Endogenous timing in contests with delegation.
Baik, Kyung Hwan ; Lee, Jong Hwa
I. INTRODUCTION
Contests with delegation, where each player hires a delegate to
expend effort or resources on the player's behalf to win a prize,
are common. (1)
An example is litigation between a plaintiff and a defendant in
which each litigant hires an attorney who expends his effort to win the
lawsuit on behalf of his client. Another example is a rent-seeking
contest in which each firm hires a lobbyist who expends his effort to
acquire a monopoly or a procurement contract from the government on
behalf of his client. Yet another example is a patent contest in which
each firm hires a group of independent researchers or university
professors who conduct research to obtain a patent on behalf of their
employer. Delegation is attractive to players because they each can use
superior ability by hiring a delegate with more ability than herself,
and achieve strategic commitments through delegation.
In such contests with delegation, we believe, delegates decide
endogenously when to expend their effort after signing delegation
contracts. Indeed, pursuing their self-interest, the delegates may well
endogenize the order of their moves, and communicate it with each other
before they expend their effort. We believe also that players take it
into account, when designing their contracts for the delegates, that the
delegates will endogenize the order of their moves. It is these ideas
that motivate this paper.
Accordingly, the purpose of this paper is to systematically study
contests with delegation in which delegates decide endogenously when to
expend their effort after signing delegation contracts and before they
expend their effort. We study two-player contests with delegation,
focusing on not only the equilibrium delegation contracts between
players and their delegates but also the equilibrium orders of the
delegates' moves. Specifically, we set up and analyze the following
three-stage game. In the first stage, two players each hire a delegate,
and they simultaneously announce their contracts written with their
delegates. Each player's contract specifies how much her delegate
will be paid if he wins the contest and how much if he loses it. In the
second stage, each delegate decides when to expend his effort, and the
delegates announce their decisions simultaneously. In the third stage,
the delegates expend their effort according to their decisions in the
second stage to win the prize on behalf of their employers.
We show that, in equilibrium, the delegate hired by the
higher-valuation player chooses his effort level after observing his
counterpart' s, and his expected payoff is greater than that of his
counterpart. This advantage of the delegate of the higher-valuation
player can be explained by the fact that his employer, the
higher-valuation player, offers better contingent compensation (as it
will be defined in Section II) to him than the lower-valuation player
does to her delegate.
We compare the outcomes of the endogenous-timing framework--the
three-stage game presented above--with those of the simultaneous-move
framework, the game which is the same as the three-stage game with the
exception that the delegates choose their effort levels simultaneously
and this order of their moves is given exogenously. An interesting
result is that each player offers her delegate a better contract in the
endogenous-timing framework than in the simultaneous-move framework.
Another interesting result is that, unless the valuation for the prize
of the higher-valuation player is significantly greater than that of the
lower-valuation player, then each delegate's expected payoff is
greater in the endogenous-timing framework than in the simultaneous-move
framework, whereas each player's expected payoff is less in the
endogenous-timing framework than in the simultaneous-move framework.
In summary, pursuing their self-interest, the delegates decide
endogenously when to expend their effort given contracts between the
players and the delegates. This in turn leads to the players offering
better contracts to their delegates. Consequently, the delegates are
better off, but the players are worse off, as compared with the
simultaneous-move framework. We are tempted to call the delegates'
endogenous-timing behavior "betrayal" of their bosses by the
delegates or "revenge" of the delegates against their bosses.
This paper is related to Baik and Kim (1997), Warneryd (2000),
Schoonbeek (2002), Konrad, Peters, and Warneryd (2004), and Baik (2007,
2008), which study delegation in contests. (2) Baik and Kim (1997) study
delegation in two-player contests in which delegation contracts are
exogenous, and show that buying superior ability is an important motive
of delegation. Considering two-player contests with bilateral
delegation, Warneryd (2000) shows that compulsory delegation may be
beneficial to the players in the case where the delegates' effort
is unobservable. Schoonbeek (2002) considers unilateral delegation in a
two-player contest, and shows that economic rent for the delegate may
exist. Konrad, Peters, and Warneryd (2004) study delegation in a
first-price all-pay auction with two buyers, and show that delegation is
beneficial to the buyers. Balk (2007) considers two-player contests with
bilateral delegation. Endogenizing delegation contracts, he finds the
equilibrium contracts between the players and their delegates, and shows
that economic rents for the delegates may exist. Balk (2008) studies
litigation with bilateral delegation, and shows that the attorneys
prefer the system with the nonnegative-fixed-fee constraint to the
system with the contingent-fee cap, while the opposite holds for the
litigants. A striking difference between this paper and the previous
papers is that this paper allows endogenous timing of delegates'
exerting effort, whereas the previous papers do not.
This paper is also related to Baik and Shogren (1992), Leininger
(1993), Nitzan (1994b), Baik (1994), Morgan (2003), Fu (2006), and
Konrad and Leininger (2007), which study endogenous timing, but not
delegation, in contests. Balk and Shogren (1992) and Leininger (1993)
show that the underdog always exerts effort before the favorite does.
(3) Unlike the other papers, Konrad and Leininger (2007) use
all-pay-auction contest success functions, and consider contests with
more than two players in which each player's cost function is a
general convex function of effort. In Baik and Shogren (1992), Leininger
(1993), Nitzan (1994b), Baik (1994), and Konrad and Leininger (2007),
each player's valuation for the prize is publicly known at the
start of the game. However, in Morgan (2003) and Fu (2006), only the
probability distribution of each player's valuation is publicly
known at the start of the game; the players' valuations are
realized after the players announce when they will expend their effort.
The realized valuations are immediately revealed to both players in
Morgan (2003), while they are immediately revealed to only one of the
players in Fu (2006).
The paper proceeds as follows. Section II develops the model and
sets up the three-stage game. In Section III, we look at the
delegates' decisions in the second and third stages of the game.
Specifically, we first look at the delegates' third-stage decisions
on their effort levels, and then the delegates' second-stage
decisions on when to expend their effort, given contracts between the
players and the delegates. In Section IV, we look at the players'
decisions on their contracts in the first stage of the game. In Section
V, to get more mileage, we modify the three-stage game by assuming
simple logit-form contest success functions, and obtain its outcomes. In
Section VI, we perform comparative statics of the outcomes of the
modified game with respect to each player's valuation for the
prize. In Section VII, we compare the outcomes of the endogenous-timing
framework with those of the simultaneous-move framework. Finally,
Section VIII offers our conclusions.
II. THE MODEL
Two players, 1 and 2, vie for a prize. Each player hires a
delegate. The two delegates, 1 and 2, compete by expending their
irreversible effort to win the prize on behalf of their employers. Each
delegate bears the cost of expending his effort. There are two periods,
the first and the second, between which each delegate chooses to expend
his effort. Each delegate expends his effort in either of the two
periods, but not in both periods. The probability that a delegate wins
the prize is increasing in his own effort level and decreasing in the
rival delegate's effort level.
We formally model this situation as the following noncooperative
game. In the first stage, the players hire delegates and simultaneously
announce their contracts written with their delegates. In the second
stage, after knowing both contracts, each delegate chooses independently
whether he will expend his effort in the first period or in the second
period. The delegates announce their choices simultaneously. In the
third stage, after knowing the contracts and knowing when his rival
expends effort, each delegate chooses his effort level in the period
which he chose and announced in the second stage. (4) Once the winning
player is determined at the end of this stage, each player (or only the
winning player, as it will be clear shortly) pays compensation to her
delegate according to her contract announced in the first stage.
The players and the delegates are risk-neutral. Player 1 values the
prize at [v.sub.1], and player 2 at [v.sub.2], where [v.sub.1] [greater
than or equal to] [von].sub.2] (5). We assume that [v.sub.1] and
[v.sub.2] are positive, measured in monetary units, and publicly known.
A contract that player i designs and offers delegate i in the first
stage takes the following form: compensation of [[alpha].sub.i][v.sub.i]
is paid to delegate i if he wins the prize, and zero if he loses it,
where 0 < [[alpha].sub.i] < 1. (6) We call compensation of
[[alpha].sub.i][v.sub.i] delegate i's contingent compensation.
Delegate i accepts player i's contract if it will yield him an
expected payoff greater than or equal to his reservation wage, given his
belief about the other player's contract.
We assume that delegate i has a reservation wage of 0. (7)
Let [x.sub.i] denote the effort level that delegate i expends in
the third stage. Each delegate's effort level is positive, measured
in monetary units, and may or may not be observable to his employer. (8)
Let [p.sub.i]([x.sub.1], [x.sub.2]) represent the probability that
delegate i wins the prize when delegates 1 and 2 expend [x.sub.1] and
[x.sub.2], respectively, where 0 [less than or equal to]
[p.sub.i]([x.sub.1], [x.sub.2]) [less than or equal to 1] and
[p.sub.1]([x.sub.1], [x.sub.2]) + [p.sub.2]([x.sub.1], [x.sub.2]) = 1.
We assume that the contest success function for delegate i is
(1) [p.sub.i]([x.sub.1], [x.sub.2]) = h([x.sub.i])/{h([x.sub.1]) +
h([x.sub.2])},
where the function h has the properties specified in Assumption 1
below. (9) Using function (1), we obtain [p.sub.1](y, z) = [p.sub.2](z,
y) for every pair, y and z, of effort levels which indicates that the
delegates have equal ability for the contest.
ASSUMPTION 1. We assume that h(0) [greater than or equal to] 0, h
is twice differentiable, h'([x.sub.i]) > 0, and
h"([x.sub.i]) [less than or equal to] 0, for all [x.sub.i] in
[R.sub.+], where h' and h" denote, respectively, the first and
second derivatives of the function h, and [R.sub.+] denotes the set of
all positive real numbers.
Assumption 1, together with function (1), implies that [partial
derivative][p.sub.i]/[partial derivative][x.sub.i] > 0 for [x.sub.j]
> 0 and [partial derivative][p.sub.i]/[partial derivative][x.sub.j]
< 0 for [x.sub.i] > 0, and that [[partial
derivative].sup.2][p.sub.i]/[partial derivative][x.sup.2.sub.i] < 0
for [x.sub.j] > 0 and [[partial derivative].sup.2][p.sub.i]/[partial
derivative][x.sup.2.sub.j] > 0 for [x.sub.i] > 0, where j is the
other delegate. Thus Assumption 1 together with function (1) implies
that, given the rival's effort level, each delegate's
probability of winning is increasing in his own effort level at a
decreasing rate; it is decreasing in his rival's effort level at a
decreasing rate, given that his own effort level remains constant.
Let [G.sub.i] denote the expected payoff for player i. Then the
payoff function for player i is
(2) [[G.sub.i] = (1 - [[alpha].sub.i])[v.sub.i][p.sub.i]([x.sub.1],
[x.sub.2]).
Let [[pi].sub.i] denote the expected payoff for delegate i. Then
the payoff function for delegate i is
(3) [[pi].sub.i] = [[alpha].sub.i][v.sub.i][p.sub.i]([x.sub.1],
[x.sub.2]) - [x.sub.i].
Note that the players and the delegates compute these expected
payoffs at the start of the game, believing that players 1 and 2 will
announce, respectively, their contracts [[alpha].sub.1] and
[[alpha].sub.2] in the first stage, and delegates 1 and 2 will expend,
respectively, their effort levels [x.sub.1] and [x.sub.2] in the third
stage. They do so because they need to know their payoff functions, at
the beginning of the game, to choose their optimal strategies.
All of the above is common knowledge among the players and
delegates. We employ subgame-perfect equilibrium as the solution
concept.
III. DELEGATES' DECISIONS IN THE SECOND AND THIRD STAGES
To obtain a subgame-perfect equilibrium of the game, we work
backward. In this section, we analyze first the subgames which start at
the third stage, and then consider the delegates' decisions, in the
second stage, on when to expend their effort. (10) Note that, in these
stages, the delegates know both contracts--or, equivalently, the values
of [[alpha].sub.1] and [[alpha].sub.2]--chosen in the first stage.
There are three distinct subgames which start at the third stage:
the simultaneous-move subgame, the 1L sequential-move subgame, and the
2L sequential-move subgame. (11) The simultaneous-move subgame arises
when both delegates announce that they will expend their effort in the
same period, either the first period or the second one. If delegate 1
announces that he will expend his effort in the first period but
delegate 2 announces the second period, then the 1L sequential-move
subgame arises. Finally, the 2L sequential-move subgame arises when
delegate 1 announces the second period but delegate 2 announces the
first period.
A. The Simultaneous-Move Subgame
In this subgame, the delegates choose their effort levels
simultaneously. To characterize a Nash equilibrium of the subgame, we
begin by looking at the delegates' reaction functions. Let
[x.sub.1] = [r.sub.1]([x.sub.2]) denote delegate 1's reaction
function, and let [x.sub.2] = [r.sub.2][([x.sub.1) denote delegate
2's reaction function. In Appendix A, we find the shapes of the
delegates' reaction functions.
The simultaneous-move subgame has a unique Nash equilibrium. (12)
Let ([x.sup.N.sub.1], [x.sup.N.sub.2]) denote the Nash equilibrium. If
([[alpha].sub.1][v.sub.1] > [[alpha].sub.2][v.sub.2], then we have
[x.sup.N.sub.1] > [x.sup.N.sub.2]. If [[alpha].sub.1][v.sub.1] <
[[alpha].sub.2][v.sub.2], then we have [x.sup.N.sub.1] <
[x.sup.N.sub.2]. If [[alpha].sub.1][v.sub.1] = [[alpha].sub.2][v.sub.2],
then we have [x.sup.N.sub.1] = [x.sup.N.sub.2]. Let the favorite [the
underdog] be the delegate who has a probability of winning greater
[less] than 1/2 at the Nash equilibrium of the simultaneous-move
subgame. Then, when [[alpha].sub.1][v.sub.1] >
[[alpha].sub.2[v.sub.2], delegate 1 is the favorite and delegate 2 the
underdog. When [[alpha].sub.1][v.sub.1] < [[alpha].sub.2][v.sub.2],
delegate 1 is the underdog and delegate 2 the favorite. When
[[alpha].sub.1][v.sub.1] = [[alpha].sub.2][v].sub.2], each
delegate's probability of winning equals 1/2 at the Nash
equilibrium.
B. The Sequential-Move Subgames
In the 1L sequential-move subgame, delegate 1 chooses his effort
level, and then after observing delegate 1's effort level, delegate
2 chooses his effort level. Let (x.sup.1L.sub.1], [x.sup.1L.sub.2])
denote the pair of the delegates' effort levels specified in the
subgame-perfect equilibrium of the 1L sequential-move subgame. If
([[alpha].sub.1][v.sub.1] > [[alpha].sub.2][v.sub.2], then we have
[x.sup.1L.sub.1]> [x.sup.N.sub.1] and [x.sup.1L.sub.2] <
[x.sup.N.sub.2]. If [[alpha].sub.1][v.sub.1] <
[[alpha].sub.2][[v.sub.2], then we have [x.sup.1L.sub.1] <
[x.sup.N.sub.1] and [x.sup.1L.sub.2] < [x.sup.N.sub.2].
If [[alpha].sub.1][v.sub.1] = [[alpha].sub.2][v.sub.2], then we
have [x.sup.1L.sub.i] = [x.sup.N.sub.i] for i = 1, 2. Next, consider the
2L sequential-move subgame in which delegate 2 chooses his effort level,
and then after observing delegate 2's effort level, delegate 1
chooses his effort level. Let ([x.sup.2L.sub.1], [x.sup.2L.sub.2])
denote the pair of the delegates' effort levels specified in the
subgame-perfect equilibrium of the 2L sequential-move subgame. If
[[alpha].sub.1][v.sub.1] > [[alpha].sub.2][v.sub.2,] then we have
[x.sup.2L.sub.1] < [x.sup.N.sub.1] and [x.sup.2L.sub.2] <
[x.sup.N.sub.2]. If [[alpha].sub.1][v.sub.1] <
[[alpha].sub.2][v.sub.2], then we have [x.sup.2L.sub.1] <
[x.sup.N.sub.1] and [x.sup.2L.sub.2] > [x.sup.N.sub.2]. If
[[alpha].sub.1][v.sub.1] = [[alpha].sub.2][v.sub.2], then we have
[x.sup.2L.sub.i] = [x.sup.N.sub.i] for i = 1,2.
C. Timing of Delegates' Exerting Effort
We now consider the second stage of the full game in which the
delegates choose and announce when to expend their effort. We begin by
comparing each delegate's equilibrium expected payoffs in the three
subgames. Denote by [[pi].sup.N.sub.i] delegate i's expected payoff
at the Nash equilibrium of the simultaneousmove subgame. Denote by
[[pi].sup.1L.sub.i] delegate i's expected payoff in the
subgame-perfect equilibrium of the 1L sequential-move subgame. Denote by
[[pi].sup.2L.sub.i] delegate i's expected payoff in the
subgame-perfect equilibrium of the 2L sequential-move subgame. Then we
obtain the following results. If [[alpha].sub.1][v.sub.1] >
[[alpha].sub.2][v.sub.2], then we have [[pi].sup.N.sub.1] <
[[pi].sup.2L.sub.1] and [[pi].sup.1L.sub.2] < [[pi].sup.N.sub.2] <
[[pi].sup.2L.sub.2]. If [[alpha].sub.1][v.sub.1] <
[[alpha].sub.2][v.sub.2], then we have [[pi].sup.2L.sub.1] <
[[pi].sup.N.sub.1] < [[pi].sup.1L.sub.1] and [[pi].sup.N.sub.2] <
[[pi].sup.1L.sub.2]. If [[alpha].sub.1][v.sub.1] =
[[alpha].sub.2][v.sub.2], then we have [[pi].sup.1L.sub.i] =
[[pi].sup.N.sub.i] = [[pi].sup.2L.sub.i] for i = 1, 2.
Using these results, we obtain Lemma 1.
LEMMA 1. (a) If [[alpha].sub.1][v.sub.1] >
[[alpha].sub.2][v.sub.2], then delegate 1 announces the second period
while delegate 2 announces the first period. (b) If
[[alpha].sub.1][v.sub.1] < [[alpha].sub.2][v.sub.2], then delegate 1
announces the first period while delegate 2 announces the second period.
(c) If [[alpha].sub.1][v.sub.1] = [[alpha].sub.2][v.sub.2], then each
delegate announces either the first period or the second period.
Lemma 1 per se is interesting. It says that, in the case where
[[alpha].sub.1][v.sub.1] [not equal to] [[alpha].sub.2][v.sub.2], the
underdog announces the first period while the favorite announces the
second period. (13) The intuition behind this result is obvious. The
underdog, or the delegate with less contingent compensation, has a
strong incentive to be the leader in the effort-expending stage because
he, as the leader, can signal (to his formidable rival) his intention to
avoid a big fight. On the other hand, the favorite has an incentive to
be the follower. Indeed, he benefits from yielding the leadership role
because he can ease up and respond efficiently to his small rival's
challenge. The two delegates' incentives are not conflicting.
IV. PLAYERS' DECISIONS IN THE FIRST STAGE
In the first stage, player i has perfect foresight about the
subgame-perfect equilibria of each subgame which starts at the second
stage of the full game. Taking player j's contract [[alpha].sub.j]
as given, player i seeks to maximize her expected payoff over her
contract [[alpha].sub.i], where j is the other player. Using payoff
function (2) and Lemma 1, we obtain player i's expected payoffs,
each depending on the value of [[alpha].sub.i] that player 1 chooses,
that are computed in the first stage but take into account the
equilibria of the subgames starting at the second stage. Given a value
of [[alpha].sub.j], if player i chooses a value of [[alpha].sub.i] such
that [[alpha].sub.1][v.sub.1] > [[alpha].sub.2][v.sub.2], then in the
second stage, delegate 1 announces the second period while delegate 2
announces the first period, which leads to the 2L sequential-move
subgame analyzed in Section III. In this case, player i's expected
payoff is [G.sup.2L.sub.i] = (1 -
[[alpha].sub.i])[v.sub.i][p.sub.i]([x.sup.2L.sub.1], [x.sup.2L.sub.2]).
Similarly, if player i chooses a value of [[alpha].sub.i] such that
[[alpha].sub.1][v.sub.1] < [[alpha].sub.2][v.sub.2], then player
i's expected payoff is [G.sup.1L.sub.i] = (1 -
[[alpha].sub.i])[v.sub.i][p.sub.i]([x.sup.1L.sub.1], x.suip.1L.sub.2].
If player i chooses a value of [[alpha].sub.i] such that
[[alpha].sub.1][v.sub.1] = [[alpha].sub.2][v.sub.2], then player
i's expected payoff is [G.sup.2L.sub.i] = [G.sup.1L.sub.i] =
[G.sup.N.sub.i], where [G.sup.N.sub.i] = (1 -
[[alpha].sub.i])[v.sub.i][p.sub.i]([x.sup.N.sub.1], [x.sup.N.sub.2].
(14) Thus player i faces the following maximization problem: given a
value of [[alpha].sub.j],
(4) [MATHEMATICAL EXPRESSION NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII]
where [G.sub.i] = [G.sup.iL.sub.i] for 0 < [[alpha].sub.i] [less
than or equal to] [[alpha].sub.j][v.sub.j]/[v.sub.i] and [G.sub.i] =
[G.sup.jL.sub.i] for [[alpha].sub.j][v.sub.j]/[v.sub.i] [less than or
equal to] [[alpha].sub.i] < 1.
Let [b.sub.i]([[alpha].sub.j]) denote player i's best response
to [[alpha].sub.j] which solves (4). Using the players' reaction
functions, [[alpha].sub.1] = [b.sub.1] ([[alpha].sub.2]) and
[alpha].sub.2] = [b.sub.2]) [alpha].sub.1], we obtain the equilibrium
contracts, [[alpha].sup.*.sub.1] and [[alpha].sup.*.sub.2], of the
players.
[FIGURE 1 OMITTED]
V. OUTCOMES OF THE THREE-STAGE GAME WITH A SPECIFIC FORM OF THE
FUNCTION h
To get more mileage, we assume henceforth that h([x.sub.i]) =
[x.sub.i]. (15) With this specific form of the function h, we obtain
first the equilibrium contracts of the players, and then other outcomes
of the three-stage game.
Taking the steps explained above, we find player i's reaction
function: (16)
(5)
[[alpha].sub.i] = [b.sub.i]([alpha].sub.j]) = [square root of
[[alpha].sub.j][v.sub.j]/2[v.sub.i] for 0 < [[alpha].sub.j] [less
than or equal to] [v.sub.i]/2[v.sub.j]
1/2 for [v.sub.i]/2[v.sub.j] < [[alpha].sub.j] < 1,
for i, j = 1, 2 with i [not equal to] j. Figure 1 illustrates the
players' reaction functions resulting when [v.sub.1] >
[v.sub.2]. In Figure 1, the straight dotted line emanating from the
origin represents the locus of points which satisfy
[[alpha].sub.1][v.sub.1] = [[alpha].sub.1][v.sub.12. Thus
[[alpha].sub.1][v.sub.1] < [[alpha].sub.2][v.sub.2] holds at any
point above the line, and [[alpha].sub.1][v].sub.1] >
[[alpha].sub.2][v.sub.2] holds at any point below the line. This,
together with Lemma 1, implies that any point above the line yields
player 1's expected payoff of [G.sup.1L.sub.1] and player 2's
expected payoff of [G.sup.1L.sub.2]; any point below the line yields
player 1's expected payoff of [G.sup.2L.sub.1] and player 2's
expected payoff of [G.sup.2L.sub.2]. (17) This in turn implies, together
with the locations of the players' reaction functions in Figure 1,
the following. For 0 < [[alpha].sub.j] [less than or equal to]
[v.sub.i]/2[v.sub.j], player i's best response
[b.sub.i]([[alpha].sub.j]) to [[alpha].sub.j] is a value of
[[alpha].sub.i] which maximizes her expected payoff [G.sup.jL.sub.i],
and for [v.sub.i]/2[v.sub.j] < [[alpha].sub.j] < 1, it is a value
of [[alpha].sub.i] which maximizes her expected payoff [G.sup.iL.sub.i].
[18]
Now, we find the equilibrium contracts of the players, which
satisfy simultaneously the players' reaction functions represented
by equation (5). Solving the pair of simultaneous equations, we obtain:
[[alpha].sup.*.sub.1] = [square root of [v.sub.2]/4[v.sub.1]] and
[[alpha].sup.*.sub.2] = 1/2. Point S in Figure 1 represents the
equilibrium contracts of the players resulting when [v.sub.1] >
[v.sub.2].
Let [x.sup.*.sub.i] represent the effort level of delegate i that
is specified in the subgame-perfect equilibria. Let
[p.sub.1]([x.sup.*.sub.1], [x.sup.*.sub.2]) be the probability that
delegate 1 and player 1 win the prize in the subgame-perfect equilibria.
Let [[pi].sup.*.sub.i] and [G.sup.*.sub.i] represent the expected payoff
for delegate i and that for player i, respectively, in the
subgame-perfect equilibria. Then, using Lemma 1 and expressions (1)
through (3), we obtain Proposition 1. (19)
PROPOSITION 1. (a) [[alpha].sup.*.sub.1] = [square root of
[v.sub.2]/4[v.sub.1]] and [[alpha].sup.*.sub.2] = 1/2, so that
[[alpha].sub.*.sub.1] [less than or equal to] [[alpha].sub.*.sub.2] and
[[alpha].sub.*.sub.1][v.sub.1] [greater than or equal to]
[[alpha].sub.*.sub.2][v.sub.2]. (b) If [v.sub.1] > [v.sub.2], then
delegate 1 announces the second period while delegate 2 announces the
first period. If [v.sub.1] = [v.sub.2], then each delegate announces
either the first period or the second period. (c) [x.sup.*.sub.1] =
[v.sub.2] (2[square root of [v.sub.1]] - [square root of [v.sub.2]])/8
[square root of [v.sub.1]] and [x.sup.*.sub.1] [greater than or equal
to] [x.sup.*.sub.2]. (d) [p.sub.1]([x.sup.*.sub.1] = [x.sup.*.sub.2]) =
1 - [square root of [v.sub.2]]/2[square root of [v.sub.1]] [greater than
or equal to] 1/2. (e) [[pi].sup.*.sub.1] = [square root of
[v.sub.2]][(2[square root of [v.sub.1]] - [square root of
[v.sub.2]]).sup.2]/8[square root of [v.sub.1]] and [[pi].sup.*.sub.2] =
[v.sub.2] [square root of [v.sub.2]]/8[square root of [v.sub.1]], so
that [[pi].sup.*.sub.1] [greater than or equal to] [[pi].sup.*.sub.2]
> 0. (f) [G.sup.*.sub.1] = [(2[square root of [v.sub.1]] - [square
root of [v.sub.2]]).sup.2]/4 and [G.sup.*.sub.2] = [v.sub.2] [square
root of [v.sub.2]]/4[square root of [v.sub.1]], so that [G.sup.*.sub.1]
[greater than or equal to] [G.sup.*.sub.2] > 0.
Note that the lower-valuation player pays her delegate half her
valuation for the prize if he wins the prize. Note also that, if
[v.sub.1] > [v.sub.2], then we obtain: [[alpha].sup.*.sub.1] <
[[alpha].sup.*.sub.2], [alpha].sup.*.sub.1][v.sub.1] >
[[alpha].sub.*.sub.2][v.sub.2], [x.sup.*.sub.1] > [x.sup.*.sub.2],
[p.sub.1]( [x.sup.*.sub.1], [x.sup.*.sub.2]) > 1/2,
[[pi].sup.*.sub.1] > [[pi].sup.*.sub.2], and [G.sup.*.sub.1] >
[G.sup.*.sub.2]. Parts (a) and (b) of Proposition 1 say that, trying to
overcome her relative "weakness" in the valuations for the
prize, the lower-valuation player (player 2) offers her delegate
(delegate 2) the "maximum" value of [[alpha].sub.2] that she
is willing to offer, but fails to make him the favorite, so that her
delegate chooses to be the leader in the effort-expending stage. Part
(e) of Proposition 1 says that the equilibrium expected payoff for the
delegate hired by the higher-valuation player is greater than that for
his counterpart. The identical delegates--before signing up for their
employers--end up having different expected payoffs because they are
offered different contracts: the higher-valuation player strategically
offers her delegate greater contingent compensation and motivates him
more strongly than her opponent does. Part (e) says also that economic
rent for each delegate exists--that is, each delegate's equilibrium
expected payoff is greater than his reservation wage. (20)
VI. COMPARATIVE STATICS
In this section, we examine how those outcomes of the game obtained
in Section V respond when the asymmetry between the players
changes--that is, we perform comparative statics of those outcomes of
the game with respect to each player's valuation for the prize.
Using Proposition 1, we examine first the effects of increasing
player l's valuation [v.sub.1] for the prize on the outcomes of the
game. Proposition 2 summarizes the comparative statics results. (21)
PROPOSITION 2. As [v.sub.1] increases from [v.sub.2], (a)
[[alpha].sup.*.sub.1] decreases but
[[alpha].sup.*.sub.1][v.sub.1]increases, and thus the gap between
[[alpha].sup.*.sub.1][v.sub.1] and [[alpha].sup.*.sub.2][v.sub.2]
widens, (b) delegate 1 expends more effort while delegate 2 expends
less, (c) total effort level remains unchanged, (d) delegate 1's
probability of winning increases while delegate 2's decreases, and
(e) delegate 1's and player 1's expected payoffs each increase
while delegate 2's and player 2's expected payoffs each
decrease.
Parts (b) and (c) are stated in more detail as follows. Delegate
l's effort level is increasing in [v.sub.1], but its limit is
[v.sub.2]/4, as [v.sub.1] approaches (plus) infinity. Delegate 2's
effort level is decreasing in [v.sub.1], but its limit is 0, as
[v.sub.1] approaches infinity. As [v.sub.1] increases, total effort
level remains constant at [v.sub.2]/4.
Part (a) of Proposition 2 says that, as her valuation for the prize
increases, the higher-valuation player (player 1) makes her delegate
more aggressive or stronger by offering him greater contingent
compensation. Because of her higher valuation, she can do so with a
lower value of [[alpha].sub.1]. Part (c) is interesting because a
previous result in the literature on the theory of contests shows that,
as [v.sub.1] increases from [v.sub.2], the equilibrium total effort
level increases. (22) The explanation for part (c) follows. In
equilibrium, the higher-valuation player (player 1) offers her delegate
greater contingent compensation than her opponent--which leads to the 2L
sequential-move subgame in the effort-expending stage--and the
lower-valuation player (player 2) offers her delegate the
"maximum" value of [[alpha].sub.2], [[alpha].sup.*.sub.2] =
1/2, that she is willing to offer (see Proposition 1). Consequently, the
equilibrium total effort level is equal to
[[alpha].sup.*.sub.2][v.sub.2]/2. (23) Next, note that, because
[[alpha].sup.*.sub.2] = 1/2, the equilibrium total effort level,
[[alpha].sup.*.sub.2][v.sub.2]/2, is independent of
[v.sub.1]--specifically, as [v.sub.1] increases from [v.sub.2], the
delegates' equilibrium effort levels change in the opposite
directions by the same amount. Therefore, the equilibrium total effort
level remains unchanged as [v.sub.1] increases from [v.sub.2].
Next, using Proposition 1, we examine the effects of decreasing
player 2's valuation [v.sub.2] for the prize on the outcomes of the
game. It may appear that, given that [v.sub.1] [greater than or equal
to] [v.sub.2], the effects of decreasing [v.sub.2] are similar to those
of increasing [v.sub.1]. However, this appearance is partly incorrect.
We obtain first that, as [v.sub.2] decreases from [v.sub.1], ceteris
paribus, both [[alpha].sup.*.sub.1][v.sub.1] and
[[alpha].sup.*.sub.2][v.sub.2] decrease, which is in contrast with part
(a) of Proposition 2. This in turn leads to some other comparative
statics results that are different from those in Proposition 2: As v2
decreases from [v.sub.1], ceteris paribus, (i) both delegate 1 and
delegate 2 expend less effort, (ii) total effort level decreases, and
(iii) delegate l's expected payoff increases if [v.sub.2] >
4[v.sub.1]/9, and decreases if [v.sub.2] < 4[v.sub.2]/9. The first
result is interesting that both parties expend less effort as one of the
player's valuations for the prize decreases. The intuitions behind
these results are as follows. As [v.sub.2] decreases from [v.sub.1],
[[alpha].sup.*.sub.1] decreases and [[alpha].sup.*.sub.2] is constantly
equal to 1/2, so that both [[alpha].sup.*.sub.1][v.sub.1] and
[[alpha].sup.*.sub.2][v.sub.2] decrease. Given less contingent
compensations, delegate 2 (the leader in the effort-expending stage) is
less motivated, and thus expends less effort; delegate 1 who also is
less motivated follows suit. The effect of decreasing [v.sub.2] on
delegate 1's expected payoff is not unidirectional because, as
[v.sub.2] decreases from [v.sub.1], delegate 1's probability of
winning increases while [[alpha].sup.*.sub.1] decreases at an increasing
rate. An increase in delegate 1's probability of winning tends to
increase his expected payoff while a decrease in his contingent
compensation [[alpha].sup.*.sub.1][v.sub.1] tends to decrease his
expected payoff. At a "high" value of [v.sub.2], the former is
less than offset by the latter, so that delegate 1's expected
payoff increases as [v.sub.2] decreases. At a "low" value of
[v.sub.2], the former is more than offset by the latter, so that
delegate l's expected payoff decreases as [v.sub.2] decreases.
VII. COMPARISON TO THE SIMULTANEOUS-MOVE FRAMEWORK
In this section, assuming that h([x.sub.i]) = [x.sub.i], we compare
the outcomes of the endogenous-timing framework--the full game analyzed
so far--with those of the simultaneous-move framework. The outcomes of
the simultaneous-move framework are provided in Lemma 3 in Appendix B.
Figure 1 shows the players' reaction functions and the
equilibrium contracts in the two frameworks when [v.sub.1] is greater,
but not "significantly" greater, than [v.sub.2] (see footnote
24). Points S and Q represent the equilibrium contracts in the
endogenous-timing framework and those in the simultaneous-move
framework, respectively.
Now, using Proposition 1 and Lemma 3 in Appendix B, we compare the
outcomes of the endogenous-timing framework with those of the
simultaneous-move framework. The superscripts * and ** in Proposition 3
indicate the outcomes of the endogenous-timing framework and those of
the simultaneous-move framework, respectively.
PROPOSITION 3. (i) If [v.sub.1] = [v.sub.2], then we obtain:
[[alpha].sup.*.sub.i] > [[alpha].sup.**.sub.i], [x.sup.*.sub.i] >
[x.sup.**.sub.i], [[pi].sup.*.sub.i] > [[pi].sup.**.sub.i], and
[G.sup.*.sub.i] < [G.sup.**.sub.i], for i = 1, 2, (ii) If [v.sub.1],
then we obtain: [[alpha].sup.*.sub.2] > [[alpha].sup.**.sub.2],
[[pi].sup.*.sub.2] > [[pi].sup.**.sub.2], and [G.sup.*.sub.2] <
[G.sup.**.sub.2]. (iii) Unless [v.sub.1] is significantly greater than
[v.sub.2], then we obtain: [[alpha].sup.*.sub.1] >
[[alpha].sup.**.sub.1] > [[pi].sup.**.sub.1], and [G.sup.*.sub.1]
< [G.sup.**.sub.1]. (24)
Proposition 3 says that each player offers her delegate better
contingent compensation in the endogenous-timing framework than in the
simultaneous-move framework: [[alpha].sup.*.sub.i] [v.sub.i] >
[[alpha].sup.**.sub.i][v.sub.i]. This result is very interesting. The
intuitions behind the result are as follows. In the endogenous-timing
framework, the delegate with greater contingent compensation (than his
counterpart) gains strategic advantage--as the second mover--against his
counterpart (see Lemma 1). Such strategic advantage of the delegate is
beneficial also to his employer. Hence, expecting that the delegates
will endogenize the order of their moves in the remainder of the game,
the higher-valuation player (in the first stage) has an incentive to
offer--and actually offers--her delegate better contingent compensation
than she does in the simultaneous-move framework. On the other hand, the
lower-valuation player--who knows that she will fail to offer her
delegate greater contingent compensation than her opponent--also does so
for a different reason. In the endogenous-timing framework, the delegate
with less contingent compensation strategically softens the competition
in the effort-expending stage by moving earlier (than his counterpart)
and expending less effort, as compared with the simultaneous-move
framework (see Section III). Thus, expecting such behavior from her
delegate, the lower-valuation player offers him better contingent
compensation than she does in the simultaneous-move framework in order
to let him fight harder.
Part (i) says that, if [v.sub.1] = [v.sub.2], each delegate's
effort level and total effort level are greater in the endogenous-timing
framework than in the simultaneous-move framework. (25) It follows from
Section III that, given contracts such that [[alpha].sub.1][v.sub.1]
[not equal to] [[alpha].sub.2] [v.sub.2], each delegate's effort
level and total effort level are smaller in the case where the delegates
decide endogenously when to expend their effort than in the case where
they must choose their effort levels simultaneously. On the basis of
this, one may conjecture that the opposite of part (i)--specifically,
[x.sup.*.sub.i] < x.sup.**.sub.i] for i = 1, 2--holds. But this
conjecture is wrong. One should not overlook the fact that both
delegates are offered better contingent compensation--so that they are
motivated to exert more effort--in the endogenous-timing framework than
in the simultaneous-move framework.
Another interesting result in Proposition 3 is that, unless
[v.sub.1] is significantly greater than [v.sub.2], each delegate's
expected payoff is greater in the endogenous-timing framework than in
the simultaneous-move framework, whereas each player's expected
payoff is less in the endogenous-timing framework than in the
simultaneous-move framework. No doubt, the players' stiffer
competition in the endogenous-timing framework, each trying to provide
her own delegate with strategic advantage against his counterpart, makes
the delegates better off but the players themselves worse off, as
compared with the simultaneous-move framework. On the basis of this
result, we argue that the players prefer the simultaneous-move framework
(to the endogenous-timing framework) while the delegates prefer the
endogenous-timing framework. We argue also that it benefits the
delegates but hurts the players' expected payoffs to allow and
facilitate the delegates to endogenize the order of their moves.
VIII. CONCLUSIONS
We have studied two-player contests with delegation in which each
player first hires a delegate, then each delegate decides independently
whether he will expend his effort in the first period or in the second
period, and then the two delegates expend their effort to win the prize
on behalf of their employers. First we have looked closely at the
delegates' decisions on when to expend their effort, given
contracts between the players and the delegates, and looked at the
players' decisions on their contracts. Next, assuming that
h([x.sub.i]) = [x.sub.i], we have found the players' contracts, the
orders of the delegates' moves, their effort levels, their
probabilities of winning, and the expected payoffs of the delegates and
the players that are specified in the subgame-perfect equilibria.
Finally, we have performed comparative statics of these outcomes with
respect to each player's valuation for the prize, and compared
these outcomes (of the endogenous-timing framework) with the outcomes of
the simultaneous-move framework.
We have shown in Section III that the underdog, or the delegate
with less contingent compensation, announces the first period while the
favorite, or the delegate with greater contingent compensation,
announces the second period. In Section V, we have shown that the
higher-valuation player offers her delegate greater contingent
compensation than her opponent, the delegate hired by the
higher-valuation player chooses his effort level after observing his
counterpart's, the equilibrium expected payoff of the delegate
hired by the higher-valuation player is greater than that of his
counterpart, and economic rent for each delegate exists. In Section VI,
we have shown that, as the valuation for the prize of the
higher-valuation player increases, total effort level remains unchanged;
as the valuation of the lower-valuation player decreases, total effort
level decreases. In Section VII, we have shown that each player offers
her delegate better contingent compensation in the endogenous-timing
framework than in the simultaneous-move framework. We have shown also
that, unless the valuation for the prize of the higher-valuation player
is significantly greater than that of the lower-valuation player, then
each delegate's expected payoff is greater in the endogenous-timing
framework than in the simultaneous-move framework, whereas each
player's expected payoff is less in the endogenous-timing framework
than in the simultaneous-move framework. On the basis of this result, we
have argued that the players prefer the simultaneous-move framework
while the delegates prefer the endogenous-timing framework, and that it
benefits the delegates but hurts the players' expected payoffs to
allow and facilitate the delegates to endogenize the order of their
moves.
We have assumed that contracts between the players and the
delegates are public information, so that the delegates decide when to
expend their effort after knowing both contracts. It would be
interesting to consider a model in which contracts between the players
and the delegates are private information, so that each delegate decides
when to expend his effort and chooses his effort level without knowing
the contract for his counterpart. We have assumed that potential
delegates have equal ability for the contest, and thus the same
reservation wage. It would be interesting to consider a model in which
delegates have different ability and different reservation wages.
Another possible extension of this paper is a model in which each player
decides first whether she will expend her own effort or hire a delegate.
We leave these modifications or extensions for future research.
APPENDIX A: THE SHAPES OF THE DELEGATES' REACTION FUNCTIONS
Delegate i's reaction function, [x.sub.i] =
[r.sub.i]([x.sub.j]), is derived from the first-order condition for
maximizing [[pi].sub.i] with respect to [x.sub.i] given [x.sub.j], where
j is the other delegate. This first-order condition is
(A1) [partial derivative][[pi].sub.i]/[partial derivative][x.sub.i]
= [D.sub.i]([x.sub.i], [x.sub.2]) - 1 = 0,
where [D.sub.i]([x.sub.1], [x.sub.2]) =
[[alpha].sub.i][v.sub.i]h'([x.sub.i])h([x.sub.j])/{h([x.sub.1]) +
h([x.sub.2])}.sup.2]. Note that, under Assumption 1, we obtain [partial
derivative][D.sub.i]/[partial derivative][x.sub.i] < 0, and thus the
second-order condition for maximizing [[pi].sub.i] is satisfied.
Differentiating along (A1), we obtain the derivative of delegate
i's reaction function:
(A2) [dr.sub.i]([x.sub.j])/[dx.sub.j] =
-h'([x.sub.1])h'([x.sub.2]){h([x.sub.i]) -
h([x.sub.j])}/h([x.sub.j])[K.sub.i],
where [K.sub.i] [equivalent to] h"([x.sub.i]){h([x.sub.1]) +
h([x.sub.2])} - 2[(h'([x.sub.i])).sup.2]. The denominator in the
right-hand side of (A2) is negative, and
h'([x.sub.1])h'([x.sub.2]) in the numerator is positive, due
to Assumption 1. Then, using (A2), we obtain Lemma 2.
LEMMA 2. (a) Delegate i's reaction function is increasing in
[x.sub.j]--in terms of the symbols, [dr.sub.i]([x.sub.j])/dx.sub.j] >
0--when it lies in the region satisfying [x.sub.i] > [x.sub.j] or,
equivalently, when [r.sub.i]([x.sub.j]) > [x.sub.j]. (b) It is
decreasing in [x.sub.j] when it lies in the region satisfying [x.sub.i]
< [x.sub.j] or, equivalently, when [r.sub.i]([x.sub.j]) <
[x.sub.j]. (c) It is stationary in [x.sub.j] when [r.sub.i]([x.sub.j]) =
[x.sub.j].
Assume naturally that [D.sub.i]([x.sub.1], [x.sub.2]) is greater
than unity--or, equivalently, [partial derivative][[pi].sub.i]/[partial
derivative][x.sub.i] > 0--at points on the 45[degrees] line which are
close to the origin. It is straightforward to show that
[D.sub.i]([x.sub.1], [x.sub.2]) decreases as we move upward from the
origin along the 45[degrees] line. Recall that, given [x.sub.j],
[partial derivative][D.sub.i]/[partial derivative][x.sub.i] < 0, and
that [D.sub.i]([x.sub.1], [x.sub.2])= l holds along delegate i's
reaction function. Using these, together with Lemma 2, we find the
shapes of the delegates' reaction functions.
APPENDIX B: THE SIMULTANEOUS-MOVE FRAMEWORK WITH THE SPECIFIC FORM
OF THE FUNCTION h
Consider the following two-stage game. In the first stage, each
player hires a delegate, and the players simultaneously announce their
contracts written independently with their delegates--that is, player 1
announces publicly the value of [[alpha].sub.1], and player 2 announces
the value of [[alpha].sub.2]. In the second stage, after knowing both
contracts, the delegates choose their effort levels simultaneously and
independently. At the end of the second stage, only the winning player
pays compensation to her delegate according to her contract announced in
the first stage.
To obtain a subgame-perfect equilibrium of the game, we work
backward. At the Nash equilibrium of the second-stage subgame that
ensues after the players announce [[alpha].sub.1] and [[alpha].sub.2] in
the first stage, the effort levels of the delegates are [x.sup.E.sub.1]
= [[alpha].sup.2.sub.1][v.sup.2.sub.1]
[[alpha].sub.2][v.sub.2]/[([[alpha].sub.1][v.sub.1] +
[[alpha].sub.2][v.sub.2]).sup.2] = and [x.sup.E.sub.2]
[[alpha].sub.1][v.sub.1] [[alpha].sup.2.sub.2]]
[v.sup.2.sub.2]/[([[alpha].sub.2][v.sub.2]).sup.2]. Next, using these
(and others), we find the equilibrium contracts chosen by the players in
the first stage, which satisfy the following reaction functions
simultaneously:
[MATHEMATICAL EXPRESSION NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII]
and
[MATHEMATICAL EXPRESSION NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII],
where [B.sub.i]([[alpha].sub.j]) represents player i's best
response to [[alpha].sub.j], for i,j = 1, 2 with i [not equal to] j.
Let [[alpha].sup.**.sub.i] represent player i's contract that
is specified in the subgame-perfect equilibrium of the two-stage game.
Let [x.sup.**.sub.i] represent the effort level of delegate i that is
specified in the subgame-perfect equilibrium. Let [[pi].sup.**.sub.i]
and [G.sup.**.sub.i] represent the expected payoff for delegate i and
that for player i, respectively, in the subgame-perfect equilibrium.
Finally, let [v.sub.1] = [theta][v.sub.2], where [theta], where [theta]
[less than or equal to] 1. Then we obtain Lemma 3.
LEMMA 3. (a) [[alpha].sup.**.sub.1] 1/(2 + [theta]k) and
[[alpha].sup.**.sub.2] = [theta]k/ (1 + 2[theta]k), where defining
[MATHEMATICAL EXPRESSION NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII], we have k = (4 +
6[theta])/3H + [MATHEMATICAL EXPRESSION NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII].
(c) [MATHEMATICAL EXPRESSION NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII].
(d) [G.sup.**.sub.1] = [[theta].sup.2]k [v.sub.2]/(2 + [theta]k)
and [G.sup.**.sub.2] = [v.sub.2]/(1 + 2[theta]k).
Note that we use the computer program Mathematica to solve for k.
Note also that k is a positive real for any value of [theta], even
though H is imaginary, where [theta] [greater than or equal to] 1. If
[theta] = 1, then k = 1, so that [[alpha].sup.**.sub.1] =
[[alpha].sup.**.sub.2] = 1/3, [x.sup.**.sub.1] = [x.sup.**.sub.2] =
[v.sub.2]/12, [[pi].sup.**.sub.2] = * = w/12, and [G.sup.**.sub.1] =
G[G.sup.**.sub.2] = [v.sub.2]/3. Table 1 in Baik (2007) complements
Lemma 3.
REFERENCES
Appelbaum, E., and E. Katz. "Seeking Rents by Setting Rents:
The Political Economy of Rent Seeking." Economic Journal, 97(387),
1987, 685-99.
Baik, K. H. "Effort Levels in Contests with Two Asymmetric
Players." Southern Economic Journal, 61(2), 1994, 367-78.
--. "Two-Player Asymmetric Contests with Ratio-Form Contest
Success Functions." Economic Inquiry, 42(4), 2004, 679-89.
--. "Equilibrium Contingent Compensation in Contests with
Delegation." Southern Economic Journal, 73(4), 2007, 986-1002.
--. "Attorneys' Compensation in Litigation with Bilateral
Delegation." Review of Law and Economics, 4(1), 2008, 259-89.
Baik, K. H., and I.-G. Kim. "Delegation in Contests."
European Journal of Political Economy, 13(2), 1997, 281-98.
Baik, K. H., and J. F. Shogren. "Strategic Behavior in
Contests: Comment." American Economic Review, 82(1), 1992, 359-62.
Baye, M. R., D. Kovenock, and C. G. de Vries. "Rigging the
Lobbying Process: An Application of the All-Pay Auction." American
Economic Review, 83(1), 1993, 289-94.
--. "The All-Pay Auction with Complete Information."
Economic Theory, 8(2), 1996, 291-305.
Che, Y.-K., and I. L. Gale. "Caps on Political Lobbying."
American Economic Review, 88(3), 1998, 643-51.
--. "Optimal Design of Research Contests." American
Economic Review, 93(3), 2003, 646-71.
Clark, D. J., and C. Riis. "Competition over More Than One
Prize." American Economic Review, 88(1), 1998, 276-89.
Congleton, R. D., A. L. Hillman, and K. A. Konrad, eds. 40
Years" of Research on Rent Seeking 1: Theory of Rent Seeking.
Berlin: Springer-Verlag, 2008.
Corchrn, L. C. "The Theory of Contests: A Survey." Review
of Economic Design, 11(2), 2007, 69-100.
Dixit, A. "Strategic Behavior in Contests." American
Economic Review, 77(5), 1987, 891-98.
Ellingsen, T. "Strategic Buyers and the Social Cost of
Monopoly." American Economic Review, 81 (3), 1991, 648-57.
Epstein, G. S., and S. Nitzan. Endogenous Public Policy and
Contests. Berlin: Springer-Verlag, 2007.
Fersbtman, C., and K. L. Judd. "Equilibrium Incentives in
Oligopoly." American Economic Review, 77(5), 1987, 927-40.
Fershtman, C., K. L. Judd, and E. Kalai. "Observable
Contracts: Strategic Delegation and Cooperation." International
Economic Review, 32(3), 1991, 551-59.
Fu, Q. "Endogenous Timing of Contest with Asymmetric
Information." Public Choice, 129(1-2), 2006, 1-23.
Hillman, A. L., and J. G. Riley. "Politically Contestable
Rents and Transfers." Economics and Politics, 1(1), 1989, 17-39.
Hirshleifer, J. "Conflict and Rent-Seeking Success Functions:
Ratio vs. Difference Models of Relative Success." Public Choice,
63(2), 1989, 101-12.
Hurley, T. M., and J. F. Shogren. "Effort Levels in a Cournot
Nash Contest with Asymmetric Information." Journal of Public
Economics, 69(2), 1998, 195-210.
Hvide, H. K. "Tournament Rewards and Risk Taking."
Journal of Labor Economics, 20(4), 2002, 877-98.
Katz, M. L. "Game-Playing Agents: Unobservable Contracts as
Precommitments." Rand Journal of Economics, 22(3), 1991, 307-28.
--. "Observable Contracts as Commitments: Interdependent
Contracts and Moral Hazard." Journal of Economics and Management
Strategy, 15(3), 2006, 685-706.
Konrad, K. A. Strategy and Dynamics in Contests. New York: Oxford
University Press, 2009.
Konrad, K. A., and W. Leininger. "The Generalized Stackelberg
Equilibrium of the All-Pay Auction with Complete Information."
Review of Economic Design, 11(2), 2007, 165-74.
Konrad, K. A., W. Peters, and K. Warneryd. "Delegation in
First-Price All-Pay Auctions." Managerial and Decision Economics,
25(5), 2004, 283-90.
Leininger, W. "More Efficient Rent-Seeking--A Munchhausen
Solution." Public Choice, 75(1), 1993, 43-62.
Loury, G. C. "Market Structure and Innovation." Quarterly
Journal of Economics, 93(3), 1979, 395-410.
Malueg, D. A., and A. J. Yates. "Equilibria and Comparative
Statics in Two-Player Contests." European Journal of Political
Economy, 21(3), 2005, 738-52.
Moldovanu, B., and A. Sela. "The Optimal Allocation of Prizes
in Contests." American Economic Review, 91 (3), 2001, 542-58.
Morgan, J. "Sequential Contests." Public Choice,
116(1-2), 2003, 1-18.
Nitzan, S. "Collective Rent Dissipation." Economic
Journal, 101(409), 1991, 1522-34.
--. "Modelling Rent-Seeking Contests." European Journal
of Political Economy, 10(1), 1994a, 41-60.
--. "More on More Efficient Rent Seeking and Strategic
Behavior in Contests: Comment." Public Choice, 79(3-4), 1994b,
355-56.
Nti, K. O. "Comparative Statics for Contests and Rent-Seeking
Games." International Economic Review, 38(1), 1997, 43-59.
Rosen, S. "Prizes and Incentives in Elimination
Tournaments." American Economic Review, 76(4), 1986, 701-15.
Santore, R., and A. D. Viard. "Legal Fee Restrictions, Moral
Hazard, and Attorney Rents." Journal of Law and Economics, 44(2),
2001, 549-72.
Schoonbeek, L. "A Delegated Agent in a Winner-Take-All
Contest." Applied Economics Letters, 9(1), 2002, 21-23.
Skaperdas, S. "Contest Success Functions." Economic
Theory. 7(2), 1996, 283-90.
Sklivas, S. D. "The Strategic Choice of Managerial
Incentives." Rand Journal of Economics, 18(3), 1987, 452-58.
Stein, W. E., and A. Rapoport. "Asymmetric Two-Stage Group
Rent-Seeking: Comparison of Two Contest Structures." Public Choice,
118(1-2), 2004, 151-67.
Szidarovszky, F., and K. Okuguchi. "On the Existence and
Uniqueness of Pure Nash Equilibrium in Rent-Seeking Games." Games
and Economic Behavior, 18(1), 1997, 135-40.
Szymanski, S. "The Economic Design of Sporting Contests."
Journal of Economic Literature, 41(4), 2003, 1137-87.
Tullock, G. "Efficient Rent Seeking," in Toward a Theory
of the Rent-Seeking Society, edited by J. M. Buchanan, R. D. Tollison,
and G. Tullock. College Station, TX: Texas A & M University Press,
1980, 97-112.
Warneryd, K. "In Defense of Lawyers: Moral Hazard as an Aid to
Cooperation." Games and Economic Behavior, 33(1), 2000, 145-58.
(1.) We define a contest as a situation in which players compete
with one another to win a prize. The literature on the theory of
contests deals with rent-seeking contests, litigation, tournaments,
patent contests, sporting contests, election campaigns, all-pay
auctions, environmental conflicts, arms races, etc. Important work in
this literature includes Loury (1979), Tullock (1980), Rosen (1986),
Dixit (1987), Appelbaum and Katz (1987), Hillman and Riley (1989),
Ellingsen (1991), Baye, Kovenock, and de Vries (1993), Nitzan (1994a),
Clark and Riis (1998), Che and Gale (1998, 2003), Moldovanu and Sela
(2001), Hvide (2002), Szymanski (2003), Corch6n (2007), Epstein and
Nitzan (2007), Congleton, Hillman, and Konrad (2008), and Konrad (2009).
(2.) Fershtman and Judd (1987) and Sklivas (1987) study strategic
managerial delegation. Fershtman, Judd, and Kalai (1991) and Katz (2006)
study delegation with observable contracts, and Katz (1991) delegation
with unobservable contracts.
(3.) Dixit (1987) studies two-player asymmetric contests without
delegation or endogenous timing, and defines the favorite [the underdog]
as the player who has a probability of winning greater [less] than 1/2
at the Nash equilibrium of a simultaneous-move contest.
(4.) If both delegates announce the same period in the second
stage, the game has exactly three stages. But if one delegate announces
to expend his effort in one period and the other delegate in the other
period, one may say that the game has four stages. For concise
exposition, we do not break this third stage into two.
(5.) Asymmetric contests are studied by, for example, Baik (1994,
2004), Nti (1997), and Malueg and Yates (2005).
(6.) We can instead assume that player i's contract specifies
as follows: compensation of [[alpha].sub.i][[upsilon].sub.i] is paid to
delegate i if he wins the prize, and [[beta].sub.i][[upsilon].sub.i] if
he loses it, where [[beta].sub.i] < [[alpha].sib.i] < 1 and
[beta].sub.i] [greater than or equal to] 0. This contract specification
is used in Baik (2007, 2008). Using this more general contract
specification, however, we obtain exactly the same (main) results
because player i chooses zero for [beta].sub.i] in equilibrium. A form
of contract in which a delegate's compensation is contingent on the
outcome of the contest is widely used in the real world. A salient
example is contracts between litigants and attorneys in various
litigation around the world.
(7.) This assumption may indicate that we restrict attention to the
pairs of the players' contracts at which neither of the
delegates' participation constraints is binding. Baik (2007, 2008)
studies contests in which delegate i has a reservation wage of
[R.sub.i], where [R.sub.i] is nonnegative.
(8.) We exclude or ignore zero effort for concise exposition
because including or excluding zero effort does not affect our analysis.
(9.) Several forms of contest success functions have been used in
the literature on the theory of contests. For example, logit-form
contest success functions are used in Tullock (1980), Rosen (1986),
Dixit (1987), Nitzan (1991), Balk and Shogren (1992), Baik (1994),
Skaperdas (1996), Szidarovszky and Okuguchi (1997), Morgan (2003),
Szymanski (2003), and Stein and Rapoport (2004). Probitform contest
success functions are used in Dixit (1987). Difference-form contest
success functions are used in Hirshleifer (1989). Ratio-form contest
success functions are used in Baik (2004). All-pay-auction contest
success functions are used in Hillman and Riley (1989), Baye, Kovenock,
and de Vries (1993, 1996), Che and Gale (1998, 2003), Clark and Riis
(1998), Moldovanu and Sela (2001), and Konrad and Leininger (2007).
(10.) For concise exposition, we omit the detailed analysis of the
second and third stages including the proofs of the characterization of
the delegates' equilibrium effort levels. They are available from
the authors upon request. See also Baik and Shogren (1992), Leininger
(1993), Baik (1994), and Morgan (2003).
(11.) We use 1L as a shorthand for "with delegate 1 as the
leader," and 2L as a shorthand for "with delegate 2 as the
leader."
(12.) See Szidarovszky and Okuguchi (1997) for a proof of the
existence and uniqueness of a pure-strategy Nash equilibrium of the
simultaneous-move subgame.
(13.) Baik and Shogren (1992) also obtain this result. Other papers
on endogenous timing, mentioned in the introduction, obtain similar
results. For example, Fu (2006) shows that the uninformed player chooses
the first period, while the informed player chooses the second period.
Konrad and Leininger (2007) show that the strongest player--the player
who has the lowest cost in expending a given effort level--typically
chooses the second period, whereas all the other players are indifferent
with respect to their choice of timing.
(14.) If player i chooses a value of [[alpha].sub.i] such that
[[alpha].sub.1][[upsilon].sub.1] = [[alpha].sub.2][[upsilon].sub.2],
then we have [x.sup.kL.sub.k] = [x.sup.tL.sub.k] = [x.sup.N.sub.k], for
k, t = 1, 2 with k [not equal to] t, so that player i's expected
payoff is [G.sup.2L.sub.i] = [G.sup.1L.sub.i] = [G.sup.N.sub.i]. For
concise exposition, we will henceforth combine this case with the other
two cases to have the case of [[alpha].sub.1][[upsilon].sub.1] <
[[alpha].sub.2][[upsilon].sub.2] and that of
[[alpha].sub.1][[upsilon].sub.1] > [[alpha].sub.2][[upsilon].sub.2].
(15.) In this case, the contest success function for delegate i is
[p.sub.i]([x.sub.1], [x.sub.2]) = [x.sub.i]/([x.sub.1] + [x.sub.2]).
This contest success function is extensively used in the literature on
the theory of contests. Examples include Tullock (1980), Appelbaum and
Katz (1987), Hillman and Riley (1989), Hirshleifer (1989), Nitzan
(1991), Leininger (1993), Hurley and Shogren (1998), Morgan (2003), Baik
(2004), and Stein and Rapoport (2004).
(16.) For concise exposition, we do not provide the full
derivations of the technical results presented in Sections V, VI, and
VII and Appendix B. They are available from the authors upon request.
(17.) With the specific form of the function h, we have
[G.sup.iL.sub.i] = (1 - [[alpha].sub.i])[v.sub.i][p.sub.i]([x.sub.iL],
[x.sub.iL.sub.2] and [G.sup.iL.sub.j] = (1 - [[alpha].sub.j])
[v.sub.j][p.sub.j]([x.sup.iL.sub.2], [x.sup.iL.sub.2]), for i, j = 1, 2
with i [not equal to] j, where [p.sub.i] ([x.sup.iL.sub.1],
[x.sup.iL.sub.2]) = [[alpha].sub.i][[upsilon].sub.i]/2[[alpha].sub.j][[upsilon].sub.j].
(18.) Stated differently, when player j offers a "low"
value of [[alpha].sub.j] to her delegate, player i offers a relatively
"high" value of [[alpha].sub.i] to her delegate and makes
delegate i the favorite, in which case delegate i chooses to be the
follower in the effort-expending stage. However, when player j offers a
"significantly high" value of [[alpha].sub.j] to her delegate,
player i steps back and offers a relatively "low" value of
[[alpha].sub.i] to her delegate and makes delegate i the underdog, in
which case delegate i chooses to be the leader in the effort-expending
stage.
(19.) Proposition 1 may hold for a more general form of the
function h. First, consider the case where [[upsilon].sub.1] =
[[upsilon].sub.2]. In this case, one may well expect that
[[alpha].sup.*.sub.1] = [[alpha].sup.*.sub.2] and [[alpha].sup.*.sub.1]
[[upsilon].sub.1] = [[alpha].sup.*.sub.2][[upsilon].sub.2] hold, which
implies that part (b), [x.sup.*.sub.1] = [x.sup.*.sub.2],
[p.sub.1]([x.sup.*.sub.1], [x.sup.*.sub.2]) = 1/2, [[pi].sup.*.sub.1] =
[[pi].sup.*.sub.2], and [G.sup.*.sub.1] = [G.sup.*.sub.2] hold. Next,
consider the case where [[upsilon].sub.1] > [[upsilon].sub.2]. Using
payoff function (2) and maximization problem (4), we have
[partial derivative][G.sup.2L]/[partial derivative][[alpha].sub.1]
= [[upsilon].sub.1] {-[p.sub.1]([x.sup.2L.sub.1], [x.sup.2L.sub.2]) + (1
- [[alpha].sub.1])[partial derivative][p.sub.1]/[partial
derivative][[alpha].sub.1]}
and
[partial derivative][G.sup.2L.sub.2]/[partial
derivative][[alpha].sub.2] = [[upsilon].sub.2]{-[p.sub.2]
([x.sup.2L.sub.1], [x.sup.2L.sub.2]) + (1 - [[alpha].sub.2]) [partial
derivative][p.sub.2]/[partial derivative][[alpha].sub.2]}.
Since [p.sub.1]([x.sup.2L.sub.1], [x.sup.2L.sub.2]) = [p.sub.2]
([x.sup.2L.sub.1], [x.sup.2L.sub.2]) and [[alpha].sub.1] <
[[alpha].sub.2] hold at values of [[alpha].sub.1] and [[alpha].sub.2]
such that [[alpha].sub.1][[upsilon].sub.1] =
[[alpha].sub.2][[upsilon].sub.2], we obtain that [partial
derivative][G.sup.2L.sub.1]/[partial derivative][[alpha].sub.1] >
[partial derivative][G.sup.2L.sub.2]/[partial derivative][[alpha].sub.2]
holds in the neighborhood of these values unless [partial
derivative][p.sub.2]/[partial derivative][[alpha].sub.2] is
significantly greater than [partial derivative][p.sub.1]/[partial
derivative][[alpha].sub.1]. This, together with the first-order
conditions [partial derivative][G.sup.2L.sub.1]/[partial
derivative][[alpha].sub.1] = 0 and [partial
derivative][G.sup.2L.sub.2]/[partial derivative][[alpha].sub.2] = 0,
implies that [[alpha].sup.*.sub.1][[upsilon].sub.1] >
[[alpha].sup.*.sub.2] [[upsilon].sub.2] holds. This in turn implies that
part (b), [x.sup.*.sub.1] > [x.sup.*.sub.1], and [p.sub.1](
[x.sup.*.sub.1], [x.sup.*.sub.2]) > 1/2 hold. Similarly, we may
obtain that [[alpha].sup.*.sub.1] < [[alpha].sup.*.sub.2] holds,
which, together with [p.sub.1] ([x.sup.*.sub.1], [x.sup.*.sub.2]) >
1/2, implies that [G.sup.*.sub.1] > [G.sup.*.sub.2] holds.
(20.) Santore and Viard (2001), Schoonbeek (2002), and Baik (2007,
2008) also obtain this result in similar or different contexts.
(21.) We believe that most of the results in Propositions 1 and 2
may hold for the function h([x.sub.i]) = [x.sup.r.sub.i], where 0 < r
< 1. In this case, however, it is not possible to obtain the
equilibrium contracts, [[alpha].sup.*.sub.1] and [[alpha].sup.*.sub.2],
of the player--and other outcomes of the game--because it is
computationally intractable to derive closed-form solutions for the
delegates' equilibrium effort levels, [x.sup.iL.sub.i] and
[x.sup.iL.sub.j], in the iL sequential-move subgame, for i, j = 1, 2
with i [not equal to] j (see Section IV).
(22.) See, for example, Balk (1994, 2004). He shows that, if h
([x.sub.i]) = [x.sub.i], then the equilibrium total effort level
increases as the valuation of the higher-valuation player increases.
Balk (1994, 2004) considers simultaneous-move asymmetric contests
without delegation, whereas we consider asymmetric contests with
delegation in which the delegates decide endogenously when to expend
their effort. Note that Proposition 2 implies that the equilibrium total
effort level of the delegates remains unchanged as the equilibrium
contingent compensation [[alpha].sup.*.sub.1][[upsilon].sub.1] of
delegate 1 increases from that of delegate 2.
(23.) Given a pair, [[alpha].sub.1] and [[alpha].sub.2], of the
players' contracts chosen and announced in the first stage, the
delegates' effort levels which are specified in the subgame-perfect
equilibrium of the 2L sequential-move subgame are [x.sup.2L.sub.1] =
(2[[alpha].sub.1][[upsilon].sub.1][[alpha].sub.2][[upsilon].sub.2] -
[[alpha].sub.2.sup.2][upsilon].sup.2.sub.2])/4[[alpha].sub.1][[upsilon].sub.1] and [x.sup.2L.sub.2] =
[[alpha].sup.2.sub.2][[upsilon].sup.2.sub.2]/[[alpha].sub.1][[upsilon].sub.1], so that total effort level is [x.sup.2L.sub.1] + [x.sup.2L.sub.2]
= [[alpha].sub.2][[upsilon].sub.2]/2. This means that, if the
equilibrium contracts, [[alpha].sup.*.sub.1] and [[alpha].sup.*.sub.2],
lead to the 2L sequential-move subgame, then the equilibrium total
effort level is equal to [x.sup.*.sub.1] + [x.sup.*.sub.2] =
[[alpha].sup.*.sub.2][upsilon]
(24.) If [v.sub.1] = 2[v.sub.2], then we obtain that
[[alpha].sup.*.sub.1] > [[alpha].sup.**.sub.1], [[pi].sup.*.sub.1]
> [[pi].sup.**.sub.1], and [G.sup.*.sub.1] < [G.sup.**.sub.1]. If
[v.sub.1] = 3[v.sub.2], then we obtain that [G.sup.*.sub.1] >
[G.sup.**.sub.1]. If [v.sub.1] = 5[v.sub.2], then we obtain that
[[alpha].sup.*.sub.1] > [[alpha].sup.**.sub.1] and [[pi].sup.*.sub.1]
> [[pi].sup.**.sub.1]. If [v.sub.1] = 6[v.sub.2], then we obtain that
[[alpha].sup.*.sub.1] < [[alpha].sup.**.sub.1] and [[pi].sup.*.sub.1]
> [[pi].sup.**.sub.1].
(25.) If [v.sub.1] = 2[v.sub.2], then we obtain that
[x.sup.*.sub.1] > [x.sup.**.sub.1] and [x.sup.*.sub.2] <
[x.sup.**.sub.2]. If [v.sub.1] = 4[v.sub.2], then we obtain that
[x.sup.*.sub.i] < [x.sup.**.sub.i] for i = 1,2.
KYUNG HWAN BAIK and JONG HWA LEE *
* An earlier version of this paper was circulated under the title,
"Contests with Delegation: Endogenous Timing of Delegates'
Exerting Effort." We are grateful to Amy Baik, Oliver Gurtler,
Sanggon Jeon, Jihyun Kim, Wooyoung Lim, Robert Ridlon, Nicholas Shunda,
two anonymous referees, and seminar participants at Ulsan National
Institute of Science and Technology for their helpful comments and
suggestions. Earlier versions of this paper were presented at the 84th
Annual Conference of the Western Economic Association International,
Vancouver, B.C., July 2009; and the 2011 Annual Meetings of the Allied
Social Science Associations, Denver, CO, January 2011. This work was
supported by the National Research Foundation of Korea Grant funded by
the Korean Government (NRF-2010-327-B00085).
Baik: Department of Economics, Sungkyunkwan University, Seoul,
110-745, South Korea. Phone 4-82-2-760-0432, Fax 2-760-0946, E-mail
khbaik@skku.edu
Lee: Department of Economics, Sungkyunkwan University, Seoul,
110-745, South Korea. Phone 10-2762-1141, Fax 2-760-0946, E-mail
jjonga31@skku.edu.
doi: 10.1111/j.1465-7295.2012.00487.x