How groups reach agreement in risky choices: an experiment.
Zhang, Jingjing ; Casari, Marco
I. INTRODUCTION
Although economists model decision makers as isolated individuals,
within firms and organizations decisions are often taken through
deliberations in groups and committees. Many of those decisions involve
options with different degrees of risk. In the last decade economists
have produced a growing number of studies on this issue.
In an experiment, we study decision-making procedures of
individuals versus groups in a series of choices between a safe and a
risky option. How do groups aggregate individual preferences when
members are initially in disagreement? In the laboratory, one can design
a clean set up, which is free from external confounding factors, in
order to better answer this question. Eliciting risk attitudes for
groups was initiated in management and social psychology (Lamm and Myers
1978; Pruitt 1971; Stoner 1961) and recently involved also economists
(Baker et al. 2008; Masclet et al. 2009). When a group decides whether
to enter a lottery or not, there is no obvious correct choice and
individuals may legitimately differ in their proposals due to their
preferences. For this reason, the psychological literature on groups and
teams would classify this task as "judgmental." On the
contrary, "intellective" tasks have a demonstrably correct
solution. For instance, Cooper and Kagel (2005) study a strategic market
entry task, which is mostly intellective. The only intellective aspect
of our lottery task is that choices should be coherent. (1) Earlier
studies in social psychology introduced the concepts of risky shifts and
cautious shifts. "Risky shift" denotes situations where groups
make riskier decisions than individuals, and "cautious shift"
otherwise.
Depending on the study, the results reported in the literature are
sometimes in one direction and sometimes in the other. One reason for
this diversity of findings may be the presence of important, but
overlooked, differences in the design and methodology among studies.
Hence, we first proceed by mapping the approach of some recent
experimental studies. In the present work, we designed group interaction
rules to facilitate information exchange, to encourage participation by
all members, and to focus the interaction on how to aggregate individual
preferences. The main aim is to understand in detail how groups of three
members deal with disagreement. Our design is novel because there is a
written record of the communication among group members to understand
internal dynamics and to correlate with actual differences in outcomes.
It is the first, among the studies of group risk attitude, where before
the discussion, each participant must post her proposal, a feature that
saves discussion time and prevents shy members from being silenced. This
piece of information allows us to perform an individual-level analysis
of preference aggregation. Moreover, in case of disagreement, the
minority has veto power over the group decision. Like many other
studies, we call for a unanimous decision but, unlike others, here the
sanction for disagreement is severe: no choice and zero earnings. In the
field this rule is observed in international bodies that do not take a
stand on an issue when they do not reach consensus, or in organizations
that do not participate in an auction unless the board of directors
agree on a bid. This rule creates a common interest within the group to
communicate and reach a decision. Other default rules do not generate
this positive group dynamic.
Through the group process, we find that lottery choices become more
coherent and closer to risk neutrality. In resolving disagreement, the
proposal of the majority did not always prevail. It prevailed more often
when its proposal was closer to risk neutrality. There are some
interesting personality and demographic effects, which we report in
detail below.
The remainder of the paper is organized as follows. Section II
reviews literature. Section III describes experimental design and
procedures. Section IV reports the results and Section V concludes.
II. LITERATURE REVIEW
This section focuses on four recent papers that examine decisions
made by groups facing risky choices, Baker et al. (2008), Harrison et
al. (2010), Masclet et al. (2009), and Shupp and Williams (2008). Table
1 presents a design comparison with the present study. All studies,
including ours, compare lottery choices of groups of three members with
individuals choosing in isolation. In both treatments, subjects face the
same set of lottery choices (ranging from 8 to 15) and identical
monetary incentives. At the end of the session, only one of the
lotteries is randomly selected for payment. Baker et al. (2008), Masclet
et al. (2009), and Shupp and Williams (2008) all found that groups are
more risk averse than individuals. On the contrary, Harrison et al.
(2010) report no group effect.
Existing studies exhibit a significant diversity in design along a
number of dimensions (Table 1). The most interesting differences pertain
to group interaction. First, Masclet et al. (2009) randomly changed
group composition for each lottery choice, whereas the others kept it
fixed. This generates different dynamic incentives to
"tune-in" with the group. Second, communication ranges from
none, to anonymous chat rooms, to face-to-face interaction. We know from
experiments on social dilemmas that communication can have profound
effects on choices. (2) With lottery choices, the issue is not to
overcome free riding but rather to aggregate preferences. Hence,
communication fulfills other aims.
In all studies in Table 1, the instructions call for a unanimous
group decision except in Harrison et al. (2010) that employed a majority
voting rule. Within the consensus call, there are substantive
differences in the default choice when a group does not reach unanimity.
Although often downplayed in experiments with groups, this aspect is
theoretically extremely important. Among the criteria to resolve
disagreement there are random choice, majority rule, mean choice, and no
choice. Each default rule implicitly sets different incentives for group
discussion, which includes incentives to "talk" and to
"listen." Let us adopt the standard assumption that subjects
have well-defined preferences toward risk and assume that they are
informed about the intended choices of others in their group. The last
column of Table 1 lists whether a subject would benefit from
successfully persuading others to change their intended choice
("talk"). Except Shupp and Williams (2007), all studies asked
the subjects to make a binary decision between a safe and a risky
option. Thus, the initial opinions must be a majority of two versus a
minority of one. (3) All default rules exhibit positive incentives to
talk, except majority rule, where if you are already part of the
majority you do not have any incentive to persuade others. Another
crucial aspect is the incentive to "listen." The default rules
implemented in the previous studies may not generate positive incentives
to listen (Table 1). Of course, there may be other types of advantages
from listening to others besides those considered in Table 1.
Communication may enhance the understanding of the task as well as
learning about the intended choices of others and so benefit everyone in
the group. Table 1 considers incentives under the more narrow view of
rational subjects endowed with precise utility functions, which are
common knowledge.
Like some of the experiments, we employed a within-subject design
which allows a more direct comparison of choices in isolation (I) and in
group (G) but may exhibit order effects. To control for order effects,
Masclet et al. (2009) run sessions with I-G and G-I sequences and do not
find any. Others employed a between-subject design, which relies instead
on an assumption of similar preferences of the two experimental samples
for I and for G treatments.
Other experimental studies have groups facing more challenging
choices under risk. Rockenbach et al. (2007) compared individuals and
groups with respect to choices among alternative financial investments
and found that groups accumulate significantly higher expected values at
a significantly lower total risk. Charness et al. (2007) study choice
monotonicity over lottery and Bayesian updating by individuals and
groups. They find that social interaction reduces violation rates, and
thus groups make substantially fewer errors than individuals and the
error rate decreases with group size.
III. EXPERIMENTAL DESIGN AND PROCEDURES
Each session had four parts plus a questionnaire and involved 15
participants. Overall 120 students participated in the experiment. In
part 1, we measured subjects' risk attitude with 15 binary choices
between lotteries. In part 2, subjects were randomly divided into groups
of three persons and faced the same task as in part 1. The per-capita
expected payoff in part 1 was equal to that in part 2. We report results
of parts 3 and 4, which involved a different task, in Casari et al.
(2010). The overall incentive structure was similar to that in Holt and
Laury (2002). Subjects chose between a "safe" Option A and a
"risky" Option B. The payoff for Option A was deterministic (50 tokens) and the payoff for Option B was either 150 or 0. On the
first decision, the probability of the high payoff (150) for Option B
was 0. In subsequent choices, the probability of the high payoff
increased by 1/20 each line, 0, 1/20, ..., 14/20. A risk-neutral person
would choose Option A in lotteries 1 through 7 and then switch to Option
B in lottery 8. Risk seeking agents may switch to Option B earlier than
lottery 7 and risk-averse agents may switch later than lottery 7. Any
rational agent should choose Option A over Option B in the first lottery
(50 vs. 0 francs always) and later on eventually switch to Option B.
Multiple switches would be a signal of confusion. We paid only one of
the 15 decisions, chosen randomly at the end of the session. Random
choices were all implemented through drawings from a bingo cage.
In part 2, there were five groups in each session. There was a
proposal phase, a chat phase, and a group choice phase. Everyone
simultaneously made an individual proposal about each of the 15 lottery
choices. Then any line with disagreement was highlighted for all three
group members to see. At this point, participants could switch to a chat
window and had 2 minutes to send free-format messages to others in their
group. We asked participants to follow two basic rules: (1) to be civil
to one another and do not use profanities and (2) not to identify
themselves in any manner. Messages were recorded. In the chat window,
subjects received an id number from 1 to 3 based on the order in which
they sent messages in that specific period. After the chat stage,
everyone had to submit a choice for the group decision. If the choices
of all three group members were identical for a specific decision line
(unanimity), then we had a group choice. If there was unanimity on all
15 choices, then part 2 was over. Otherwise, the line(s) with
disagreement was (were) high-lighted and all three group members were
asked to submit their new proposals. If there was still disagreement,
there was another, final round of proposals. At this point part 2 was
over even if disagreement remained. The design followed a default rule
of "no choice": if the group reached no unanimous decision, no
decision was placed, so earnings were zero for everyone in the group.
Such a default rule generates positive incentives both to talk and to
listen to others in the chat. In fact, these incentives are the highest
among the studies listed in Table 1. With disagreement between a safe
and a risky option, a default rule with random selection induces a game
where a subject's dominant strategy is to choose her most preferred
option. Instead, a default rule of "no choice" induces a
battle-of-the sexes game where a subject would always switch choice to
avoid a disagreement outcome. We paid only one of the 15 decisions,
chosen randomly at the end of the session. Random choices were all
implemented through drawings from a bingo cage. If for the line selected
the group was still in disagreement, then the group earned 0 for part 2.
Overall, there were 40 groups and 600 group decisions taken.
We distributed written instructions and read them aloud, taking
questions as they arose. The experiment was performed with a z-tree
application (Fishbacher 2007). No person participated in more than one
experimental session. We guaranteed a minimum payment of $5. We
converted each experimental token to an actual dollar at the rate of
$0.03. Including all parts, a session lasted on average about 2 hours
and average earnings per person were about $20. We conducted eight
experimental sessions at Purdue University (USA) between 25 September
and 28 October, 2007. Participants were recruited from the undergraduate
campus population by email.
IV. RESULTS
We report five main results.
A. Result 1: The Monotonicity of Lottery Choices Improved from the
Individual to the Group Treatment
We employed a table format to elicit risk attitude, where a subject
with monotonic risk preferences would choose Option A in decision 1 and
then eventually switch forever to Option B at one later decision. A
subject who switched from A to B more than once, or who switched from B
back to A, is classified as nonmonotonic, which is taken as a proxy of
confusion or irrationality. (4) Recorded levels of monotonicity in the
experiment were very high, ranging from 87.5% for individual choices
(105/120) to 95.0% for group choices (38/40) (one-sided t test, m = 120,
n = 40, p-value = 0.034). A small portion of this improvement may be
attributed to task learning, but we find no significant difference in
monotonicity levels between individual proposals and individual choices
(90.0% vs. 87.5%, one-sided t test, m = 120, n = 120, p-value = .27). In
part 2, individual proposals do not have significantly different level
of monotonicity in lottery choices than group final decisions (90.0 vs.
95.0%, one-sided t test, m = 120, n = 40, p-value = .32).
B. Result 2: Group Choices Were Closer to Risk Neutrality Than
Individual Choices. In Particular, Group Choices Exhibited a Risky Shift
from Individual Choices
Support for Result 2 comes from Table 2 and Figure 1. We discuss
separately lotteries 1-7 from lotteries 8-15. In lotteries 1-7, only a
risk-seeking agent would choose the risky Option B. Differences here
were rather limited because risk seeking behavior was rare: on average,
only 2% of individual choices and 0.4% of group choices were for B. In
these lotteries, groups were less risk seeking than individuals. Most of
the differences came from lotteries 8-15 where a risk-neutral agent
would choose the risky Option B. In these lotteries, groups were more
risky than individuals. On average, 57.4% of individual choices and
61.7% of group choices were for B. Group choices are more risky than
individual choices (p-value < 0.05). (5) Recall that part l elicited individual choices while part 2 elicited individual proposals and group
choices. Although this fixed order may have had some impact on results,
order effects are unlikely to explain the risky shift. First, we stated
in part 1 of the instructions that the tasks in parts 1 and 2 were the
same lottery choices. Hence subjects could optimize considering the
overall level of uncertainty. Second, little evidence can be traced from
a comparison of the individual choices in part 1 with the individual
proposals in part 2. We elicited individual proposals before any
communication could take place in the group setting and report only
minimal differences with part 1 choices, which helps to rule out large
order effects. As mentioned after Result l, some of this difference is
simply a correction of nonmonotonic behavior. Third, Masclet et al.
(2009) explicitly studied order effects but did not find any.
Result 2 may be a consequence of the default rule adopted in the
design. The "no choice" rule may have generated a different
group dynamic. In particular an asymmetry in payoffs between risk-averse
and risk-neutral subjects in the negotiation over disagreement. More
risk-averse subjects may have less to lose from switching to their least
preferred choice. (6)
C. Result 3: When in Disagreement, the Majority Proposal Did Not
Always Prevail. It Prevailed More Often When Its Proposal Was Closer to
Risk Neutrality. Proposals from Nonmonotonic Subjects Were Less Likely
to Prevail
Support for Result 3 comes from Tables 3-5 and Figure 2. We focus
explicitly on group decisions where there was an initial disagreement.
We define disagreement as a situation where not all three individual
proposals were equal. All groups disagreed on at least one decision,
77.5% found an agreement on the first round, 20% after a second or third
round, and only 2.5% (1 group) never found complete agreement. (7) On
average, a group disagreed on four lottery decisions (27% of decisions).
The bulk of the disagreement (85%) was in lotteries 8-13, where risk
neutrality pointed toward Option B while risk-averse subjects may have
preferred the safer Option A (Figure 2).
[FIGURE 1 OMITTED]
The analysis of disagreement is particularly interesting because
one can understand the internal process that led to a decision and shed
light on Result 2. Given that the decision was binary, A or B, and a
group comprised three individuals, there were only two possible patterns
of disagreement, a majority for A (AAB) or a majority for B (ABB). Out
of a total of 600, there were 159 group decisions with disagreement. In
order to study how disagreement was resolved through group interaction,
we consider two possible benchmarks: the outcome with a dictator selected at random in the group and the outcome with majority voting.
Following a random dictator process the proposal of the majority would
prevail in 66.7% of the cases while following majority voting the
proposal of the majority would prevail in 100% of the cases. As Table 3
illustrates, when in disagreement, the proposal of the majority
prevailed in 81.1% of the decisions, while the minoritarian proposal
prevailed in the remaining 18.9% (two Pearson chi-squared tests, p-value
< .01, n = 159). The actual outcome is in-between a random dictator
and a majority rule process and exhibits some interesting biases in
group decision making.
[FIGURE 2 OMITTED]
When in disagreement, 52.7% of individual proposals and 61.0% of
group choices were the same as those of a risk-neutral agent. Table 3
suggests that the proposal of the majority prevailed more often when its
proposal was the same as that of a risk-neutral agent (79/91 vs. 50/68,
Pearson chi-squared test, p-value = .011). Hence the group interaction
generated a shift toward more risk-neutral choices.
Table 4 presents a breakdown with respect to whether the more risky
proposal prevailed. Overall, with disagreement the more risky proposal
prevailed in 54.7% of the decisions, which is slightly higher than
predicted by a coin flip resolution of disagreement (50.0%) and higher
than what is expected had the proposal of the majority always prevailed
(49.7%). (8) In particular, when the majority prevailed, in 52.7% of the
decisions it had the more risky position; when the minority prevailed,
in 63.3% of the decisions it had the more risky position.
Table 5 presents the marginal effect from a probit regression on
individual proposals. The dependent variable is equal to one when an
individual proposal equals the actual group choice (hence it prevails in
case of disagreement). Among the independent variables, we included some
aspects of lottery choices, demographic and personality traits, and chat
activity. The focus is on individual proposals in disagreement with
others in the group. We will postpone the discussion of chat activity to
Result 4 and discuss the other findings. Demographic regressors include
skill, gender, and major. Skills are proxied by the ACT/SAT scores
obtained from the university Registrar's Office. We have either SAT
or ACT scores for 92.5% of the subjects (missing data = 0), who are
coded using the US nationwide distribution of the SAT-takers (College
Board of Education 2006) and ACT-takers. The threshold for high ability
is being in the top quartile of the distribution and for low ability is
being in the lower quartile. The variables are primarily based on SAT
scores and, when missing, on ACT scores. The cutoff values are the
average between male and female national tables.
Another class of regressors code five personality traits using
questionnaire answers. The personality traits are designed based on the
big five inventory by John et al. (1991), agreeableness,
conscientiousness, neuroticism, openness, and extroversion. For example
one variable measures conscientiousness through the average rating on
nine statements. (9) Subjects circle a number 1 through 5, where 1
stands for "strongly disagree," 2 for "disagree," 3
for "neutral," 4 for "agree," and 5 for
"strongly agree."
Table 5 presents results from the same econometric specification
run on five data samples. Column 1 includes all decisions with
disagreement, columns 2 and 3 show a breakdown of the sample into cases
where the majority or minority prevailed, respectively. We will later
comment on the other columns. The results corroborate five points.
First, there was a significant shift toward risk neutrality as stated in
Result 2 (columns 1, 2, and 3). Second, as already discussed, being in a
majority substantially raised the likelihood to prevail in case of group
disagreement (column 1). Third, subjects who are confused with the task
are less likely to prevail (columns 1 and 2). We proxied a
subject's confusion using a lottery-specific dummy for her
individual choice being different from her proposal and a
subject-specific dummy for her proposal not being monotonic. Fourth,
personality matters, in the sense that more conscientious subjects
conceded more chances to the proposal of the minority when they were in
a majority that prevailed (column 2). Fifth, skill sometimes matter but
not in an expected way: low skilled subjects were more likely to prevail
(column 2).
D. Result 4: About One Third of Groups Did Not Find Agreement
Immediately after Communication. Groups with High Skill and Science and
Engineering Members Were More Likely to Find an Immediate Agreement as
well as Those with Monotonic and More Extrovert Members
Tables 5 and 6 provide support for Result 4. Table 6 presents a
probit regression on the difficulty of reaching a group agreement in the
first attempt. Predictably, the higher the number of lotteries with
disagreement the less likely the groups would resolve disagreement
immediately. In addition, both skill and personality measures had an
impact. Groups with members with SAT/ACT score above the 75th percentile
and with monotonic proposals were more likely to find an immediate
agreement. Groups with more extrovert members were also more likely to
find an immediate agreement (also more conscientious members, albeit at
a 10% significance level). There was also a strong effect of Science and
Engineering although no gender effect was recorded. We will comment on
the impact of chat activity in Result 5.
When disagreement persists after the communication stage, group
processes may change substantially. In column 4 of Table 5 we restrict
the sample to those groups who required multiple attempts before
converging toward unanimity. Those groups faced an emergency situation
since they would have obtained 0 payoffs if they had not reached an
agreement after three attempts. When disagreement is not resolved
immediately, our previous conclusions need qualification. Putting
forward a risk-neutral proposal is no longer important in the emergency
situation (risk-neutral proposal prevailed in 95 out of 109 in one
attempt vs. 30 out of 50 in multiple attempts); different personality
traits prevailed: extroversion has now a significant impact while
conscientiousness is no longer important; finally, proposals from
Science and Engineering majors were more likely to prevail.
E. Result 5: Chat Activity Was Intense, Growing with the Level of
Disagreement and Aimed at Finding Consensus. The Amount and Timing of
Chat Messages Help to Predict Group Choices
Figures 3 and 4 and Tables 5 and 6 provide support for Result 5.
All of the 120 subjects intervened in the 2 minutes of chat time. On an
average, a person intervened 4.3 times and wrote a total of 23.9 words.
Hence, the average length of an intervention was rather short (5.6
words). Interestingly, the higher the number of decisions with
disagreement the more intense was the chat activity, suggesting that
messages were aimed at finding a common ground. With more disagreements,
participants intervened on average about the same number of times but
with longer messages (Figure 3).
Figure 4 informs about the content of the communication by giving
an uncensored list of the top 100 words employed. In the figure, the
character size is proportional to frequency of use. "A" and
"B" were the option names and were among the most frequently
used. Notice numbers 1-15, whose sizes are roughly linked to how
controversial that particular lottery decision was. "I" and
"we" suggest the tension between individual and group.
Overall, the words employed denote a very practical use of communication
to reach consensus or express opinions for or against a choice. This
content analysis did not rely on human coders, as Cooper and Kagel
(2005) but on quantitative statistics on the text, which delivered
interesting results.
[FIGURE 3 OMITTED]
The probit regressions in Tables 5 and 6 show that chat activity
helps to predict how groups resolved disagreement. In Table 5 four
variables summarized chat activity: who talked first, who talked last,
number of words written by the subject, and total number of words
written by the other two people in the group. Even without analyzing the
content of the messages, one can see the effects on whose choice
prevailed in group decision making. The persuasion effort as measured by
the number of words written paid off in the expected direction. Not
voicing your own reasons lowered someone's chances of determining
the group decision. In particular a subject with a majority proposal was
more likely to be the first to express opinions and to render the
majority proposal to prevail. A subject in a minoritarian position had
chances to convince the other two if she wrote longer messages. This
evidence is consistent with Eliaz et al. (2007)'s theory which
predicts that the majority prevails through greater voice and larger
group size and, whenever the minority prevails, voice more than
compensates for the group size.
In Table 6, four other variables that are based on the count of the
number of words summarized the chat activity: overall activity in the
group, difference in activity between the most and least active member
in the group, length of the last intervention and of the second to last
intervention. We report two major effects of chat activity on the
difficulty of reaching a group agreement in the first attempt. First,
groups with more words written in the chat can sort out disagreement
more quickly. Second, a large inequality in chat activity among group
members and more words in the second to last intervention correlate with
more difficulties of reaching a consensual group choice.
V. CONCLUSIONS
We study group decision making with the aim to understand how small
groups resolve disagreement when facing a safe versus a risky option. We
present experimental evidence both at the aggregate and at the
individual level.
[FIGURE 4 OMITTED]
In the aggregate, we report that group decisions generate a
"risky shift" in comparison to individual decisions. This
shift occurs because group choices were 4.3 percentage points more
frequently closer to risk neutrality than individual choices; groups
made choices that were less risk averse than those of their members. In
addition, group choices followed monotonicity more often than individual
choices. These aggregate results contribute to the debate on whether
group decision making generates a risky or a cautious shift. Baker et
al. (2008), Masclet et al. (2009), and Shupp and Williams (2008) all
found that groups are more risk averse than individuals. On the
contrary, Harrison et al. (2010) report no group effect. We put forward
the explanation that the attitude of group decisions over risk depends
on the interaction rules and on group size. These conjectures spring
from considering the variety of default rules adopted in the literature
in case of group disagreement. Chat communication alone did not always
generate unanimity because individuals may hold genuinely different
stands over what risks to take. In these cases, as Baker et al. (2008)
note, the unanimity rule is more likely to induce more pressure toward
conformity in groups than the majority rule. We carried out analyses of
the incentives set by alternative default rules, which makes clear that
our design gives the highest incentives to negotiate and reach
consensual decisions within the group. In addition to formal incentives,
there may be a behavioral group pressure to conform, which depends on
members' personality and group size. We did not explore differences
in group sizes but conjecture that in a group of three members, a
two-against-one situation is qualitatively different than a disagreement
in a group of two of one-against-one. In our experiment, in situations
of two-against-one the minority proposal prevailed on average in 19% of
cases. This fraction is positive but less than one third, as a random
selection would suggest, and further reduced to 14% in case the
disagreement persisted over multiple attempts to decide, which signals
an even stronger attraction toward the opinion of the group majority.
Lack of agreement caused an emergency situation because without
unanimity in a lottery choice, participants' payoff was zero for
that lottery. Agreement could eventually be reached without further
communication in a second or third attempt. In these emergency
situations, the mode of interaction within group members changed
substantially.
We report evidence that personality and communication abilities
mattered. In particular, the presence of extrovert and conscientious
members influences group choices. A conscientious subject may be more
willing to give in to minimize the chances of no choice in case of
disagreement. Extrovert subjects were more likely to push for an
immediate agreement or to voice his or her proposals when in emergency
situation. The patterns of communication in terms of amount, equality,
and timing significantly influence the outcome. In the experiment, the
more one writes relative to others, the more likely is one's
opinion to prevail. Moreover, a balanced exchange of messages among
members makes immediate agreement more likely.
To conclude, in a group with clearly outlined individual
preferences and incentives to solve disagreements, group decisions
exhibited a shift toward risk neutrality. This "risky shift"
was not found in other studies and likely depends on the incentives to
internally negotiate an agreement. We conjecture that the risk attitude
of group decisions is rule-specific: it depends on the interaction rules
in place within the group.
ABBREVIATION
CRRA: Constant Relative Risk Aversion
doi:10.1111/j.1465-7295.2010.00362.x
REFERENCES
Baker, R. J., S. K. Laury, and A. W. Williams. "Comparing
Small-Group and Individual Behavior in Lottery-Choice Experiments."
Southern Economic Journal, 75(2), 2008, 367-82.
Casari, M., J. Zhang, and C. Jackson. "Do Groups Fall Prey to
the Winner's Curse?" Working Paper No. 504, Institute for
Empirical Research in Economics, University of Zurich, 2010.
Cason, T. N., and F. U. Khan. "A Laboratory Study of Voluntary
Public Goods Provision with Imperfect Monitoring and
Communication." Journal of Development Economics, 58(2), 1999,
533-52.
Cason, T. N., and V.-L. Mui. "A Laboratory Study of Group
Polarization in the Team Dictator Game." Economic Journal,
107(444), 1997, 1465-83.
Charness, G., E. Karni, and D. Levin. "Individual and Group
Decision Making Under Risk: An Experimental Study of Bayesian Updating
and Violations of First-Order Stochastic Dominance." Journal of
Risk and Uncertainty, 35(2), 2007, 129-48.
College Board of Education. "SAT Percentile Ranks for Males,
Females, and Total Group, College-Bound Seniors--Critical Reading +
Mathematics + Writing." 2006. Accessed December 14, 2010.
http://www.collegeboard.com/prod_downloads/highered/ra/
sat/SATPercentileRanksCompositeCR_M_W.pdf.
Cooper, D. J., and J. H. Kagel. "Are Two Heads Better Than
One? Team versus Individual Play in Signaling Games." American
Economic Review, 95(33), 2005, 477-509.
Eliaz, K., D. Ray, and R. Razin, "Group Decision-Making in the
Shadow of Disagreement." Journal of Economic Theory, 132, 2007,
236-73.
Fischbacher, U. "z-Tree-Zurich Toolbox for Readymade Economic
Experiments." Experimental Economics, 10(2), 2007, 171-78.
Hackett, S., E. Schlager, and J. Walker. "The Role of
Communication in Resolving Commons Dilemmas: Experimental Evidence with
Heterogenous Appropriators."
Journal of Environmental Economics and Management, 27, 1994,
99-126.
Harrison, G.W., I.L. Morton, E.E. Rutstrom, and M. Tarazona-Gomez.
"Preferences over Social Risk."
Working Paper No. 19, J. Mack Robinson College of Business, Georgia
State University, 2010.
Holt, C. A., and S. K. Laury. "Risk Aversion and Incentive
Effects." American Economic Review, 92, 2002, 1644-55.
Isaac, R. M., and J. M. Walker. "Communication and Free-Riding
Behavior: The Voluntary Contribution Mechanism." Economic Inquiry,
26(4), 1988, 585-608.
John, O. P., E. M. Donahue, and R. L. Kentle. The Big Five
Inventory. Berkeley: University of California, 1991.
Kocher, M. G., and M. Sutter. "The Decision Maker Matters:
Individual versus Group Behavior in Experimental Beauty-Contest
Games." Economic Journal, 115(500), 2005, 200-23.
Lamm, H., and D. G. Myers. "Group-induced Polarization of
Attitudes and Behavior." Advances in Experimental Social
Psychology, 11, 1978, 145-95.
Luhan, W., M. Kocher, and M. Sutter. "Group Polarization in
the Team Dictator Game Reconsidered." Experimental Economics, 12,
2009, 26-41.
Masclet, D., Y. Loheac, D.-B. Laurent, and N. Colombier.
"Group and Individual Risk Preferences: A Lottery-Choice
Experiment." Journal of Economic Behavior and Organization, 70(3),
2009, 470-84.
Pruitt, D. G.. "Choice Shifts in Group Discussion: An
Introductory Review." Journal of Personality and Social Psychology,
20, 1971, 339-60.
Rockenbach, B., A. Sadrieh, and B. Mathauschek. "Teams Take
the Better Risks." Journal of Economic Behavior and Organization,
63, 2007, 412-22.
Shupp, R., and A. W. Williams. "Risk Preference Differentials
of Small Groups and Individuals." The Economic Journal, 118(525),
2008, 258-83.
Stoner, J. A. F. "A Comparison of Individual and Group
Decisions Under Risk." Unpublished Master's Thesis,
Massachusetts Institute of Technology, School of Management, 1961.
(1.) Tasks involving other-regarding preferences are mostly
judgemental tasks, Cason and Mui (1997) or Luhan et al. (2009). The
beauty contest game is a task with both components (Kocher and Sutter
2005).
(2.) It has been documented in the experimental literature that
pre-play face-to-face communication significantly improves cooperation
in public good game (for instance, Cason and Khan 1999; Isaac and Walker
1988) and common-pool resource experiments under conditions of
heterogeneity in resource endowment and payoffs (Hackett et al. 1994).
(3.) Shupp and Williams (2007) asked to price each lottery and then
awarded the lottery using an incentive compatible mechanism. The default
bid without unanimity is the average of individual bids.
(4.) Some multiple switches could also be a sign of preference
indifference over a certain range.
(5.) The two-sample Kolmogorov-Smirnov test rejects the equality of
two distributions of the switching points from A to B with monotonic
preference (n = 105, m = 39, p-value = 0.0476). About 58.8% of
individual proposals were for B (1.4 points more than individual
choices). The distribution of the switching points in individual
proposals does not significantly differ from group decisions
(Kolmogorov-Smirnov test, n = 108, m = 39, p-value = 0.978), neither
from individual choices (Kolmogorov-Smirnov test, n = 108, m = 105,
p-value = 0.998).
(6.) Without pretence of generality, below we illustrate this
point. Consider a game with two players with different risk attitudes
who choose between a safe option S = 50 and a risky option R = (150, p;
0, 1 - p). Assume player 1 has a CRRA utility function and is risk
averse, u(x), u'> 0, u" < 0 and player 2 is risk
neutral, v(x) = x. Assume disagreement, that is player I prefers S, U[S]
> U[R], and player 2 prefers R, V[S] < V[R]: u(50)> pu(150) and
50 < 150 p, which implies that 1/3 < p < u(50)/u(150). One can
show that for lotteries 9-15 we have that V[R]/V[S] > U[S]/U[R],
i.e., 3[p.sup.2] > u(50)/u(150), which holds for p > l/sqrt(3)
and, given the actual values of p, for lotteries 9-15. There were
instances of disagreement also for lotteries 6-8.
(7.) The group reached agreement on 12 of the 15 lottery choices
(disagreement over lotteries 8-10). Analyses with 159 groups (477
proposals) dropped those three observations while analyses with 162
groups (486 proposals) replaced those three group lottery choices with
the individual inputs in the third attempt to reach a group decision.
(8.) These differences are not statistically significant.
(9.) I do a thorough job. I do things efficiently. I make plans and
follow through. I am a reliable worker. I persevere until the task is
finished. I am easily distracted. I can be somewhat careless. I tend to
be lazy. I tend to be disorganized.
JINGJING ZHANG and MARCO CASARI *
* This project was developed while both authors were at Purdue
University, which provided an excellent research environment. We are
grateful to Christine Jackson for her support and contribution of ideas.
We thank Anya Savikhin for valuable research assistance, Tim Cason for
comments on an earlier version of the paper as well as seminar
participants at the IMEBE meeting in Alicante, Spain, CapuaLabSi
meeting, Italy, ESA meeting in Lyon, France. Two anonymous referees made
useful suggestions. J.Z. wishes to thank McMaster University for support
during her post-doc when the paper was completed.
Zhang: Assistant Professor, Institute for Empirical Research in
Economics, University of Zurich, Blumlisalpstrasse 10, Zurich CH-8006,
Switzerland. Phone +41-44-634-5562, Fax +41-44-634-4907, E-mail
zhang148@gmail. com
Casari: Associate Professor, Department of Economics, University of
Bologna, Piazza Scaravilli 2, Bologna 40126, Italy. Phone
+39-51-209-8662, Fax +39-51-209-8493, E-mail marco.casari@unibo.it
TABLE 1
Design Comparison across Five Studies of Group Lottery Choices
Includes Group
Number of Between- Composition
Groups in the Subject across
Experiment Design Choices
Zhang and Casari (this study) 40 No Fixed
Masclet et al. 2009 36 No Random
Shupp and Williams 2007 28 Yes Fixed
Baker et al. 2008 40 Yes Fixed
Harrison et al. 2010 36 No Fixed
Maximum
Default Choice Attempts to
When No Group Reach Group
Unanimity Choice
Zhang and Casari (this study) None (zero earnings) 3
Masclet et al. 2009 Random 5
Shupp and Williams 2007 Mean of individual bids 1
Baker et al. 2008 Majority rule 1
Harrison et al. 2010 Majority rule l
Every Individual
Posts a
Nonbinding
Proposal
Zhang and Casari (this study) Yes
Masclet et al. 2009 No
Shupp and Williams 2007 No
Baker et al. 2008 No
Harrison et al. 2010 No
Communication
Zhang and Casari (this study) Chat (2 min)
Masclet et al. 2009 None
Shupp and Williams 2007 Face-to-face (20 min)
Baker et al. 2008 Face-to-face
Harrison et al. 2010 None
Positive Incentives to
Talk/Listen to Others
Zhang and Casari (this study) Yes/yes
Masclet et al. 2009 Yes/no
Shupp and Williams 2007 Yes/no (a)
Baker et al. 2008 Yes for minority/no
Harrison et al. 2010 Yes for minority/no
(a) It may be "yes/yes," a short explanation follows. Shupp and
Williams (2007) asked to price each lottery and then awarded the
lottery using an incentive compatible mechanism. The default bid
without unanimity is the average of individual bids. An individual
player may have an incentive to manipulate the group price by
strategically over- or under-bidding in order to generate a
group bid closer to her preferred level.
TABLE 2
Lottery Choice Task
Option A Option B
Probability Expected
Lottery of Getting Payoff of
Number Payoffs Payoffs 150 Tokens Option B
1 50 150 or 0 0 0
2 50 150 or 0 0.05 7.5
3 50 150 or 0 0.1 15
4 50 150 or 0 0.15 22.5
5 50 150 or 0 0.2 30
6 50 150 or 0 0.25 37.5
7 50 150 or 0 0.3 45
8 50 150 or 0 0.35 52.5
9 50 150 or 0 0.4 60
10 50 150 or 0 0.45 67.5
11 50 150 or 0 0.5 75
12 50 150 or 0 0.55 82.5
13 50 150 or 0 0.6 90
14 50 150 or 0 0.65 97.5
15 50 150 or 0 0.7 105
Percentage of monotonic decision makers
Individual Individual Group
Risk Preference Choices Proposals Choices
Range of CRRA if
Switch from A to B Frequency Frequency Frequency
Lottery at the Following of Choices of Choices of Choices
Number Lottery for B (%) for B (%) for B (%)
1 r < -1.73 0 0.8 0
2 -1.73 < r < -1.1 0 0 0
3 -1.1 < r < -0.73 1.7 0 0
4 -0.73 < r < -0.47 0 0 0
5 -0.47 < r < -0.27 1.7 0 0
6 -0.27 < r < -0.1 5 2.5 0
7 -0.1 < r < 0.04 5.8 6.7 2.5
8 0.04 < r < 0.16 15 20 16.7
9 0.16 < r < 0.27 24.2 26.7 21.7
10 0.27 < r < 0.36 31.7 32.5 36.7
11 0.36 < r < 0.45 58.3 58.3 65
12 0.45 < r < 0.53 68.3 67.5 80
13 0.53 < r < 0.6 80 80 87.5
14 0.6 < r < 0.66 88.3 90.8 95
15 0.66 < r 93.3 95 97.5
87.5 90 95
Notes: Everyone should choose Option A in decision 1. Risk-neutral
subjects would switch to Option B in decision 8. A switch in
later decisions reveals risk aversion and a switch in earlier
decisions reveals risk-seeking behavior. CRRA stands for a utility
function exhibiting constant relative risk aversion. Number of
individual observations for each line is 120.
TABLE 3
Risk Neutrality When Disagreement
Majority Minority
Prevailed Prevailed
Majority at risk 79 12 91
neutrality (57.2%)
Minority at risk 50 18 68
neutrality (42.8%)
Totals 129 30 159
(81.1%) (18.9%) (100%)
Notes: The unit of observation is a decision a group
made in a lottery in part 2. This table includes only
group decisions with disagreement (159/600 obs.). The
table compares individual proposals with group choice. The
majority proposal was A when AAB and B when ABB.
TABLE 4
Risky Shift When Disagreement
Majority Minority
Prevailed Prevailed
Majority more risky 68 11 79
(49.7%)
Minority more risky 61 19 80
(50.3%)
Totals 129 30 159
Notes: The unit of observation is a decision a group
made in a lottery in part 2. This table includes only
group decisions with disagreement (159/600 obs.). The
table compares individual proposals with group choice. The
majority proposal was A when AAB and B when ABB.
TABLE 5
Probit Regression on How Groups Resolve Disagreement
Sample: Decisions with Disagreement Only
Dependent variable: Majority
1 = my proposal equals group choice, All Prevails
0 = otherwise (1) (2)
Independent variables:
My proposal was the risk-neutral choice 0.20 * 0.14 *
(1 or 0) (0.103) (0.060)
My proposal was in the majority (1 or 0) 0.65 ** --
(0.081) --
My individual choice was different -0.27 -0.40 *
than my proposal (0.138) (0.191)
My proposals were not monotonic (1 or 0) -0.29 ** -0.19
(0.074) (0.103)
Number of lottery decisions on which 0.00 0.00
the group disagree (0.011) (0.010)
Multiple attempts to decide (1 or 0) 0.05 0.04
(0.048) (0.036)
Chat messages
I talked first (1 or 0) 0.08 0.09 *
(0.066) (0.036)
I talked last (1 or 0) -0.10 -0.06
(0.058) (0.030)
Number of words I wrote in my group (x 100) 0.18 -0.19
(0.453) (0.190)
Number of words that all other members wrote -0.38 -0.36 **
(x 100) (0.253) (0.111)
Demographics
Science and Engineering Major (I or 0) 0.07 0.06
(0.079) (0.034)
Above 75 percentile SAT/ACT (1 or 0) 0.05 0.04
(0.059) (0.035)
Below 25 percentile SAT/ACT (1 or 0) 0.09 0.08 **
(0.076) (0.028)
Male (1 or 0) -0.03 -0.03
(0.080) (0.041)
Missing SAT/ACT or demographic data (1 or 0) 0.10 0.06
(0.085) (0.033)
Personality traits
Agreeableness 0.00 0.01
(0.045) (0.029)
Conscientiousness -0.10 -0.08 *
(0.059) (0.038)
Neuroticism -0.01 -0.03
(0.066) (0.035)
Openness 0.02 0.00
(0.050) (0.027)
Extroversion 0.00 0.00
(0.048) (0.021)
Number of observations 477 318
Pseudo [R.sup.2] 0.361 0.284
Log likelihood -204.7 -110.2
Sample: Decisions with Disagreement Only Multiple
Dependent variable: Minority Attempts
1 = my proposal equals group choice, Prevails before
0 = otherwise (3) Unanimity
Independent variables: (4)
My proposal was the risk-neutral choice 0.15 * 0.09
(1 or 0) (0.063) (0.114)
My proposal was in the majority (1 or 0) -- 0.71 **
-- (0.160)
My individual choice was different 0.05 -0.38 **
than my proposal (0.120) (0.144)
My proposals were not monotonic (1 or 0) -0.07 -0.23
(0.043) (0.118)
Number of lottery decisions on which 0.00 -0.03
the group disagree (0.019) (0.034)
Multiple attempts to decide (1 or 0) -0.06 --
(0.073) --
Chat messages
I talked first (1 or 0) 0.10 -0.07
(0.083) (0.129)
I talked last (1 or 0) -0.06 0.14
(0.048) (0.103)
Number of words I wrote in my group (x 100) 0.55 ** 0.04
(0.210) (0.429)
Number of words that all other members wrote 0.16 -0.49 **
(x 100) (0.176) (0.181)
Demographics
Science and Engineering Major (I or 0) -0.06 0.29 **
(0.071) (0.103)
Above 75 percentile SAT/ACT (1 or 0) -0.02 -0.05
(0.059) (0.138)
Below 25 percentile SAT/ACT (1 or 0) 0.08 0.00
(0.097) (0.085)
Male (1 or 0) 0.04 0.17
(0.082) (0.187)
Missing SAT/ACT or demographic data (1 or 0) -0.02 -0.33
(0.056) (0.339)
Personality traits
Agreeableness 0.03 0.00
(0.037) (0.105)
Conscientiousness 0.01 0.15
(0.082) (0.129)
Neuroticism 0.01 0.08
(0.053) (0.205)
Openness 0.00 0.06
(0.052) (0.090)
Extroversion 0.00 0.20 **
(0.056) (0.062)
Number of observations 159 150
Pseudo [R.sup.2] 0.205 0.498
Log likelihood -61.23 -49.97
Sample: Decisions with Disagreement Only One
Dependent variable: Attempt
1 = my proposal equals group choice, before
0 = otherwise Unanimity
Independent variables: (5)
My proposal was the risk-neutral choice 0.34 **
(1 or 0) (0.121)
My proposal was in the majority (1 or 0) 0.63 **
(0.112)
My individual choice was different -0.33 *
than my proposal (0.158)
My proposals were not monotonic (1 or 0) -0.32 **
(0.116)
Number of lottery decisions on which 0.01
the group disagree (0.011)
Multiple attempts to decide (1 or 0) --
--
Chat messages
I talked first (1 or 0) 0.04
(0.074)
I talked last (1 or 0) -0.11
(0.074)
Number of words I wrote in my group (x 100) 0.15
(0.579)
Number of words that all other members wrote -0.30
(x 100) (0.334)
Demographics
Science and Engineering Major (I or 0) 0.03
(0.094)
Above 75 percentile SAT/ACT (1 or 0) 0.21 **
(0.057)
Below 25 percentile SAT/ACT (1 or 0) 0.20 **
(0.068)
Male (1 or 0) -0.17 *
(0.084)
Missing SAT/ACT or demographic data (1 or 0) 0.23 **
(0.084)
Personality traits
Agreeableness -0.05
(0.055)
Conscientiousness -0.11
(0.083)
Neuroticism -0.06
(0.069)
Openness 0.04
(0.056)
Extroversion -0.03
(0.050)
Number of observations 327
Pseudo [R.sup.2] 0.375
Log likelihood -137.9
Notes: Marginal effects, robust standard errors in parentheses,
clusters on groups. Sample: decisions with disagreement only.
The regression includes lottery decision dummies, which have
not been reported in the table. One group did not agree on three
lottery decisions and those decisions are excluded from this table.
Statistical significance ** p < .01, * p < .05.
TABLE 6
Probit Regression on Group Difficulty of Reaching an Agreement
Sample: Decisions with Disagreement Only
Dependent variable:
1 = my group required more than one
attempt to decide; 0 = otherwise
Independent variables:
My proposal was the risk-neutral choice (0/1) -0.02
(0.068)
My individual choice was different than my proposal 0.07
(0.116)
My proposals were not monotonic (0/1) 0.40 **
(0.139)
Number of lotteries with disagreement in the group 0.17 **
(0.051)
Number of words written overall by group (x 100) -0.57
(0.313)
Number of words written in the last intervention (x 100) 0.02
(0.020)
Number of words written in the second to last 0.04 **
intervention (x 100) (0.012)
Difference in words written between the most and 1.35 *
the least active individual (x 100) (0.617)
Science and engineering major -0.28 **
(0.104)
Above 75 percentile SAT/ACT -0.19 *
(0.076)
Below 25 percentile SAT/ACT 0.03
(0.111)
Male 0.12
(0.088)
Missing SAT/ACT or demographic data 0.04
(0.113)
Agreeableness -0.01
(0.060)
Conscientiousness -0.14
(0.074)
Neuroticism 0.06
(0.073)
Openness -0.10
(0.090)
Extroversion -0.14 *
(0.063)
Observations 477
Pseudo [R.sup.2] 0.523
Log likelihood -141.8
Notes: Marginal effects, robust standard errors in parentheses,
clusters on groups. Sample: decisions with disagreement only.
The regression includes lottery decision dummies, which have not
been reported in the table.
Statistical significance ** p < 0.01, * p < 0.05.