R, it follows
that ln ([P.sub.t]/M) > 0. Given (A30) and (A31), it follows that
0< ln ([P.sub.t+1]/M) < ln([P.sub.t]/M) for all t [member of]
{0,1,2, ...}. Therefore, the general price level converges monotonically
toward M for any [P.sup.0] [member of] (M, [infinity]) [subset] R.
(iv) If the economy is initially at any state (0, [P.sup.0])
[member of] [theta], the proportion of Nash firms rises. Moreover, for
any ([[lambda].sup.t], sufficiently close to one, the proportion of Nash
firms falls.
When there is mutation, so that (per Proposition 1) the Nash
information-updating strategy is played by the minority of firms in the
long-run equilibrium, the boundedly rational information-updating
strategy is not evolutionarily stable. In fact, when ([[lambda].sup.0] =
0, it follows that ([[lambda].sup.1] - ([[lambda].sup.0] = [theta]/2
> 0 for all [theta] [member of] (0, 1) [member of] R.
Meanwhile, when the Nash information-updating strategy is played by
the vast majority of firms, the proportion of firms playing the
boundedly rational information-updating strategy rises. This result can
be demonstrated as follows. If we add ([[theta].sup.0] (1/2 -
([[lambda].sup.t]) to both sides of the inequality in (A20), we can
establish the following inequality for any X, e (1/2,1) [subset] R:
(A32) [MATHEMATICAL EXPRESSION NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII].
Therefore, for any ([[lambda].sup.1][member of] (1 - [theta]/2,1)
[subset] R with [theta] [member of] (0,1) [subset] R, we obtain
([[lambda].sup.t+1] + ([[lambda].sup.t] < 0.
APPENDIX E: COMPARATIVE STATICS FOR THE MIXED-STRATEGY EVOLUTIONARY
EQUILIBRIUM
Applying the implicit function theorem to the long-run equilibrium
condition (A23), we obtain the following comparative static results:
(A33) [MATHEMATICAL EXPRESSION NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII]
(A34) [MATHEMATICAL EXPRESSION NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII]
The common denominator in (A33) and (A34) is strictly positive.
Because c [member of] [R.sub.++], it follows that F(c)>G(-c).
Therefore, we have (1 - [[lambda].sup.*])G(-c) - F(c) < 0 for all c
[member of] [R.sub.++] and [[lambda].sup.*] e [0,1/2) c R. Besides,
because G(-c)>0, we have --[[lambda].sup.*]G(-c)<0. Hence, we
obtain [theta] - (1 - [theta]) {[(1 - [[lambda].sup.*])G(-c) -
[[lambda].sup.*]G(c)] - [[lambda].sup.*]G(-c)} < 0 for all c [member
of] [R.sup.++], [theta] [member of] (0,1) [subset] R, and
[[lambda].sup.*] [member of] [0,1/2) [subset] R.
Meanwhile, the numerator in (A33) is strictly positive. It is
immediate that 1/2 - [[lambda].sup.*] > 0 for all [[lambda].sup.*]
[member of] [0,1/2) [subset] R. As shown above, we have (1
-[[lambda].sup.*])G(-c) -F(c) <0 for all c [member of] [R.sub.++] and
[[lambda].sup.*] e [0,1/2) c R. Hence, it follows that
(1/2-[[lambda].sup.*])- [[lambda].sup.*] [(1 -
[[lambda].sup.*])G(-c)-F(c)]>0 for all c [member of] [R.sub.++] and
[[lambda].sup.*] [member of] [0,1/2) c R, which completes the proof that
[delta] [[lambda].sup.*]/[delta][theta] > 0.
Now, it can be shown that the numerator in (A34) is strictly
negative. Given that F'(c)> 0 and G'(-c)>0, it follows
that -(1-0)[(1-X*)G'(-c) + F'(c)] <0 for all c [member of]
[R.sub.++], [theta](0,1)[subset]R, and [[lambda].sup.*] [member of]
[0,1/2) [subset] R. This completes the proof that [[lambda].sup.*] <
0.
In order to evaluate how [[lambda].sup.*] varies with the standard
deviation of firms' cognitive abilities [sigma], it is convenient
to express the values of the cumulative distribution functions F and G
in the long-run equilibrium as follows:
(A35) F (c) = 1/2 [1 + erf (x)],
(A36) G(-c) = 1/2 [l + erf (-x/2)] = 1/2 [l - erf (x/2)] ,
where x = c/([sigma][square root of 2]) and [MATHEMATICAL
EXPRESSION NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII] is the error
function (Gautschi 1972; Zelen and Severo 1972). Therefore, we can
use (A35) and (A36) to obtain the following derivatives:
(A37) [MATHEMATICAL EXPRESSION NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII],
(A38) [MATHEMATICAL EXPRESSION NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII].
Applying again the implicit function theorem to the long-run
equilibrium condition (A23), we obtain:
(A39) [MATHEMATICAL EXPRESSION NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII].
We have already demonstrated above that the denominator in (A39) is
strictly positive. Moreover, given that (A37) and (A38) jointly imply
that the numerator in (A39) is also strictly positive, the demonstration
that [delta] [[lambda].sup.*]/[delta][theta] > 0. is completed.
REFERENCES
Alvarez, L., E. Dhyne, M. Hoeberichts, C. Kwapil, H. Le Bihan, P.
Liinemann, F. Martins, R. Sabbatini, H. Stahl, P. Vermeulen, and J.
Vilmunen. "Sticky Prices in the Euro Area: A Summary of New Micro
Evidence." Journal of the European Economic Association, 4(2-3),
2006, 574-84.
Andrade, P., and H. Le Bihan. "Inattentive Professional
Forecasters." Journal of Monetary Economics, 60, 2013. 967-82.
Anufriev, M., T. Assenza, C. Hommes, and D. Massaro. "Interest
Rate Rules and Macroeconomic Stability Under Heterogeneous
Expectations." Macroeconomic Dynamics, 17, 2013, 1574-604.
Ball, L., and D. Romer. "Are Prices Too Sticky?"
Quarterly Journal of Economics, 104(3), 1989, 507-24.
--. "Sticky Prices as Coordination Failure." American
Economic Review, 81(3), 1991, 539-52.
Blanchard. O., and N. Kiyotaki. "Monopolistic Competition and
the Effects of Aggregate Demand." American Economic Review, 4,
1987, 647-66.
Blanchard, O., and S. Fischer. Lectures on Macroeconomics.
Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1989.
Branch. W. "The Theory of Rationally Heterogeneous
Expectations: Evidence from Survey Data on Inflation Expectations."
The Economic Journal, 114, 2004, 592-621.
--. "Sticky Information and Model Uncertainty in Survey Data
on Inflation Expectations." Journal of Economic Dynamics and
Control, 31, 2007, 245-76.
Branch. W., and B. McGough. "Replicator Dynamics in a Cobweb
Model with Rationally Heterogeneous Expectations." Journal of
Economic Behavior & Organization, 65, 2008, 224-44.
--. "Dynamic Predictors Selection in a New Keynesian Model
with Heterogeneous Expectations." Journal of Economic Dynamics and
Control, 34, 2010, 1492-508.
Brock, W. A., and C. H. Hommes. "A Rational Route to
Randomness." Econometrica, 65, 1997, 1059-160.
Calvo, G. "Staggered Prices in a Utility Maximizing
Framework." Journal of Monetary Economics, 12, 1983, 383-98.
Carroll, C. "Macroeconomic Expectations of Households and
Professional Forecasters." Quarterly Journal of Economics, 118,
2003,269-98.
--. "The Epidemiology of Macroeconomic Expectations," in
The Economy as an Evolving Complex System, III, edited by L. Blume and
S. Durlauf. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2006, 5-29.
Christiano, L., M. Eichenbaum, and C. Evans. "Monetary Policy
Shocks: What Have We Learned and to What End?," in Handbook of
Macroeconomics, edited by M. Woodford and J. Taylor. Amsterdam, The
Netherlands: North Holland, 1999.
Coibion, O., and Y. Gorodnichenko. "What Can Survey Forecasts
Tell Us About Information Rigidities?" Journal of Political
Economy, 120(1), 2012, 116-59.
Dopke, J., J. Dovern, U. Fritsche, and J. Slacalek. "The
Dynamics of European Inflation Expectations." The B.E. Journal of
Macroeconomics, 8, 2008, 1-23.
--. "Sticky information Phillips Curves: European
Evidence." Journal of Money, Credit and Banking, 40, 2008, 1513-20.
Droste, E., C. Hommes, and J. Tuinstra. "Endogenous
Fluctuations Under Evolutionary Pressure in Cournot Competition."
Games and Economic Behavior, 40, 2002, 232-69.
Fischer, S. "Long-Term Contracts, Rational Expectations, and
the Optimal Money Supply Rule." Journal of Political Economy, 85,
1977, 191-205.
Gale, J., K. Binmore, and L. Samuelson. "Learning to Be
Imperfect: The Ultimatum Game." Games and Economic Behavior, 8(1),
1995, 56-90.
Gautschi, W. "Error Function and Fresnel Integrals," in
Handbook of Mathematical Functions with Formulas, Graphs, and
Mathematical Tables, edited by M. Abramovitz and I. A. Stegun. New York:
Dover Publications, 1972.
Gavetti, G. "Cognition and Hierarchy: Rethinking the
Microfoundations of Capabilities' Development." Organization
Science, 16, 2005, 599-617.
Gavetti, G., and J. W. Rivkin. "On the Origin of Strategy:
Action and Cognition Over Time." Organization Science,
18,2007,420-39.
Kandori, M., G. J. Mailath, and R. Rob. "Learning, Mutation,
and Long Run Equilibria in Games." Econometrica, 61, 1993,29-56.
Khan, H., and Z. Zhu. "Estimates of the Sticky Information
Phillips Curve for the United States." Journal of Money, Credit and
Banking, 38, 2006, 195-207.
Kiley, M. T. "Aquantitative Comparison of Sticky-Price and
Sticky-Information Models of Price Setting." Journal of Money,
Credit and Banking, 39, 2007, 101-25.
Klenow, P. J., and B. A. Malin. "Microeconomic Evidence on
Price-Setting," in Handbook of Monetary Economics, Vol. 3A. edited
by B. Friedman and M. Woodford. Amsterdam, The Netherlands:
Elsevier-North Holland, 2011,231-84.
Lines, M., and F. Westerhoff. "Inflation Expectations and
Macroeconomic Dynamics: The Case of Rational Versus Extrapolative
Expectations." Journal of Economic Dynamics and Control, 34, 2010,
246-57.
Lucas, R. E. Jr. "Expectations and the Neutrality of
Money." Journal of Economic Theory, 4, 1972, 103-24.
Mackowiack, B., and M. Wiederholt. "Optimal Sticky Prices
Under Rational Inattention." American Economic Review, 99(3), 2009,
769-803.
Mankiw, N. G., and R. Reis. "Sticky Information Versus Sticky
Prices: A Proposal to Replace the New Keynesian Phillips Curve."
Quarterly Journal of Economics, 4, 2002, 1295-328.
--. "Sticky Information: A Model of Monetary Nonneutrality and
Structural Slumps," in Knowledge, Information and Expectations in
Modern Macroeconomics: Essays in Honor of Edmund Phelps, edited by P.
Aghion,
R. Frydman, J. Stiglitz, and M. Woodford. Princeton, NJ: Princeton
University Press, 2003.
--"Imperfect Information and Aggregate Supply," in
Handbook of Monetary Economics, Vol. 3A, edited by B. Friedman and M.
Woodford. Amsterdam, The Netherlands: Elsevier-North Holland, 2011,
183-229.
Nakamura, E" and J. Steinsson. "Price Rigidity:
Microeconomic Evidence and Macroeconomic Implications." Annual
Review of Economics, 5, 2013, 133-63.
Pfajfar, D., and E. Santoro. "Heterogeneity, Learning and
Information Stickiness in Inflation Expectations." Journal of
Economic Behavior & Organization, 75, 2010, 426-44.
Phelps, E. S. "The New Microeconomics in Inflation and
Employment Theory." American Economic Review, 59(2), 1969, 147-60.
Reis, R. "Inattentive Producers." Review of Economic
Studies, 73(3), 2006, 793-821.
Romer, C. D., and D. H. Romer. "A New Measure of Monetary
Shocks: Derivation and Implications." American Economic Review,
94(4), 2004, 1055-84.
Saint-Paul, G. "Some Evolutionary Foundations for Price Level
Rigidity." American Economic Review, 3, 2005, 765-79.
Samuelson, L. Evolutionary Games and Equilibrium Selection.
Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1997.
Sethi, R" and R. Franke. "Behavioural Heterogeneity Under
Evolutionary Pressure: Macroeconomic Implications of Costly
Optimisation." The Economic Journal, 150(430), 1995,583-600.
Sims, C. A. "Stickiness." Carnegie-Rochester Conference
Series on Public Policy, 49(1), 1998, 317-56.
--. "Implications of Rational Inattention." Journal of
Monetary Economics, 50(3), 2003, 665-90.
--. "Rational Inattention and Monetary Economics," in
Handbook of Monetary Economics, Vol. 3A, edited by B. Friedman and M.
Woodford. Amsterdam, The Netherlands: Elsevier-North Holland, 2011,
155-81.
Veldkamp, L. Information Choice in Macroeconomics and Finance.
Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 2011.
Weibull, J. W. Evolutionary Game Theory. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press,
1995.
Woodford, M. "Imperfect Common Knowledge and the Effects of
Monetary Policy," in Knowledge, Information and Expectations in
Modern Macroeconomics: Essays in Honor of Edmund Phelps, edited by P.
Aghion, R. Frydman, J. Stiglitz, and M. Woodford. Princeton, NJ:
Princeton University Press, 2003, 25-58.
--. "Information-Constrained State-Dependent Pricing."
Journal of Monetary Economics, 56, 2009, 100-24.
Zelen, M., and N. C. Severo. "Probability Functions," in
Handbook of Mathematical Functions with Formulas, Graphs, and
Mathematical Tables, edited by M. Abramovitz and I. A. Stegun. New York:
Dover Publications, 1972.
(1.) Branch and McGough (2008) compare the dynamics across
predictor choice in Brock and Hommes (1997) with an alternative
evolutionary dynamics (the replicator dynamic) to the one set forth in
our model. In fact, they extend the dynamics in Brock and Hommes (1997)
by introducing a generalized version of the replicator dynamic having
more than two predictors. The main reason why our evolutionary dynamics
is not a replicator dynamic is our purpose to treat the individual
access to the net benefit of each alternative foresight strategy as
asymmetric. While firms playing the adaptive foresight strategy rely on
a pairwise random matching process to access the relative net benefit of
so playing, perfect foresight firms access the same relative net benefit
as a further gain from paying the information cost. A small (but
representative) sample of macroeconomic models with heterogeneous
behavior embedding the dynamics across predictor choice in Brock and
Hommes (1997) include Branch and McGough (2010), Lines and Westerhoff
(2010), and Anufriev et al. (2013).
(2.) A first significant difference with respect to the basic model
set forth in Ball and Romer (1989, 1991) is that the utility function in
(3) does not feature a utility-reducing (constant) menu cost a producer
has to pay to change his nominal price. As specified later, in this
paper, a producer decides about whether or not to pay an
information-updating cost to obtain perfect knowledge of the structure
of relative prices in an environment characterized by strategic
complementarity in price setting.
(4.) This interpretation will be convenient later on when we
compare our simulation results to the empirical evidence. The reason is
that the empirical literature sees the frequency of updating a forecast
about a variable such as inflation as furnishing a reasonable measure of
the extent with which forecasters are (in)attentive to new information.
(5.) Mankiw and Reis (2002) note that microfoundations for the
Phillips curve may ultimately require a better understanding of bounded
rationality. Their conclusion is suggestive: "Yet we must admit
that information processing is more complex than the time-contingent
adjustment assumed here ... [developing better models of how quickly
people incorporate information about monetary policy into their plans,
and why their response is faster at some times than others, may prove a
fruitful avenue for future research on inflation-output dynamics"
(1319). Indeed, an essential feature of the model set forth herein is
that firms do not follow an exogenous rule in updating the information
set, as in Mankiw and Reis (2002), in which, following Calvo (1983),
firms do so randomly. In this paper, firms decide continuously on the
convenience of updating the information set relevant for setting the
optimal price based on net (of costs) payoffs featuring a random term.
Moreover, the resulting evolutionary dynamics may operate in the
presence of a noise component, analogous to mutation in natural
environments.
(6.) As we intend to follow the behavior of this imperfectly
competitive economy over time, thereafter we attach a sub script t to
variables.
(8.) As firms have heterogeneous cognitive abilities, it is
conceivable that the perceived losses associated with the bounded
rationality information-updating strategy differ across firms playing
it. For instance, firms with lower cognitive ability may make greater
miscalculations of the (say) fundamental value of such losses (given by
18a) by (say) misprocessing the relevant available information. These
heterogeneous cognitive abilities are represented in (19) through
individual losses of bounded rationality firms featuring a random
component. The essential role played by the firm's cognitive
abilities in its strategic decision making is established, for instance,
in Gavetti (2005) and Gavetti and Rivkin (2007).
(9.) As conjectured in Branch (2004), actual prediction costs may
be different across individuals if some people have higher calculation
costs. For instance, some people may have greater cognitive ability that
allows them to form a sophisticated forecast at a lower cost. The
specification in (20) can, therefore, be seen as somehow carrying out
the suggestion in Branch (2004) that heterogeneous cognitive abilities
could be introduced via stochastic costs.
(10.) We thank one of the referees for pointing this out to us.
(11.) It can be shown that the main qualitative results found in
this paper (especially the existence and stability of an evolutionary
equilibrium in which monetary policy shocks have persistent, but not
permanent, real effects) are robust to the specification of the average
information-updating cost as varying (positively or negatively) with the
distribution of information-updating strategies rather than being fixed
(when the average optimization cost is treated as variable in Sethi and
Franke 1995, it varies only positively with the proportion of
sophisticated firms). Predictors' costs are also exogenously given
in Brock and Hommes (1997). Further research is needed to find sound
theoretical support for information-updating costs, which vary with the
proportion of updating agents, but it is reassuring that our qualitative
results are robust to this specification. Admittedly, however,
information-updating costs may be found to vary with variables unrelated
to the distribution of information-updating strategies.
(12.) While in the evolutionary microfoundation to nominal
adjustment in Saint-Paul (2005), the results are obtained through
simulations, our results are derived both as explicit analytical
solutions and using simulations. Also, while in Saint-Paul (2005), money
is roughly neutral in the long run if the autocorrelation of money
shocks is high, we obtain longrun monetary neutrality without assuming a
specific process for the exogenous money supply. Meanwhile, the
evolutionary contribution in Sethi and Franke (1995) does not include
any policy exercise, explores the response (solely) of aggregate output
to shocks to production costs arriving in every period (and only)
through simulation, and investigates analytically the evolutionary
dynamics (only) in the degenerate case when the production cost shock is
constant. In this paper, we explore the response of the price level and
output to a one-time permanent monetary policy shock in a deterministic
macroeconomic context both analytically and through simulation.
(13.) Coibion and Gorodnichenko (2012), using survey forecast
quarterly data from the U.S. professional forecasters, consumers, firms,
and central bankers, obtain an average estimate across all
specifications (and with a small dispersion across agent types) of X =
0.18. Meanwhile, Mankiw and Reis (2003) and Branch (2007) perform
survey-based empirical studies for the U.S. setting [lambda] = 0.1.
(14.) In their simulations, Mankiw and Reis (2002) set [lambda] =
0.25, which implies a frequency of information updating
[[lambda].sup.-1] of four quarterly periods (i.e., information sets are
updated once a year). Other studies reporting values of X estimated for
the United States or the European countries directly from surveys or
using proxies (and also using quarterly periods) include: Mankiw and
Reis (2003), 0.25; Carroll (2003), 0.27; Khan and Zhu (2006), 0.14 (for
long forecasting horizon) and 0.33 (for short forecasting horizon);
Kiley (2007), an average of about 0.56; Dopke et al. (2008a, 2008b), an
average of about 0.25; and Andrade and Le Bihan (2013), an average not
much higher than 0.50. Meanwhile, Pfajfar and Santoro (2010) find an
average minimum updating period of 7 months, and Branch (2007) finds
that, on average, the highest proportion of agents update their
information sets every 3-6 months, a lower proportion of agents do so
every period, and few agents update their information sets at periods of
9 months or more, with these proportions varying over time.
GILBERTO TADEU LIMA and JAYLSON JAIR SILVEIRA *
* We are grateful to three anonymous referees and the Co-Editor,
Bruce McGough, for helpful comments and suggestions. Any remaining
errors are our own. We are also grateful to CNPq (Brazil) for providing
us with the research funding. JJ.S. gratefully acknowledges the
Department of Economics of the University of Massachusetts Amherst,
whose hospitality assisted his work on the completion of this paper, and
the CAPES Foundation, Ministry of Education of Brazil, for the grant
(Proc. BEX 18175/12-0), which funded his visit to UMass-Amherst. Lima:
Professor, Department of Economics, University of Sao Paulo, Sao Paulo,
Brazil. Phone +55 11 30915907, E-mail giltadeu@usp.br
Silveira: Associate Professor, Department of Economics and
International Relations, Federal University of Santa Catarina,
Florianopolis, Brazil. Phone +554837219458, Email
jaylson.silveira@ufsc.br