Mutual admiration clubs.
Suen, Wing
Birds of a feather flock together; presumably, they admire their
peers' plumage. There is a wealth of evidence that members of a
particular social group evaluate in-group members more favorably than
out-group members (e.g., Brewer and Kramer 1985; Brown 1986). At least
two possible explanations can account for this observation. One is that
repeated interactions within a group produce feelings of solidarity and
identification, which lead to mutual admiration. Alternatively, people
who appreciate one another may self-select into the same social group.
Economics has little to add to the first explanation. Accordingly, this
article pursues the second line of argument.
The social contacts that a person has are influenced by his social
roles and by factors such as physical proximity, but they are also a
matter of choice. People choose whom to make friends with. Casual
observation as well as academic research indicates that attitudinal
similarity is a major determinant of interpersonal attraction and
positive social judgment (e.g., Byrne 1971; McElwee et al. 2001; Newcomb
1961; Wittenbaum, Hubbell, and Zuckerman 1999). In other words, even
after controlling for socioeconomic status, people prefer to associate
with those who share similar views as their own. In his book
Republic.com, Sunstein (2001) describes how the advent of information
technology has enormously expanded the range of social contacts
available to individuals. By logging into Internet chat rooms, for
example, the choice of conversation partners is not confined by physical
distance or social status. But instead of increasing the exchange of
opinion among people of diverse viewpoints, Sunstein argues that
information technology has led to an increasing fragmentation of the
social space. The reason is that people choose to expose themselves only
to familiar viewpoints, and technology has facilitated a more precise
matching of individuals who share similar attitudes.
In this article, I develop a model of group formation, which
explains why people prefer to exchange information with like-minded
individuals. In this model, people are differentiated by their prior
beliefs about some unknown state. They receive private information about
the state and exchange their information with others in their group.
There are two types of private signals. Informed persons observe real
signals that are partially revealing about the state, while uninformed
persons observe bogus signals that are pure noise but are believed to be
informative. I assume that an individual derives utility from learning
real signals; hence, each tries to join the group that is believed to
contain the largest proportion of informed persons.
Internet chat rooms provide a convenient metaphor for the nature of
the problem. Of the many chat rooms that focus on a particular subject,
the choice of which one to join depends on who else is present in each
chat room. I may enter a chat room that I believe contains cogent and
insightful arguments related to the subject. But other people in the
chat room may leave because they think that the quality of the arguments
deteriorates as I enter the discussion. It is therefore possible that
this kind of situation may admit no equilibrium, as is driven by the
logic of Groucho Marx's dictum. (1) Nevertheless, for the setup
described in this article, equilibrium can be proved to exist. In this
equilibrium, society is segmented into two or more distinct groups.
Members of each group prefer to canvass opinion from one another than to
sample views from people in other groups because everyone believes that
members
of his own group are smarter (i.e., more likely to be informed) than
those of other groups. Moreover, the equilibrium has the interesting
property that each group consists of individuals who share similar
beliefs; people with disparate views do not mingle together.
The intuition behind this result is not difficult to understand.
Since each person--informed or not--believes that his own private signal
is informative, each will revise his prior in the direction of the
signal. As informative signals are correlated with the state while
uninformative signals are not, this updating process implies that the
distribution of posterior beliefs among informed persons is more
clustered near the true state than is the distribution of posterior
beliefs among uninformed persons. Therefore, for a person who believes
that the state is [[theta].sub.0], say, he expects to find a high
concentration of informed persons among a group of people with posterior
beliefs near [[theta].sub.0]. To put it differently, this person finds
it unlikely that informed persons who have amended their priors based on
real signals would have posteriors that are far away from
[[theta].sub.0]. He concludes that a group of people with beliefs far
away from his own beliefs must consist predominantly of uninformed
persons; learning from their bogus signals would add little to his
utility. To be sure, such feelings are mutual. People with beliefs far
away from [[theta].sub.0] do not want to associate with those with
beliefs near [[theta].sub.0] as they think that the other group must
have been influenced by pure noise. In this model, people evaluate
others through the lens of their own beliefs. There is no commonly
agreed yardstick of who are informed and who are not. This explains why
the model can escape from Groucho Marx's logic to admit an
equilibrium social structure.
The mechanism presented in this article is related to Prendergast
(1993). Prendergast shows that using subjective information to evaluate
the performance of subordinates produces an incentive for subordinates
to conform to the opinion of their supervisors. Similarly, Gentzkow and
Shapiro (2006) argue that when there is uncertainty regarding whether
information providers are well informed, consumers of information infer
that those who produce reports that conform to consumers' priors
are more likely to be competent. This article does not discuss the
strategic and organizational issues arising from conformity but focuses
on the implications of subjective evaluation for equilibrium social
structure.
This model of equilibrium social structure shaped by differences in
beliefs is closest to the recent work by Murphy and Shleifer (2004).
They assume that agents with beliefs that are too dissimilar cannot
influence one another. Therefore, the size of any group cannot be too
large, and the centers of any two groups must be sufficiently far apart.
This article seeks to go one step further by explaining why agents
prefer to be influenced by people with similar beliefs.
Currarini, Jackson, and Pin (forthcoming) study the effects of
homophily ("love of own kind") on the formation of friendship
networks. In their model, individuals prefer to make friends with others
with similar demographic characteristics (such as race), producing
network structure with a high degree of clustering. The present work
does not adopt a network-theoretic approach. Individuals are
differentiated along a continuous dimension (their subjective beliefs),
but the desire to seek informed opinion leads to their partitioning into
distinct social groups.
I. THE STRUCTURE OF INFORMATION AND MISINFORMATION
There are two possible states of the world, [s.sub.L] and
[s.sub.R]. The prior probability that an individual attaches to state
[s.sub.R] is denoted p. Sometimes, it is convenient to work with log
odds ratios instead of probabilities; so, I denote [rho] = log(p/(1 -
p)). Assume a continuum of agents with different priors. Let F([rho])
represent the mass of population with a prior log odds ratio lower than
[rho].
A fraction [pi] of the population are informed. Assume that whether
a person is informed or not does not depend on his beliefs. An informed
individual i receives a private signal [Y.sub.i] that is partially
revealing about the true state. In particular, assume
Pr[Y.sub.i] = L|[S.sub.L]] = Pr[[Y.sub.i] = R |[s.sub.R]] = q
[member of] (0.5, 1).
Let k = log(q/(1 - q)). By Bayes' rule, an individual who
observes [Y.sub.i] = R will have a posterior log odds ratio of
[rho]' = [rho] + k. Similarly, an individual who observes [Y.sub.i]
= L will have a posterior log odds ratio of [rho]' = [rho] - k.
Conditional on the state, the signal [Y.sub.i] is identically and
independently distributed across informed individuals.
A fraction 1 - [pi] of the population are uninformed. Each
uninformed agent i receives a bogus signal [X.sub.i] such that,
regardless of the underlying state,
Pr[[X.sub.i] = L] = Pr[[X.sub.i] = R] = 0.5.
These signals are independently distributed across uninformed
agents.
Since the distribution of the bogus signals does not depend on the
state, they are totally uninformative. Uninformed individuals are aware
that only a fraction [pi] of the population are informed. However, each
uninformed person believes that he himself is among one of the blessed.
That is, an uninformed individual mistakenly thinks that his private
signal is [Y.sub.i]. Hence, a person who observes [X.sub.i] = R revises
his posterior to [rho]' = [rho] + k, and a person who observes
[X.sub.i] = L revises his posterior to [rho]' = [rho] - k. (2)
II. SOCIAL NETWORKS AND INFORMATION EXCHANGE
Because of the assumption that signals are independently
distributed across the population, individuals will further update their
beliefs if they know the realization of the private signals of other
informed agents. People therefore have an incentive to exchange
information and learn from one another. Unlike random sampling, much of
this kind of informational exchange occurs along established social
ties. People do not talk to just anyone on the street; they mostly talk
to their friends. Even when the informational flow is one way, the
search for information is seldom random. People do not ask just any
expert for advice; they ask their trusted experts. Such nonrandom
selection would make sense if a person believes that people in his
social group are systematically more well informed than other agents in
the population. But how do different individuals arrive at the
conclusion that their own social groups are superior?
Some notation is needed to clarify the nature of this problem. Let
there be two social groups in the population, labeled L and R. I assume
that social groups are formed after each individual has received his
private signal and that the exchange of information takes place only
within members of the same group. Suppose all individuals with posterior
belief [rho]' [member of] A belongs to group L, and all individuals
with belief [rho]' [not member of] A belongs to group R. Such a
partition is an equilibrium if L is preferred to R by all [rho]'
[member of] A and R is preferred to L by all [rho]' [not member of]
A. To focus on the interesting case, I require that the preference is
strict for at least some individuals.
To give content to this definition, I need to specify preferences
over social groups. Let [[phi].sup.j.sub.i](A) be the ratio of informed
to uninformed persons in group j(j =L, R) in state [s.sub.i](i = L, R).
Individuals do not directly observe the fraction of informed agents in a
group, but they form expectations about this quantity using their
subjective beliefs. Let p' be the posterior probability corresponding to the posterior log odds ratio [rho]'. I assume that
the expected utility from joining group j (j = L, R) for a person with
posterior probability p' is
[U.sup.j](p'; A) = p'u([[phi].sup.j.sub.R](A)) + (1 -
p')u([phi].sup.j.sub.L] (A)), (1)
where u is an increasing function.
This assumption about people's objective function departs from
standard decision theory, which postulates that individuals seek
information in order to improve the quality of their decisions. Suen
(2004) describes a model in which people seek information to improve
their decisions. In that model, experts coarsen continuous information
into binary signals, and individuals prefer to consult experts who share
similar preferences and beliefs as their own. More generally, the cheap
talk literature (e.g., Crawford and Sobel 1982) shows that preference
similarity tends to facilitate communication and improve the quality of
decision making. While I do not deny the instrumental value of
information, I argue that this is not the only--perhaps not even the
dominant--motive for seeking information in some situations. Consider,
for example, the consumption of political news and opinion. The
probability that a voter is pivotal in any large election is negligible.
Yet people do talk about politics and social issues with friends, and
some spend considerable time and effort to follow campaign information.
They may be doing this for the sheer fun of it, or they may be trying to
educate themselves or to impress upon others. If academics specialize in
the disinterested pursuit of truth, it is not hard to imagine that other
people may also treat information as a good in itself. But people do not
want to consume just any piece of information; they want to consume
informed opinion. Learning from a novel and valid argument is a delight,
while listening to empty chatter, cliche, or falsehood can be a pain.
This is reflected in the assumption that utility u is an increasing
function of the ratio of informed to uninformed agents in the group.
Alternatively, one may imagine that the primary motive behind the
choice of social groups is to establish social contacts and networks
with successful people for future career advancement or business
opportunities; the exchange of information is merely incidental to this
dominant motive. If this is the case, and to the extent that informed
individuals are more intelligent and more likely to be (or become)
successful people, then there are gains from joining a group with a
greater fraction of informed agents.
With Equation (1) as the criterion for the choice of social group,
the following lemma holds.
LEMMA 1. Any equilibrium in which at least some individuals
strictly prefer one group to another is characterized by a critical [??]
such that a person with posterior belief p' [less than or equal to]
[??] belongs to one group and a person with p' > [??] belongs to
the other group.
Proof Let [a.sub.i] be the fraction of all informed agents who
belong to group L under state [s.sub.i] (i = L, R). Let b be the
fraction of all uninformed agents who belong to group L. (Note that b is
state independent because bogus signals are state independent.) Then,
[[phi].sup.L.sub.L] = [[pi].sub.aL]/((l - [pi])b);
[[phi].sup.L.sub.R] = [[pi].sub.aR]/((l - [pi])b)
Similarly,
[[phi].sup.R.sub.L] = [pi](1 - [a.sub.L]/((l - [pi] (1 - b));
[[phi].sup.R.sub.R] = [pi](1 - [a.sub.R]/((l - [pi] (1 - b)).
If [a.sub.L] > [a.sub.R], then [[phi].sup.L.sub.L] >
[[phi].sup.L.sub.R] and [[phi].sup.R.sub.R] > [[phi].sup.R.sub.L]. In
this case, [U.sup.L](p'; A) - [U.sup.R](p'; A) is strictly
decreasing in p'. So, if an individual with belief [P.sub.0]
prefers L to R, all individuals with P'< [P.sub.0] prefer L and
R. If [a.sub.L] < aR, then [U.sup.L](p'; A) - [U.sup.R](p';
A) is strictly increasing in p'. So, if individual with belief Po
prefers L to R, all individuals with p'> [P.sub.0] have the same
preference. Finally, if [a.sub.L] = [a.sub.R], then either everybody
strictly prefers one group to another or everybody is indifferent
between the two groups. Q.E.D.
Lemma 1 reduces the problem of finding an equilibrium partition to
the problem of finding a critical value [??]. (3) Assume without loss of
generality that all agents with p' [less than or equal to] [??] are
in group L. Let [??] = log([??]/(1 - [??])). Then, any agent whose prior
is less than [??] + k and who observes a signal value of L will belong
to this group. Any agent whose prior is less than [??] - k and who
observes a signal value of R will also belong to this group. Therefore,
[MATHEMATICAL EXPRESSION NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII].
Since q > 1 - q and F([??])+ k) > F([??]-k), the relative
proportion of informed to uninformed persons in group L is larger when
the state is [s.sub.L] than when the state is [s.sub.R]. This reflects
the fact that informed individuals tend to revise their beliefs toward
the truth. If the true state is sc, informed individuals will have a
smaller posterior for se than average. One is then more likely to meet
an informed person among a group of individuals whose posterior for
[s.sub.R] is small.
Since u([[phi].sup.L.sub.L]) > u([[phi].sup.L.sub.R]), Equation
(1) implies that [U.sup.L](p'; [??]) is decreasing in p'.
Thus, the incentive to join a group with low values of p' (i.e.,
group L) is higher among individuals with low values of p'.
Similarly, let S = 1 - F. Then, the ratio of informed to uninformed
persons in group R in each state is given by
[MATHEMATICAL EXPRESSION NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII].
Since u([[phi].sup.R.sub.R]) > u([[phi].sup.R.sub.L]), the
function [U.sup.R](p'; [??]) is increasing in p'. Thus,
individuals with high values of p' have a greater incentive to join
group R. This means that individuals with different beliefs p' have
the tendency to segregate themselves into two distinct social groups.
Indeed, the following result holds.
PROPOSITION 1. An equilibrium [??] [member of] (0, 1) exists such
that any individual with posterior belief p' [less than or equal
to] [??] prefers group L to R and any individual with p' > [??]
prefers group R to L.
Proof The critical value [??] is defined by the indifference
condition
(2) [MATHEMATICAL EXPRESSION NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII].
Since [[phi].sup.L.sub.R]([rho]) < [pi]/(1 - [pi]) <
[[phi].sup.L.sub.L]([rho]) and [[phi].sup.R.sub.R]([rho]) > [pi]/(1 -
[pi]) > [[phi].sup.R.sub.L]([rho]) for all [rho], the left-hand side of Equation (2) is strictly greater than the right-hand side when [??]
is sufficiently close to 0, while the reverse is true when [??] is
sufficiently close to 1. By the intermediate value theorem, a solution
[??] [member of] (0, 1) to the indifference condition exists. Q.E.D.
Proposition 1 establishes existence but not necessarily uniqueness
of equilibrium. In general, the equilibrium value of [??] depends on the
form of the distribution F. The following result allows one to sidestep this dependence with an assumption about the utility function u.
COROLLARY 1. If the utility function u is linear, then [??] = 0.5
is the unique equilibrium for any distribution function F.
Proof The indifference condition Equation (2) can be written as
[??]/1 - [??] = u([[phi].sup.L.sub.L]) - u
([[phi].sup.R.sub.L]/u[[phi].sup.R.sub.R] - u[[phi].sup.L.sub.R].
When u is linear, the right-hand side of this equation is
identically equal to 1. Hence, [??] = 0.5 is the only equilibrium.
Q.E.D.
The equilibrium concept introduced in this section assumes that
individuals have to choose to join exclusively one group or another. In
some settings, it may be appropriate to allow the possibility that some
individuals can sample randomly from the population at large without
joining any exclusive groups. Since the overall fraction of informed
agents is [pi], an individual who chooses not to join any group has
utility u([pi]/(1 - [pi])). Note that u([[phi].sup.L.sub.L]) >
u([pi]/(1 - [pi])) > u([[phi].sup.L.sub.R]). Hence, a person always
prefers joining group L to sampling randomly from the population if his
belief p' is sufficiently small. We have the following result.
PROPOSITION 2. Suppose the utility function u is weakly concave.
Then, there exists [[??].sub.L] [less than or equal to] 0.5 [less than
or equal to] [P.sub.R] such that any individual with posterior belief
p' [less than or equal to] [p.sub.L] prefers to join group L, any
individual with p' [greater than or equal to] [[??].sub.R] prefers
to join group R, and any individual with p' [member of]
([[??].sub.L], [[??].sub.R]) prefers not to join any group. When u is
linear, no one strictly prefers not to join an exclusive group.
Proof Let [[??].sub.L] = log([[??].sub.L]/(1 - [[??].sub.L])). The
marginal type [[??].sub.L] is determined by the indifference condition
(3) [MATHEMATICAL EXPRESSION NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII].
Since [[phi].sup.L.sub.L] > [pi](1 [pi]/1 - [pi] >
[[phi].sup.L.sub.R], the left-hand side is strictly greater than the
right-hand side when [[??].sub.L] is sufficiently close to 0. By
Jensen's inequality, at [[??].sub.L] = 0.5, the left-hand side of
Equation (3) is less than or equal to u(0.5 [[phi].sup.L.sub.R] + 0.5
[[phi].sup.L.sub.L]) = u([pi]/1 - [pi])). Hence, there exists a
[[??].sub.L] [member of] (0, 0.5) such that the indifference condition
is satisfied. Moreover, since [U.sup.L](p'; [[??].sub.L]) is
decreasing in p', every individual with p' < [[??].sub.L]
strictly prefers sampling exclusively from group L to sampling from the
general population. The proof that [[??].sub.R] [member of] [0.5, 1)
follows the same logic. Q.E.D.
Proposition 2 shows that even when individuals are not required to
join any exclusive group, those with extreme beliefs still prefer to
collect information from like-minded persons than to sample randomly
from the population. Only individuals with moderate beliefs prefer not
to join any exclusive groups. Moreover, if u is linear, the equilibrium
entails [[??].sub.L] = [[??].sub.R] = 0.5. In this case, every
individual prefers to join one of the two exclusive groups.
III. MULTIPLE GROUPS
In an environment with binary states, it is natural to consider an
equilibrium in which the population self-select into two distinct
groups. If the model is extended to a richer state space, the pattern of
equilibrium group formation can be more complex. In particular,
individuals with moderate beliefs may prefer to interact with one
another than with people who hold more extreme views. It turns out that
the existence of a multiple-group equilibrium is not merely a
straightforward generalization of the two-group case. Proposition 3
below shows that the existence of moderate groups depends on, among
other things, the variance of the informative signal relative to that of
the bogus signal. If the variance of the bogus signal is either too
large or too small, equilibrium can only support two polar groups. A
general discussion of multiple-group equilibrium with unrestricted state
space is beyond the scope of this article. In this section, I study the
possibility of a three-group equilibrium when the state variable is a
one-dimensional continuous variable using some specific assumptions
regarding functional forms. In particular, I assume that the utility
function u(*) from group membership is a linear function and that the
updation of beliefs follows the linear Bayesian updating rule for
normally distributed signals. A fuller treatment of multiplegroup
equilibrium has to await further work.
Suppose the underlying state variable is represented by a
one-dimensional variable [theta] on the real line. Different individuals
have different prior beliefs about [theta]. Let person i's beliefs
about [theta] be described by the normal distribution N([[mu].sub.i], v)
with mean [[mu].sub.i] and variance v. The distribution of the prior
mean [[mu].sub.i] across the population is given by the distribution
function F. That is, the mass of population with prior mean [[mu].sup.i]
[less than or equal to] m is equal to F(m).
A fraction [pi] of the population are informed. Each informed
person observes an informative signal [Y.sub.i] = [theta] +
[[epsilon].sup.y.sub.i], where [[epsilon].sup.y.sub.i] is independent of
[theta] and is distributed N(0, [[tau].sub.y]). The remainder of the
population are uninformed. An uninformed person i observes a bogus
signal [X.sub.i] = [[epsilon].sup.x.sub.i] which is distributed N(0,
[tau]x). As in Section I, all individuals believe that their own signals
are informative. Upon observing signal [Z.sub.i] ([Z.sub.i] = [X.sub.i],
[Y.sub.i]), person i updates his posterior mean about [theta] to
[[mu]'.sub.i] = (1 - [beta])[[mu].sub.i] + [beta] [Z.sub.i],
where [beta] = [upsilon]/([upsilon] + [[tau].sub.y]).
Define the function [??] to be the distribution of the variable (1
- [beta])[[mu].sub.i] + [beta] [[epsilon].sup.y.sub.i]. That is,
[??](m) = [[integral].sup.[infinity].sub.-[infinity]] F (m - [beta]
[[epsilon].sup.y])/1 - [beta]) n ([[epsilon].sup.y]; [[tau].sub.y]) d
[[epsilon].sup.y]
where n(x; [[tau].sub.y].) is the normal density function with mean
0 and variance [[tau].sub.y]. Then, conditional on [theta], the mass of
informed agents with posterior mean less than m is [pi][??](m -
[beta][theta]). Similarly, let G denotes the distribution of the
variable (1 - [beta]) [[mu].sub.i] + [beta] [[epsilon].sup.x.sub.i]:
G (m) = [[integral].sup.[infinity].sub.-[infinity]] F (m - [beta]
[[epsilon].sup.x]/1 - [beta]) n ([[epsilon].sup.x]; [[tau].sub.x])
d[[epsilon].sup.x].
The mass of uninformed agents with posterior mean less than m is
given by (1 - [pi])G(m). For future reference, let g represent the
density functions corresponding to G.
Let [[phi].sup.j] ([theta]) be the ratio of informed to uninformed
agents in group j(j = 1, 2, ..., J) under state [theta]. The utility
from joining group j for a person with posterior mean [mu]' is
given by
(4) [U.sup.j] ([mu]') = E [u ([[phi].sup.j] (0))],
where the expectation is taken using the subjective posterior
distribution over [theta]. I assume that the utility function u is
linear for the subsequent analysis.
Consider an equilibrium in which people with beliefs [mu]'
[member of] [[[??].sub.j-1], [[??].sub.j] belong to group j. (Set
[[??].sub.0] = - [infinity] and [[??].sub.j] = [infinity].) Then,
Equation (4) can be written as
(5) [MATHEMATICAL EXPRESSION NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII],
The expression for H follows from the fact that the posterior
variance of [theta] is (1 - [beta]) [upsilon].
It is straightforward to see from Equation (5) and from the
definition of [[??].sub.0] and [[??].sub.j] that [U.sup.1] is monotonic decreasing in [mu]', while [U.sup.J] is monotonic increasing in
[mu]'. Thus, people with extreme beliefs tend to prefer the extreme
groups. (4) The following lemma characterizes people's preference
for the less extreme groups.
LEMMA 2. If the distribution F has a logconcave density, then
[U.sup.j] ([mu]'; [[??].sub.j-1], [[??].sub.j]) is single peaked in
[mu]' for j = 2, ..., J - 1.
Proof From Equation (5), [partial derivative][U.sup.j]/[partial
derivative][mu]' has the same sign as
h ([[??].sub.j-1] - [beta] [mu]')/[[??].sub.j] - [beta]
[mu]') - 1.
where h is the density function corresponding to the distribution
function H. Note that H is a convolution of [??] and a normal
distribution, and [??] in turn is a convolution of F and a normal
distribution. Since the normal density is log-concave, and since the
class of log-concave densities is closed under convolutions (e.g.,
Dharmadhikari and Joag-dev 1988), h is log-concave. Log-concavity
implies that h ([[mu].sub.j-1] - [beta] [mu]') / h ([[??].sub.j] -
[beta][mu]') is decreasing in [*' for all [[mu].sub.j] >
[[??].sub.-1]. It follows that the derivative [partial
derivative][U.sup.J]/[partial derivative][mu]' can change sign
(from positive to negative) at most once. Q.E.D.
Suppose that society is divided into three groups. Lemma 2 implies
that preference for Group 2 (the moderate group) is most intense among
people with moderate posterior beliefs. However, even though [U.sup.2]
reaches a peak at some intermediate value of [mu]', this peak may
not be higher than [U.sup.1] or [U.sup.3]. For Group 2 to be viable, the
moderates must prefer the moderate group to the extreme groups.
Similarly, in a three-group equilibrium, people with extreme beliefs
must prefer their respective extreme groups to the moderate group.
Existence of equilibrium can be established by making the following
assumptions.
ASSUMPTION 1. The function h(x - d)/g(x) is unimodal in x for all
d.
ASSUMPTION 2. The function g(x)/h((1 - [beta])x) is unimodal in x
for fixed [beta].
ASSUMPTION 3. For any [d.sub.2] > [d.sub.1], [lim.sub.x[right
arrow][infinity]] h([d.sub.2] - x)/h([d.sub.1] - x) = [infinity] and
[lim.sub.x[right arrow][infinity]] h ([d.sub.2] - x)/h([d.sub.1] - x) =
O.
PROPOSITION 3. Suppose that the density function h is log-concave
and satisfies Assumptions 1-3. There exists a three-group equilibrium in
which individuals with [mu]' [member of [-[infinity], [[??].sub.1]]
belong to Group 1, those with [mu]' [member of] ([[??].sub.1],
[[??].sub.2]) belong to Group 2, and those with [mu]' [member of]
[[[??].sub.2], [infinity]] belong to Group 3. The critical values
satisfy [[??].sub.1] < [[??].sub.2] and
(6) [MATHEMATICAL EXPRESSION NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII].
The proof of Proposition 3 involves several steps and is relegated
to the Appendix. Briefly, Equation (6) is the indifference condition for
the critical types:
(7) [MATHEMATICAL EXPRESSION NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII],
One can think of these two conditions as defining two implicit
functions, [[??]'.sub.1] = [[psi].sup.i]/([[??].sub.1],
[[??].sub.2]) for i = 1, 2. The equilibrium cutoff values are
characterized by the fixed point of this mapping. Assumption 3 is a
technical condition invoked to guarantee that these implicit functions
exist. Assumption 1 is used to ensure [[??]'.sub.1] <
[[??]'.sub.2] for any [[??].sub.1] < [[??].sub.2]. Assumption 2
is required to ensure that [[??]'sub.i] remains bounded for any
hounded [[??].sub.i](i = 1, 2). The fixed point theorem then implies
that a solution to Equation (6) exists and satisfies [[??].sub.1] <
[[??].sub.2]. Finally, log-concavity of h is used to show that
indifference by the critical types implies strict preference by people
with beliefs in the interior of the group boundaries. That is, the
indifference condition Equation (7) suffices to characterize an
equilibrium in which no member of any group has an incentive to move to
another group.
Assumptions 1 and 2 are related to the concept of "conditional
variability ordering" introduced by Whitt (1980). (5) Since they
play an important role in the Proof of Proposition 3, it is useful to
discuss their economic interpretation. Recall that H is the (subjective)
cross-sectional distribution of the posteriors of informed agents, given
by [[mu]'.sub.y] = (1 - [beta])[mu] + [beta]0 +
[beta]][epsilon].sup.y], while G is the distribution of the posteriors
among uninformed agents, given by [[mu]'.sub.x] = (1 - [beta])[mu]
+ [beta] [[epsilon].sup.x].
If the distribution of priors is normal, then both H and G are
normal as well. In this case, Assumption 1 is satisfied if and only if
(8) var([[mu]'.sub.y])/var([mu]'.sub.x]) < 1.
When the relative variance in Equation (8) is too large, informed
agents are dispersed toward the two ends of the distribution, and the
chances of meeting an informed person in the moderate group are small.
In that case, a three-group equilibrium is not possible because no one
wants to join the moderate group. When both H and G are normal,
Assumption 2 is satisfied if and only if
(9) var([[mu]'.sub.y])/var([mu]'.sub.x]) > [(1 -
[beta]).sup.2].
If the relative variance is too small, there are too many
uninformed agents near the two ends of the distribution. Again, a
three-group equilibrium cannot be supported because even people with
extreme posteriors would leave the extreme groups to join the moderate
group.
Numerical calculations based on the case in which F is a standard
normal distribution illustrate this intuition. For example, if
[[tau].sub.y] = 1 and [upsilon] = 1, a solution to Equation (6) exists
only for [[tau].sub.x] [member of] (1.5, 9), which corresponds to the
bounds specified in Equations (8) and (9). (6) In this range,
[[??].sub.1] decreases while [[??].sub.2] increases with [[tau].sub.x].
In other words, as the bogus signal becomes more noisy, people expect
the extreme groups to contain more uninformed agents. Thus, the moderate
group becomes relatively more attractive, and its equilibrium size gets
larger.
IV. CONCLUDING REMARKS
The sorting of individuals into nonoverlapping social groups is an
abstraction of the structure of social networks in the real world.
Granovetter (1973) argues that while many social networks exhibit
clusters of strong ties which resemble the social groups described in
this article), these clusters do have some overlap mediated by what he
calls "weak ties." Watts (1999) shows that a few random
rewiring of a clustered network is sufficient to connect every
individual in society to within a short distance from any other
individual. The equilibrium model in this article can be used to account
for the stability of cliques in the network structure but does not
adequately capture the evolution of these cliques or provide for the
role of weak ties as emphasized by Granovetter and by Watts. In this
article, an individual chooses to join a social group and interacts with
a randomly picked fellow member of his group each period. A more
satisfactory description of informal social networks would have social
groups emerge endogenously as a result of repeated interactions among a
cluster of individuals. A step toward that direction may be to embed the
present model in a search framework. For example, a pair of individuals
may meet each other at random, but they can choose to maintain or sever their tie depending on their assessment of the probability that the
other partner is informed. Another possible extension of the model is to
explore the relationship between the core beliefs of a group and its
peripheral beliefs as in Murphy and Shleifer (2004). For example, the
state variable may be taken to be two-dimensional, and the set of
informed persons for one issue may not be the same as the set of
informed persons for the other issue. Finally, this article assumes that
people speak the truth when they exchange information with one another.
The strategic manipulation of information (e.g., Morris 2001;
Prendergast 1993) is another area for further investigation. Although
none of these extensions is a straightforward exercise, I hope this
article will provide a useful framework and starting point for thinking
about more complicated problems in the analysis of social networks and
social influence.
APPENDIX
Proof of Proposition 3
For [[??].sub.1] < [[??].sub.2], the indifference condition
Equation (9) can be written as
(A1) H ([[??].sub.2] - [beta] [[??]'.sub.1]/H [[??].sub.1] -
[beta] [[??]'.sub.1] - G([[??].sub.2])/G ([[??].sub.1]) = 0;
(A2) 1 - H ([[??].sub.2] - [beta] [[??]'.sub.2]/1 - H
[[??].sub.1] - [beta] [[??]'.sub.2] - 1 - G([[??].sub.2])/1 - G
([[??].sub.1]) = 0;
One can think of Equations (A1) and (A2) as defining two implicit
functions, [[??]'.sub.1] = [[psi].sup.i]([[??].sub.1],
[[??].sub.2]) (i = l, 2). For [[??].sub.1] = [[??].sub.2], Equations
(A1) and (A2) do not uniquely determine [[??]'.sub.1]
[[??]'.sub.2] In this case, since
[MATHEMATICAL EXPRESSION NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII],
let [[psi].sup.1] and [[psi].sup.2] be implicitly defined by the
solution to, respectively,
(A1') h([[??].sub.1] - [beta][[??]'.sub.1])/H
([[??].sub.1] - [beta][[??]'.sub.1] -
g([[??].sub.1])/G([[mu].sub.1] = 0;
(A2') - h([[??].sub.1] - [beta][[??]'.sub.2])/1 - H
([[??].sub.2] - [beta][[??]'.sub.2] + g([[??].sub.2])/1 -
G([[mu].sub.1] = 0;
The proof proceeds in several steps.
Step 1. For all [[??].sup.1] [less than or equal to] [[??].sub.2],
[[psi].sup.1], ([[??].sub.1], [[??].sub.2])(i = 1, 2) exists and is
unique.
When [[??].sup.1] < [[??].sup.2], the left-hand side of Equation
(Al) approaches 1 as [[??]'.sup.1] approaches - [infinity] because
of the nature of distribution function. This ratio approaches [infinity]
as [[??]'.sub.1] approaches infinity by Assumption 3. Since the
right-hand side of Equation (A1) is greater than 1, by the intermediate
value theorem, there is a finite [[??]'.sub.1] that solves Equation
(A1). Furthermore, since h is log-concave, the left-hand side of
Equation (A1) is increasing in [[??]'.sub.1]. Hence, the solution
is unique. Similar reasoning establishes that the solution to Equation
(A2) exists and is unique.
When [[??].sub.1] = [[??].sub.2] Assumption 3 implies that the
left-hand side of Equation (A1') approaches 0 and [infinity] as
[[??]'.sub.1] approaches minus and plus infinity. Moreover,
log-concavity of h implies that this expression is increasing in
[[??]'.sub.1]. Hence, a unique solution to Equation (Al')
exists. A similar argument suggests that [[??]'.sub.2] exists and
is unique when [[??].sub.1] = [[??].sub.2].
Step 2. For all [[??].sub.1] [less than or equal to] [[??].sub.2],
[[??]'.sub.1] [less than or equal to] [[??]'.sub.2].
Suppose the opposite is true, that is, [[??]'.sub.1] >
[[??]'.sub.2] Then,
(A3) [MATHEMATICAL EXPRESSION NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII],
where the inequality follows from the log-concavity of h and the
equality follows from Equation (Al).
Now, by Assumption 1, the function h(x -
[beta][[??]'.sub.1])/g(x) is unimodal in x. Unimodality of h/g
implies unimodality of H/G (see, e.g., Metzger and Ruschendorf 1991).
So, if Equation (A1) holds, it must be the case that
H([[??].sub.2] - [beta] [[??]'.sub.1]) G([[??].sub.2] >
[lim.sub.x[right arrow][infinity] H(x - [beta] [[??]'.sub.1])/G (x)
= 1.
In other words, the expression Equation (A3) is strictly negative,
which contradicts Equation (A2).
Suppose [[??].sub.1] = [[??].sub.2] and assume that
[[??]'.sub.1] > [[??].sub.2]. Then,
(A3) [MATHEMATICAL EXPRESSION NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII]
When Equation (A1') holds, it must be the case that
H([[??].sub.1] - [beta] [[??]'.sub.1])/G([[??].sub.1] >
[lim.sub.x[right arrow][infinity]] H(x - [beta] [[??]'.sub.1])/G(x)
= 1
In other words, the expression Equation (A3') is strictly
negative, which contradicts Equation (A2').
Step 3. The function [[psi].sup.i] ([[??].sub.1], [[??].sub.2])(i =
1, 2) is increasing in both arguments.
Differentiate Equation (A1) with respect to [[??].sub.1] to get
[partial derivative([H.sub.2]/[H.sub1])/[partial derivative]
[[??]'.sub.1] [partial derivative] [[psi].sup.1]/[partial
derivative [[??].sub.1] = [H.sub.2] [g.sub.1]/[H.sup.2.sub.1]
([h.sub.1]/[g.sub.1] - [H.sub.1]/[G.sub.1]),
where [H.sub.1] stands for value of the function H(x -
[beta][[??]'.sub.1]) at the point x = [[??].sub.1], and so forth.
Log-concavity of h implies that [partial
derivative]([H.sub.2]/[H.sub.1])/[partial derivative][[??]'.sub.1]
> 0. The unimodal property of h(x - d)/g(x) implies that H/G < h/g
when H/G is increasing and H/G > h/g when H/G is decreasing. Since
H/G is increasing at x = [[??].sub.1], [h.sub.1]/[g.sub.1] >
[H.sub.1]/[G.sub.1]. Hence, [partial derivative][[psi].sup.1]/[partial
derivative][[??].sub.1] > 0.
Differentiate Equation (A1) with respect to 112 to get
[partial derivative([H.sub.2])/[H.sub.1])/[partial derivative]
[[??]'.sub.1] [partial derivative[[psi].sup.1] [partial derivative]
[[??].sub.2] = [g.sub.2]/[H.sub.1] ([H.sub.2]/[G.sub.2] -
[h.sub.2]/[g.sub.2]).
Since H/G is decreasing at x = [[??].sub.2], unimodality of h(x
d)/g(x) implies that [H.sub.2]/[G.sub.2] > [h.sub.2]/[g.sub.2].
Hence, [partial derivative] [[psi].sup.1]/[partial derivative]
[[??].sub.2] > 0. The monotonicity of [[psi].sup.2] can be
established similarly.
Step 4. The function [[psi].sup.i] ([[??].sub.1], [[??].sub.2])(i =
1,2) is bounded for bounded [[??].sub.1] and [[??].sub.2].
By Assumption 2, g(x)/h((l-[beta])x) is unimodal in x. This in turn
implies that G(x)/H((1- [beta])x) and (1 - G(x))/(1- H((1 - [beta])x))
are unimodal in x. Let [m.sub.u], be the mode of G(x)/H((1 - [beta])x)
and [m.sub.1] be the mode of (1 - G(x))/(1 H(1 - [beta])x)). Since
G(x)/H((1 - [beta])x) reaches a peak when g(x)/h((1 - [beta])x) is
falling while (1 - G(x))/(1 - H((1 - [beta])x)) reaches a peak when
g(x)/ h((1 - [beta])x) is rising, [m.sub.u] > [m.sub.l]. The
remainder of this step establishes [m.sub.l] [less than or equal to]
[[??].sub.1] [less than or equal to] [[??].sub.2] [less than or equal
to] [m.sub.u] for all [m.sub.l] [less than or equal to] [[??].sub.1]
< [[??].sub.2] [less than or equal to] [m.sub.u].
Let [[??].sub.1] = [[??].sub.2] = [m.sub.l] and suppose
[[??]'.sub.1] = [m.sub.l]. Then, the left-hand side of Equation
(A1') is equal to
(A4) h((1 - [beta])[m.sub.l])/H ((1 - [beta]) [m.sub.l]) -
g([m.sub.l])/G ([m.sub.l]).
Notice that Assumption 2 implies that g(x)/h((1[beta])x) >
G(x)/H((1 - [beta])x) when x = [m.sub.l] < [m.sub.u]; hence, Equation
(A4) is negative. Since [H.sub.2]/[H.sub.1] - [G.sub.2]/[G.sub.1] is
increasing in [[??]'.sub.1], in order for Equation (Al') to
hold, it must be the case that [[??]'.sub.1] > [m.sub.l].
Finally, by the monotonicity of the [[psi].sup.1], for all [[??].sub.2]
[greater than or equal to] [[??].sub.1] [greater than or equal to]
[m.sub.l],
[[psi].sup.1] ([[??].sub.1], [[??].sub.2]) [greater than or equal
to] [[psi].sup.1] ([m.sub.l], [m.sub.l]) > [m.sub.l].
To show that [[??]'.sub.2] < [m.sub.u], let [[??].sub.1] =
[[??].sub.2] = [m.sub.u] and suppose [[??]'.sub.2] = [m.sub.u].
Then, the left-hand side of Equation (A2') is equal to
(A5) - h((1 - [beta]) [m.sub.u])/ 1 - H ((1 - [beta]) [[m.sub.u]) +
g([m.sub.u]/1 - G ([m.sub.u]).
Assumption 2 implies that g(x)/h((l - [beta])x) > (1 G(x))/(1 -
H((1 - [beta])x) at x = [m.sub.u], > [m.sub.l]; hence, Equation (A5)
is positive. Since (1 - [H.sub.2])/(1 - [H.sub.1]) - (1 - [G.sub.2]/(1
[G.sub.1]) is increasing in [[??]'.sub.2], in order for Equation
(A2') to hold, it must be the case that [[??]'.sub.2] < m,.
Furthermore, for all [[??].sub.1] [less than or equal to] [[??].sub.2]
[less than or equal to] [m.sub.u], we have
[[psi].sup.2] ([[??].sub.1], [[??].sub.2], [less than or equal to]
[[psi].sup.2]([m.sub.u], [m.sub.u]) < [m.sub.u]
Step 5. The fixed point of the mapping [psi] exists such that
[[??].sub.1] < [[??].sub.2].
Let T = {(x, y) : [m.sub.l] [less than or equal to] x [less than or
equal to] y [less than or equal to] [m.sub.u]}. The previous steps
establish that [psi] is a mapping from T to T. Hence, a fixed point
([[??].sub.1], [[??].sub.2]) [member of] T of [psi] exists. Moreover,
this fixed point must be such that [[??].sub.1], < [[??].sub.2].
Suppose otherwise, that is, let [[??].sub.1] = [[??].sub.2] = [??].
Then, Equations (A1') and (A2') require
H([??] - [beta][??])/G ([??]) = h([??] - [beta][??])/g([??]) = 1 -
H([??] - [beta] ([??])/1 - G([??].
But the first equality holds only at [??] = [m.sub.u], while the
second equality holds only at [??] = [m.sub.l]. Since [m.sub.u] [not
equal to] [m.sub.l], this is a contradiction.
Step 6. Indifference by the critical types implies strict
preference by the interior types.
Since Equation (Al) holds at [[??]'.sub.1] =
[[??]'.sub.1], and since logconcavity of h implies that Equation
(Al) is increasing in [[??]'.sub.1], any individual with a
posterior less than [[??].sub.1], prefers Group 1 to Group 2. Similarly,
log-concavity of h implies that Equation (A2) is increasing in
[[??]'.sub.2]. So, any individual with a posterior less that
[[??].sub.2], prefers Group 2 to Group 3. This means that Group 1 is the
best group for individuals with posteriors in the range [- [infinity],
[[??].sub.1],]. Similar reasoning establishes that for [mu]'
[member of] [[[??].sub.j-1], [[??].sub.1]](j = 2, 3),
max{[U.sup.1]([mu]'), [U.sup.2]([mu]'),
[U.sup.3]([mu]')} = [U.sup.i]([mu]).
Q.E.D.
doi: 10.1111/j.1465-7295.2009.00254.x
REFERENCES
Brewer, M. B., and R. M. Kramer. "The Psychology of Intergroup Attitudes and Behaviors." Annual Review of Psychology, 36, 1985,
219-43.
Brown, J. D. "Evaluations of Self and Others: Self-Enhancement
Biases in Social Judgments." Social Cognition, 4, 1986, 353-76.
Byrne, D. The Attraction Paradigm. New York: Academic Press, 1971.
Crawford, V., and J. Sobel. "Strategic Information
Transmission." Econometrica, 50, 1982, 1431-51.
Currarini. S., M. O. Jackson, and P. Pin. Forthcoming. "A
Economic Model of Friendship: Homophily, Minorities and
Segregation." Econometrica,.
Dharmadhikari, S., and K. Joag-dev. Unimodality, Convexity, and
Applications. San Diego, CA: Academic Press, 1988.
Gentzkow, M., and J. Shapiro. "Media Bias and
Reputation." Journal of Political Economy, 114, 2006, 280-316.
Granovetter, M. S. "The Strength of Weak Ties." American
Journal of Sociology, 78, 1973, 1360-80.
McElwee, R. O., D. Dunning, P. L. Tan, and S. Hollmann.
"'Evaluating Others: The Role of Who We Are Versus What We
Think Traits Mean." Basic and Applied Social Psychology, 23, 2001,
123-36.
Metzger, C., and L. Ruschendorf. "Conditional Variability
Ordering of Distributions." Annals of Operations Research, 32,
1991, 127-40.
Morris, S. "Political Correctness." Journal of Political
Economy, 109, 2001, 231-65.
Murphy, K. M., and A. Shleifer. "Persuasion in Politics."
American Economic Review, 94, 2004, 435-39.
Newcomb, T. M. The Acquaintance Process. New York: Holt, Rinehart,
and Winston, 1961. Prendergast, C. "A Theory of 'Yes
Men'." American Economic Review, 83, 1993, 757-70.
Suen. W. "The Self-Perpetuation of Biased Beliefs."
Economic Journal, 114, 2004, 377-96.
Sunstein, C. Republic.com. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 2001.
Watts, D. J. Small Worlds. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University
Press, 1999.
Whitt, W. "Uniform Conditional Stochastic Order." Journal
of Applied Probability, 17, 1980, 112-23.
Wittenbaum, G. M., A. P. Hubbell, and C. Zuckerman. "Mutual
Enhancement: Toward an Understanding of the Collective Preference for
Shared Information." Journal of Personality and Social Psychology,
77, 1999, 967-78.
(1.) The comedian Groucho Marx was reported to have said, "I
don't care to belong to a club that accepts people like me as
members."
(2.) This model does not depend on the assumption that everyone
believes that his own signal is informative. Suppose each person
attaches probability [pi] that his own signal is informative and
probability 1 - [pi] that his own signal is bogus. Let
k' = log [[pi].sub.q] + (1 - [pi]) (0.5)/[pi](1 - q) + (1 -
[pi]) (0.5) > 0.
Then, each person updates his belief to [rho] + k' upon
observing a private signal R or to [rho] - k' upon observing a
private signal L. The argument in the next section goes through by
replacing k with k'.
(3.) There is also a trivial equilibrium in which the composition
of agents in group L is identical to that of agents in group R. The
trivial equilibrium is ruled out by the requirement that at least some
individuals strictly prefer one group to another.
(4.) For this reason, an equilibrium with two groups always exists.
(5.) See also Metzger and Ruschendorf (1991) for how the
unimodality of the ratio of the density functions implies the
conditional variability ordering.
(6.) If [[tau].sub.x] = [[tau].sub.y], uncertainty about [theta]
implies that the informative signal [Y.sub.i], = [theta] +
[[epsilon].sup.y.sub.i] is more variable than the bogus signal [X.sub.i]
= [[epsilon].sup.x.sub.i]. In that case, equilibrium can only support
two groups since people expect any moderate group to consist of
primarily uninformed agents. In a more general setup, one can let
[X.sub.i] = [[xi].sub.i] + [[epsilon].sup.x.sub.i], where [[xi].sub.i]
is the bias of the bogus signal. If var([[xi].sub.i])= var([theta])>
var([theta] | [Y.sub.i]), then a moderate group can be supported in
equilibrium even when [[tau].sub.x] = [[tau].[sub.y]
WING SUEN, This work grew out of conversations with Jimmy Chan and
Dan Usher. Ronald Chan, Priscilla Man, and Kwan To Wong provided able
research assistance. Valuable comments from Parimal Bag and Li Hao are
gratefully acknowledged. I thank Alan Siu in particular for suggesting
the title of this article.
Suen: Henry G. Leong Professor in Economics, School of Economics
and Finance, University of Hong Kong, Pokfulam, Hong Kong. Phone (852)
25481152, Fax (852) 25481152, E-mail wsuen@econ.hku.hk