Social preferences and tax policy design: some experimental evidence.
Ackert, Lucy F. ; Martinez-Vazquez, Jorge ; Rider, Mark 等
I. INTRODUCTION
This article examines whether a taste for fairness influences
people's preferences among alternative tax structures. Using an
experimental approach, we devise a simple test for social preferences in
voting for alternative tax structures. We find that accounting for
social preferences helps explain the choices among alternative tax
structures of some individuals. However, we find that the willingness to
accept a smaller payoff for greater distributional equity decreases as
the deadweight loss from progressive taxation increases. These findings
have important implications for tax policy design. If, for example,
individuals are averse to income inequality, tax structures that
increase inequality may reduce individual utility. In addition,
according to Alm (1998) and Andreoni, Erard, and Feinstein (1998) among
others, the perceived fairness of a tax system also may influence
voluntary tax compliance.
Outside the context of tax policy design, the existence of social
preferences is now well established. (1) Within the context of tax
policy design, the most direct evidence bearing on the fundamental issue
examined in this study comes from the pathbreaking work of Engelmann and
Strobel ([ES] 2004) and Frohlich and Oppenheimer ([FO] 1992). (2) FO use
laboratory experiments to investigate which principle of distributive
justice people choose, absent knowledge of their position in the income
distribution. More specifically, they ask subjects to express a
preference for a principle of distributive justice among several
stylized principles, such as the maxi-min principle of Rawls (1971) and
the efficiency principle of Harsanyi (1953, 1955) among others. (3) FO
find that most groups choose a mixed principle: they prefer to maximize
average income, as suggested by Harsanyi, constrained by an income floor
for the worst-off individual as suggested by Rawls.
FO do not directly address the choice of tax structure; rather
their results imply that people care about both the efficiency and
distributional consequences of tax policy. Though very instructive,
their experiments do not provide quantitative evidence on the nature of
the trade-offs among the potentially conflicting goals of maximizing
one's own payoff, maximizing the sum of individual payoffs, and
maximizing the payoff of the worst-off individual. In a related study,
ES use one-shot distribution experiments to compare the performance of
several behavioral models, including theories reflecting social
preferences. Consistent with FO, ES conclude that theories of inequality
aversion have no additional explanatory power in their data beyond what
can be explained by the mixed rule of efficiency and maxi-min. They also
conclude that theories of inequality aversion perform poorly in cases
where a distribution with less inequality is Pareto dominated by another
distribution.
The focus of the current study is on the relevance of fairness
motives in the choice of tax structures. We use Fehr and Schmidt's
([FS] 1999) model of inequality aversion to test whether people are
willing to choose a distribution with a smaller own payoff to achieve a
more equitable distribution of after-tax payoffs. In the experiments
reported below, we present participants with a simple task. We randomly
assign nine participants in each experimental session with a payoff that
is uniformly distributed between $10 and $50, in increments of $5. Then,
the participants are asked to vote for either a uniform head tax or a
progressive tax. The vote of the majority determines the tax structure
and consequently the distribution of after-tax payoffs to the subjects.
Thus, the laboratory experiments are designed to elicit individually held social preferences for redistributive taxation. Our
central finding is that some people are willing to accept a smaller own
after-tax payoff to reduce payoff inequality, but this apparent demand
for fairness decreases as the cost of reducing inequality increases.
Our experiments differ from those of FO and ES in a number of ways.
In particular, our experimental design allows us to gauge whether
participants are willing to sacrifice in terms of a smaller after-tax
payoff to reduce payoff inequality. ES's canonical experiments do
not. (4) The difference is crucial because, in our view, a decision
reflects a taste for fairness when the preferred outcome requires the
decision maker to sacrifice by reducing their own after-tax payoff to
achieve a more equitable distribution of payoffs.
The article proceeds as follows. In the next section, we describe a
model that formalizes our notion of fairness. Section III presents a
summary of voting behavior, and Section IV discusses an econometric
model and presents additional results. Section V offers concluding
comments.
II. A MODEL OF SOCIAL PREFERENCES
As reviewed in the previous section, there is growing empirical
evidence of social preferences. Although theoretical work continues on
the form of such preferences, from our perspective, three recent models
are particularly relevant in framing the way people vote for different
tax structures. First, Charness and Rabin (2002) develop a model that
combines social preferences, efficiency concerns, and reciprocity to
predict behavior in economic experiments. In their two-person
formulation, a player's utility is the weighted average of
one's own payoff and the other player's payoff, where the
weight of the other player depends on payoff inequality and whether the
other player has behaved fairly. Second, Bolton and Ockenfels (2000)
argue that own payoff and relative standing can explain observed
behavior in many economic games. In their formulation, however, players
do not care about inequality among other players or efficiency. Finally,
FS (1999) develop a model where own payoff and inequality aversion play
key roles.
Several considerations are pertinent in choosing a theoretical
framework to explain individual preferences among alternative tax
structures. First, we are not concerned here with reciprocity because
voting processes are often anonymous, which prevents participants from
observing one another's voting behavior and rules out the ability
to punish unfair play. Second, the choice of tax structure may be
affected not only by income inequality aversion but also by concerns
about efficiency. Third, social preferences may take varied and complex
forms in the population. An approach that allows some people to be
concerned with their own payoff and income inequality aversion is, we
believe, sufficiently flexible to account for different possible voting
behaviors. Fourth, people may be more apt to show social preferences in
"low-cost" voting environments when their decisions tend to
matter less, as compared to "high-cost" private choice
environments, with the latter being the context of the three models
summarized above. (5)
The FS model provides a basis for our examination of social
preferences. In their model, a player's utility is a linear sum of
one's own payoff and the losses from disadvantageous and
advantageous inequality. (6) In the FS model with n players, an
individual's utility depends on one's own payoff and inequity
aversion as follows:
[MATHEMATICAL EXPRESSION NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII].
In this model [[pi].sub.i] is the monetary payoff to player i,
[[delta].sub.1] is a parameter measuring the degree of disadvantageous
inequality aversion, and [[delta].sub.2] is a parameter measuring the
degree of advantageous inequality aversion. The first term on the
right-hand side reflects player i's concern for his/her own payoff.
The next two terms reflect i's utility loss from disadvantageous
and advantageous inequality, respectively. Following FS, we assume that
a player's inequity aversion is self-centered, so that he/she does
not care about inequities among other players. Finally, we normalize the
disutility from inequity aversion by n - 1 in order to ensure that the
effect of inequity aversion is independent of the number of players. As
discussed below, this model of individual utility can be adapted to
predict an individual's vote between two tax structures, and our
experimental design allows us to test for social motives. (7)
III. EXPERIMENTAL DESIGN AND METHOD
The choice of tax structure in a democratic country is a complex
process, but ultimately it can be reduced to voters supporting different
political platforms with tax proposals that differ in terms of the
associated efficiency losses and distribution of tax burdens. In our
experimental setting, individuals may express a preference for
distributional equity by voting for a progressive tax, some of which
involve efficiency losses.
There are nine experimental sessions, each consisting of a series
of five trials or rounds. (8) Nine university students participate in
each session, which are completed in approximately 30 min. (9) The
average age of the participants is 22.0 yr, and no participant takes
part in more than one session. (10) After they arrive for the
experiment, participants receive a set of instructions and follow along
as an experimenter reads aloud. The instructions are provided in
Appendix 1. The experimental design is summarized in Table 1 and
described below.
In all sessions, participants are endowed with an income or pretax payoff that is theirs to keep for participating in the experiment except
that they must pay a tax. Each participant's pretax payoff or
experimental income is determined by drawing a card from a set of nine
cards. The following incomes are recorded on the cards: $10, $15, $20,
$25, $30, $35, $40, $45, and $50. They also are reminded that because
each income is equally likely, the average pretax payoff across
participants is $30. (11) Within each period, income cards are drawn
without replacement, and participants are instructed that their income
is private information that should not be revealed at any time during
the session.
In all treatments, the tax is one of two types. As Table 2 reports,
Tax 1 is a lump-sum head tax of $7.50, and Tax 2 is a progressive income
tax. Notice from Panel A of Table 2 that the sum of after-tax payoffs in
Treatments 1 through 3 is $202.50 for both the head tax and the
progressive tax. In other words, the two tax regimes are revenue
neutral. (12) For Treatments 1 through 3, four of the nine participants
receive a higher after-tax payoff under the head tax, as noted in Table
1. Four low-income participants receive a higher after-tax payoff under
the progressive tax, whereas the median participant with a pretax payoff
of $30 receives the same after-tax payoff under both tax structures.
(13) If the participants care only about their after-tax payoff,
high-income participants (i.e., pretax payoff > $30) prefer the head
tax, low-income participants (i.e., pretax payoff < $30) prefer the
progressive tax, and the median-income participant (i.e., pretax payoff
= $30) is indifferent between the two. The subjects' after-tax
payoffs are determined by the vote of the majority in the choice between
the head tax (Tax 1) and the progressive tax (Tax 2). (14) Participants
are given 5 min to indicate the preferred tax. In Treatments 1 and 2,
the votes are tallied, the chosen tax structure is publicly announced
after each round of voting, and participants are reminded that their
after-tax payoff is private information that should not be disclosed at
any time. In Treatment 3, the result of each round of voting is withheld
from the participants until the conclusion of all five rounds to control
for the potential influence on individual voting of observing whether
others are "cooperating" by voting for the progressive tax.
These procedures are repeated five times in each session. As the
instructions indicate, participants are told at the outset that they
will be paid according to the results of only one of the trials, and
this trial will be chosen by a card drawn at random by one of the
participants from a set of cards labeled 1-5. Since ex ante the students
have no way of knowing which trial is the payout trial, it is in their
interest to treat all trials with equal seriousness. (15)
Treatment 1 differs from Treatments 2 and 3 in that participants in
Treatment 1 vote for a tax structure before they draw an income card. In
other words, participants in Treatment 1 vote before they know their
pretax payoff. Since they do not know their place in the income
distribution when they vote, they have no way of knowing whether the
chosen tax regime increases or decreases their after-tax payoff, and, in
that sense, they vote "as if behind a veil of ignorance," to
use a phrase coined by Rawls (1971). In Treatments 2 and 3, participants
vote after drawing an income card; so they know their standing in the
income distribution when they vote. These treatments allow us to see if
knowledge of one's position in the income distribution, and thus
the effect of the vote on their own after-tax payoff, changes the
majority vote.
At the conclusion of each session, participants complete a
postexperiment questionnaire, designed to collect demographic
information. Consideration of demographic information does not indicate
any notable differences between participants across all sessions (1-10),
as expected given that all subjects are recruited from the same pool. In
addition, their responses on the questionnaire indicate that they found
the experiment interesting and the monetary incentives motivating.
Participants respond on an 11-point scale as to how interesting they
found the experiment, where 1 = not very interesting and 11 = very
interesting. The mean response across all treatments is 9.0.
Participants also respond on an 11-point scale as to how they would
characterize the amount of money earned for taking part in the
experiment, where 1 = nominal amount and 11 = considerable amount. The
mean response across all treatments is 10.0. (16)
IV. SUMMARY OF VOTING BEHAVIOR
A. Revenue-Neutral Treatments
Table 3 summarizes the preferences of participants as revealed by
their voting behavior. In Treatment 1, the majority vote for Tax 2 (the
progressive tax) in 11 of 15 trials. In these sessions, participants do
not know their income level when they cast their votes, and the majority
choose the progressive tax. This result supports the view that people
care about the distributional consequences of taxation and not simply
their own payoff. Since the participants do not know their pretax
payoff, however, some may be attempting to pool payoff risk by voting
for the progressive tax, reflecting risk aversion rather than payoff
inequality aversion.
To control for this potential confound, we allow participants to
observe their pretax payoff before voting. (17) This experimental design
also allows us to observe whether participants are willing to sacrifice
income to satisfy a taste for fairness, if in fact a taste for fairness
drives the previous finding. In Treatment 2, the majority vote for the
progressive tax (Tax 2) in 10 of 15 trials. As we will see, it is not
necessarily the median participant with a pretax payoff of $30 who is
decisive. Thus, some participants vote for the progressive tax even
though they suffer in terms of their own after-tax payoff. In other
words, it appears that some participants are prepared to pay or
sacrifice income in order to satisfy a taste for fairness. In contrast,
some median-income participants vote against the progressive tax even
though their after-tax payoff is unaffected by their choice of
distribution. Such evidence of heterogeneity in the population may play
an important role in distribution experiments and may explain ES's
conclusion that theories of inequality aversion do not provide
additional explanatory power beyond that afforded by the efficiency and
maxi-min principles.
An additional concern about the experimental design described above
may stem from participants attempting to play cooperative strategies.
When participants know their income before they vote and the majority
vote is revealed after each round, high-income participants in a given
round may attempt to "signal" a cooperative strategy by voting
for the progressive tax, even though doing so reduces their after-tax
payoff in that round. In this manner, they may try to elicit cooperation
to "insure" against the risk of being low income in subsequent
rounds.
A solution to this potential confound is a treatment in which
participants receive no information about the majority vote in each
round until the end of the session. Thus, in Treatment 3, we withhold the result of each voting round until the conclusion of the experiment
to control for the potential influence of "cooperation" on
individual voting. The results of Treatment 3 are reported in Table 3
and indicate that the majority vote for the progressive tax (Tax 2) in
11 of 15 trials. Since these results are very similar to those obtained
with Treatment 2 (10 of 15), votes by high-income participants for the
progressive tax do not appear to reflect attempts to signal a
cooperative strategy.
Table 4 provides additional insight into the behavior of our
experimental participants. As one might expect, in Treatment 1 where the
participants vote "behind a veil of ignorance," voting for
either Tax 1 or Tax 2 shows no pattern across payoffs. Interestingly,
however, we observe approximately the same proportion of total votes for
the progressive tax (Tax 2) in Treatment 2 (56% or 76/135), in which
pretax payoffs are known before voting as when they are not, as in
Treatment 1 (60% or 81/135).
In Treatment 2, we observe a clear pattern in voting behavior with
low (high)-payoff individuals showing a strong preference for the
progressive tax (head tax). It is impossible to infer whether low-payoff
individuals are voting for the progressive tax out of concern for their
own payoff and/or due to disadvantageous inequality aversion because the
two motives are congruent. However, we also see that the median-income
participant whose pretax payoff is $30 votes only slightly more often
for Tax 2 (53% or 8/15). (18) Significantly, in terms of our hypothesis,
some individuals vote for the progressive tax (Tax 2) even when it is
clearly not in their monetary self-interest to do so. In fact, we
observe more votes for Tax 2 by high-income participants (15.0% or 9/60
votes) as compared to votes for Tax 1 (head tax) by low-income
participants (1.6% or 1/60 votes).
For Treatment 3 in which participants do not know the results of
previous rounds of voting, the results are very similar. As in Treatment
2, we observe a strong preference for the progressive tax (56% or
75/135) and more high-income participants vote for Tax 2 (15.0% or 9/60
votes) as compared to votes for Tax 1 by low-income participants (0% or
0/60 votes),
Table 4 also provides further insight into voting behavior. For
each of Treatments 2 and 3 (pretax income is known before voting), nine
out of a possible 60 votes cast are for the progressive tax by
participants with a pretax payoff greater than the median and therefore
risk a smaller own payoff by voting for the progressive tax (Tax 2).
Eight participants cast these 18 votes, and no more than two participate
in any session. We refer to these subjects as fairness minded. Six of
the eight always vote for the progressive tax (Tax 2), regardless of
their income level.
Demographic information indicates the following. The median
participant is in the third year of university study. Three
fairness-minded participants are in their first year at the university,
two are in their third year, and three are in their fourth year. Four
fairness-minded participants are men, and four are women. The median
participant in our experiment and the median fairness-minded participant
both report income in the $25,001 to $50,000 range. Thus, there is no
apparent demographic link across participants who are fairness minded.
Overall, the results support the hypothesis that some subjects exhibit
social preferences and prefer a more equitable distribution of after-tax
payoffs, even if it is personally costly to do so.
B. Treatments with a Distortionary Progressive Tax
Because previous experimental evidence suggests that some people
care about efficiency or maximizing the sum of payoffs, we conduct two
additional treatments. In Treatments 4 and 5, we require participants to
choose between two tax regimes that are not revenue neutral. In other
words, the sum of the after-tax payoffs from the
"distortionary" progressive tax is less than that of the
lump-sum head tax. Notice from Panel B of Table 2 that in Treatment 4,
the sum of the after-tax payoffs is $247.50 with the head tax, whereas,
the sum of the after-tax payoff with the progressive tax is $202.50.
With the exception of the two lowest pretax payoff participants ($10 and
$15), all the subjects have an economic incentive--absent inequality
aversion--to vote for the head tax (Tax 1).
Turning to Treatment 5, the after-tax payoffs are summarized in
Panel C of Table 2. Again, the tax regimes are not revenue neutral. The
sum of after-tax payoffs with the lump-sum head tax is $225.00, whereas
the sum of after-tax payoffs with the distortionary progressive tax is
$202.50. Now, five of nine participants have an economic incentive,
again absent inequality aversion, to vote for the head tax (Tax 1). In
short, the tax regimes in Treatments 4 and 5 are not revenue neutral;
otherwise, the procedures are identical to those described above for
Treatment 2.
Table 3 reports the voting behavior of the majority in Treatments 4
and 5. In contrast to the behavior observed in Treatments 2 and 3, the
majority of participants vote against the progressive tax. In Treatment
4, the majority vote for the lump-sum head tax in every trial. In
Treatment 5, the majority vote for the lump-sum head tax in eight out of
ten trials. In other words, when the tax is not revenue neutral, fewer
people are willing to sacrifice in terms of a smaller own after-tax
payoff to reduce payoff inequality. This result is suggestive:
individuals care about distributional equity, but they also care about
the total size of the pie or efficiency. (19)
Votes by income level, reported in Table 4, support this
interpretation. Few people with high incomes (i.e., pretax payoff >
$30) vote for the progressive tax. In Treatment 4, all participants with
incomes greater than or equal to $20 have an economic incentive--absent
distributional considerations--to vote for the head tax (Tax 1). We
observe only 2.0% (1/ 50 votes) of high-income votes for the progressive
tax (Tax 2) in Treatment 4. Similarly, in Treatment 5, only 4.0% (2/50)
of high-income voters (pretax payoff [greater than or equal to] $30)
choose the progressive tax (Tax 2).
However, the votes of participants with pretax payoffs less than
$20 in Treatment 4 are particularly suggestive regarding social
preferences assuming the form of a taste for efficiency. Low-income
participants (pretax payoffs < $20) in Treatment 4 benefit in terms
of own payoff from the progressive tax (Tax 2). Yet, as Table 4 shows,
20% (5/20) of these participants vote for the lump-sum tax, which
results in a smaller own payoff.
Turning to a similar analysis of Treatment 5, those with pretax
payoffs less than $30 benefit in terms of own payoff under the
progressive tax (Tax 2). In contrast to Treatment 4, now, only 13%
(2/15) vote for the lump-sum tax and against their self-interest in
terms of own payoff. As Table 4 shows, however, the benefit in terms of
the increase in the sum of total payoffs of voting for the lump-sum tax
is smaller, and the cost in terms of own payoff is larger for these
low-income participants in Treatment 5 than in Treatment 4. In other
words, the price of fairness has increased for these low-income
participants in Treatment 5 relative to the price facing them in
Treatment 4. The increasing price of fairness may account for the
smaller percentage of low-income participants willing to vote for the
efficient, lump-sum tax in Treatment 5.
In short, there is evidence that some participants exhibit social
preferences among tax structures in the form of inequality aversion and
concern for efficiency. This is evidenced by those who vote for tax
structures that impose a sacrifice in terms of a smaller own payoff with
the only apparent compensating benefits being reduced payoff inequality
in the case of high-income participants and a more efficient tax in the
case of some low-income participants in Treatments 4 and 5. Finally, the
percentage of fairness-minded votes decreases as the cost of achieving
these social goals increases in terms of a reduced own payoff. This
suggests a downward sloping demand for fairness.
V. STATISTICAL MODEL AND RESULTS
The foregoing discussion provides a number of interesting insights.
Generally speaking, the results are consistent with the predictions of
the FS model of inequality aversion. Yet, we recognize that preferences
may take varied and complex forms. An approach that allows some people
to be concerned with their own payoff, efficiency (e.g., the sum of
total after-tax payoffs), and income inequality aversion provides
flexibility to account for a variety of possible voting behaviors. (20)
However, an examination of these three motives in a single empirical
model is problematic because, as shown in Appendix 2, there is an exact
linear relationship between the sum of total payoffs, own payoff,
disadvantageous inequality, and advantageous inequality. (21) Thus, to
perform a more rigorous test of the observations reported in the
previous sections, we evaluate two models relative to the FS model, as
described subsequently.
An empirical analog of the FS model, which predicts voting behavior
in our experimental environment, is given as follows:
[y.sup.*.sub.i] = ([B.sub.0] + [[alpha].sup.*.sub.i]) +
[B.sub.1][DELTA][[pi].sub.i] + [B.sub.2][DELTA][(n - 1).sup.-1]
[DI.sub.i] + [B.sub.3][DELTA][(n - 1).sup.-1][AI.sub.i] +
[[epsilon].sub.i].
In this model, [y.sub.i.sup.*] is a latent-continuous random
variable representing the difference in utility from a head tax (Tax 1)
relative to a progressive tax (Tax 2). The right-hand side variables
include the difference in own payoff, the difference in disadvantageous
inequality, and the difference in advantageous inequality. (22) The
difference in utility of a particular choice cannot be observed, but we
can observe the individual's vote. Since voting for a binary choice
is incentive compatible, we assume that an individual votes in favor of
the tax structure that maximizes own utility, and
[MATHEMATICAL EXPRESSION NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII].
If individual i prefers a head tax, then [y.sub.i.sup.*] > 0 and
[Vote.sub.i] assumes a value of 1. On the other hand, if i prefers a
progressive tax as evidenced by a vote for a progressive tax, then
[y.sub.i.sup.*] [less than or equal to] 0 and [Vote.sub.i] assumes a
value of 0.
The analysis of voting behavior by income suggests that there may
be heterogeneous tastes for fairness in our sample. To control for such
unobserved heterogeneity, we include [[alpha].sub.i.sup.*], which is a
latent random variable that reflects unobserved idiosyncratic tastes for
fairness. Finally, the random error of the structural model is given by
[[epsilon].sub.i].
To provide insight into the relative ability of the FS model to
predict observed voting behavior in our experiments, we estimate two
additional models. The conventional model of purely selfish preferences
is given as follows:
[y.sup.*.sub.i] = ([B.sub.0] + [[alpha].sup.*.sub.i]) +
[B.sub.1][DELTA][[pi].sub.i] + [[epsilon].sub.i].
In this model, the difference in own aftertax payoffs is the only
explanatory variable. To account for social preferences assuming the
form of a concern for efficiency, irrespective of distributional
concerns, we estimate a model that accounts for the difference in own
payoff and the difference in the sum of after-tax payoffs or the
selfishness and efficiency (S/E) model, which is given as follows:
[y.sup.*.sub.i] = ([B.sub.0] + [[alpha].sup.*.sub.i]) +
[B.sub.1][DELTA][[pi].sub.i] + B.sub.2][DELTA][E.sub.i] +
[[epsilon].sub.i].
This model reflects concern for own payoff and efficiency, where
[DELTA][E.sub.i] is the difference in the sum of after-tax payoffs in
the two tax regimes. (23) We test whether the purely selfish or the S/E
model provides a superior fit to the experimental data than the FS
model.
In estimating the three models, we are confident that
[[alpha].sub.i.sup.*] is statistically independent of the other
regressors, as required by the random-effects probit specification. Our
confidence is based on the fact that the regressors for each observation
depend on pretax income, which is randomly assigned to participants by
the draw of a card. We also include a constant in each regression,
therefore [[alpha].sub.i.sup.*] measures deviations from a common mean.
Lacking any information about the distribution of [[alpha].sub.i.sup.*],
it seems reasonable to assume that deviations from a common mean are
normally distributed in the student population from which we draw our
sample.
Accordingly, we assume [[alpha].sub.i.sup.*] ~
N(0,[[sigma].sub.[alpha].sup.2]) and
E[[[alpha].sub.i.sup.*]|[[pi].sub.i][E.sub.i],[DI.sub.i],
[AI.sub.i],[[epsilon].sub.i] = E[[[alpha].sub.i.sup.*], where [DI.sub.i]
and [AI.sub.i] are the indices of disadvantageous and advantageous
inequality, respectively. By further assuming the error term
[[epsilon].sub.i] has a standard normal distribution, it follows that
our specification is a multivariate probit model. (24) Therefore, we
estimate the three empirical models using random-effects probit. (25)
Our experimental design elicits repeated binary choices by 90
subjects. The resulting data include 450 votes from Treatments 2-5. (26)
Our results are very similar to those reported subsequently whether we
estimate random-effects or fixed-effects linear probability (logit)
models. In contrast to ES's one-shot design, our experimental
design allows us to control for individual effects, which Charness and
Rabin (2002) and the analysis of voting behavior in the previous section
suggest may be important in experiments designed to elicit tastes for
distributional equity.
Table 5 reports estimated coefficients, t-statistics in
parentheses, and marginal effects in brackets for the three
specifications. Recall that the estimated coefficients of a probit
equation indicate the direction of change due to a vote for a head tax
(Tax 1), whereas the marginal effects show the change in the probability
of a vote for the head tax due to a unit change in the corresponding
independent variable. (27) Below the number of observations, the table
reports a [chi square] statistic for a test of the linear restriction
among the coefficients implied by the model with respect to the FS
model. The implied linear restrictions are described in Appendix 2.
Finally, the table reports goodness-of-fit measures, including
Wald's [chi square] test statistic for the significance of the
regression, the estimated value of the log-likelihood function, and
McFadden's adjusted pseudo-[R.sup.2]. (28)
In general, the estimated coefficients of the three models take the
expected signs and are statistically significant at conventional levels,
except for the measure of disadvantageous inequality, which is
statistically insignificant (p = 0.115). (29) In the purely selfish
model, a vote for a head tax is positively related to the change in own
payoff. In the S/E model, a subject is more likely to vote for a head
tax as the deadweight loss from the progressive tax increases. Finally,
as predicted by the FS model of social preferences, subjects are averse
to payoff inequality as evidenced by the negative and statistically
significant, estimated coefficient of the difference in the index of
advantageous inequality. (30) The likelihood ratio tests reject the
linear restrictions implied by the purely selfish and S/E models in
favor of the unrestricted FS model; both models are rejected with a
p-value less than 0.01. The values of the [chi square] test statistics
(df = 2) are reported in Table 5.
In summary, our evidence suggests that the FS model of social
preferences best explains the decisions made by our experimental
participants. Though we cannot separate the impacts of own payoff,
efficiency, and inequity aversion, the empirical analysis supports the
assertion that social preferences matter.
VI. CONCLUSION
We report the results of a simple experiment designed to examine
individual preferences among tax structures. We find that some
individuals possess social preferences or concern for one's own
payoff as well as for the payoffs of others. While precise measurement
and identification of social preferences are not requisite for a policy
issue or concern, our findings do beg the question of the origin or
source of social preferences. Absent a satisfactory answer, it may be
tempting to conclude that our experimental results are simply an
artifact of idiosyncratic behavior by individuals that are peculiar to
our sample. Of course, future research will be needed to establish
whether similar results can be replicated in other settings.
There are two schools of thought regarding the origin of social
preferences. Bicchieri and Zhang (2004) represent a careful statement of
one school of thought, which contends that social preferences are based
in social norms. For example, "love they neighbor as thyself"
(Leviticus, 19:18) is an example of a potentially influential social
norm from an ancient and widely shared creed, and "practice random
acts of kindness" is a contemporary statement of a similar
sentiment and perhaps better suited to a highly mobile and relatively
impersonal society.
In contrast to norm-based explanations, Brosnan and de Waal (2004)
report evidence that social preferences have an evolutionary basis. In
their study, monkeys respond negatively to unfair treatment in
food-related exchanges. The subjects refuse previously acceptable
rewards (cucumbers) if they witness their partners receiving higher
valued rewards (grapes) for equal or less work. This line of research
supports the view that economic decision making is based on an emotional
sense of fairness as well as on rational considerations.
Our experimental design does not permit us to distinguish between
these two equally plausible explanations for our findings. However, both
explanations suggest that our findings could be deeply rooted in human
psychology and are therefore likely to be shared by the population from
which they are drawn. (31)
In summary, our experimental evidence suggests that at least some
individuals may be far more concerned with the distributional
consequences of tax policy design than generally recognized by some
economists and policymakers. Economic models that do not account for
social preferences may provide a faulty guide to tax policy design. For
example, ours is a cautionary message for advocates of substituting a
consumption tax for the current progressive federal income tax.
Proponents of this policy ostensibly believe that the potential benefit
of efficiency gains more than compensates for the potential cost of
greater after-tax income inequality. Clearly, this may not be the case.
ABBREVIATIONS
ES: Engelmann and Strobel
FO: Frohlich and Oppenheimer
FS: Fehr and Schmidt
S/E: Selfishness and Efficiency
doi:10.1111/j.1465-7295.2007.00048.x
APPENDIX 1: EXPERIMENTAL INSTRUCTIONS
The experimental instructions for Treatment 2 follow. Changes in
the instructions for other treatments are noted in brackets.
A. General Instructions
This experiment is concerned with the economics of decision making.
The instructions are simple, and if you follow them carefully and make
good decisions, you might earn a considerable amount of money that will
be paid to you in cash.
In this experiment, you will be given an endowment of cash. This
endowment is your income for participating in the experiment today
except that you must pay a tax.
A Record Sheet is included with these instructions. You will keep
track of your decisions on this sheet.
B. Specific Instructions
Your income, before taxes, is determined by drawing a card from a
set of nine cards. The incomes recorded on the nine cards are as
follows: $10, $15, $20, $25, $30, $35, $40, $45, and $50. Notice that
because each income level is equally likely, the average income is $30
before taxes are paid.
The tax you pay on income will be one of two types. With Tax 1, all
participants in this room will pay a tax of $7.50. With Tax 2, the tax
paid varies across income levels. The following table summarizes the tax
that is paid for each income level.
Tax 1 ($) Tax 2 ($)
Pretax After-Tax After-Tax
Income ($) Tax Payoff Tax Payoff
10.00 7.50 2.50 0 10.00
15.00 7.50 7.50 2.00 13.00
20.00 7.50 12.50 3.00 17.00
25.00 7.50 17.50 4.00 21.00
30.00 7.50 22.50 7.50 22.50
35.00 7.50 27.50 11.00 24.00
40.00 7.50 32.50 12.00 28.00
45.00 7.50 37.50 13.00 32.00
50.00 7.50 42.50 15.00 35.00
Note: The amount paid with Tax 2 varies in Treatment 4 and 5.
The tax structures are reported in Table 2.
Whether the tax you pay is Tax 1 or Tax 2 will be determined by
majority vote. After the experimenter distributes the income cards, you
will be given 5 min to indicate which tax you prefer. When all
participants have recorded their votes on their Record Sheets, the
experimenter will tally the votes and report on the outcome. Please
record the tax paid and your after-tax payoff on your Record Sheet. Your
income is your private information and should not be disclosed to other
participants at any time.
Note: In Treatment 1, income cards are distributed after votes are
recorded.
We will repeat these steps five times. At the end of each trial,
the tax chosen by the majority vote is announced. However, only one of
the five trials will be binding. A number from 1 to 5 will be randomly
selected to determine the binding trial. Your after-tax payoff from the
binding trial is yours to keep and will be paid to you in cash.
Note: In Treatment 3, the outcome of voting each round is not
revealed until the conclusion of the session.
Please do not confer with other participants in making your
decisions at any time. Please remember that once you record your vote in
each trial, you cannot change it.
Record Sheet
[TABLE OMITTED]
APPENDIX 2: PROOF OF LINEAR DEPENDENCE
This appendix shows that an exact linear relationship exists
between changes in own payoff, disadvantageous inequality, advantageous
inequality, and the sum of total payouts.
PROPOSITION 1: The change in the sum of total payoffs ([DELTA]E) is
an exact linear function of the sum of a change in own payoff, a change
in the index of disadvantageous inequality and a change in the index of
advantageous inequality under any two tax regimes, or [DELTA]E =
n[DELTA][[pi].sub.i] + (n - 1)[DELTA][D.sub.i] (n - 1)[DELTA]A[I.sub.i]
for all i, where [DELTA]E = [[summation].sup.n.sub.i=1]
([[pi].sub.1i][[pi].sub.2i]) is the difference in the sum of the
after-tax payoffs under Tax regimes 1 and 2.
Before proceeding with the proof of this proposition it is helpful
to establish our notation and rewrite some familiar expressions. Let
[[pi].sub.ki] be the after-tax payoff of individual i = 1, ..., n under
tax regime k = 1, 2. Further, assume that the after-tax payoofs are
ranked in ascending order such that [[pi].sub.-i] [less than or equal
to] [[pi].sub.k2] [less than or equal to] ... [less than or equal to]
[[pi].sub.ki] [less than or equal to] ... [less than or equal to]
[[pi].sub.kn]. This allows us to rewrite [DI.sub.ki] and [AI.sub.ki] as
follows:
[DI.sub.ki] = [(n - 1) [sup.-1] [n. summation over ([for
all]j>i)] ([[pi].sub.kj] - [[pi].sub.ki]) and [AI.sub.ki] = [(n - 1)
[sup.1] [(n - 1).sup.-1] [n. summation over (j = 1)] (([[pi].sub.ki] -
([[pi].sub.kj]).
With these definitions in hand, we proceed to a proof of our
proposition.
Proof. We begin with the following expression: [nS.sub.ki] + (n -
1)[DI.sub.ki] - (n - 1)[AI.sub.ki].
Now, we rewrite this expression.
[MATHEMATICAL EXPRESSION NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII].
Since [DELTA] is a linear operator, this completes the proof.
This result is extremely useful. It shows that the FS model is
flexible enough to represent a variety of theories of individual choice
with different linear restrictions on the coefficients of the FS model.
(1) [Vote.sub.i] = [a.sub.1] + [a.sub.2][DELTA][S.sub.1] +
[a.sub.2][[DELTA]I.sub.i] + [a.sub.3][DELTA][DI.sub.i] +
[a.sub.4][DELTA][AI.sub.i] + [e.sub.i]
(2) [Vote.sub.i] = [a.sub.1] + [a.sub.2][DELTA][S.sub.1] +
[epsilon]
(3) [Vote.sub.i] = [a.sub.1] + [a.sub.2][DELTA][S.sub.1], +
[a.sub.3][DELTA]E + [e.sub.1].
Model (1) is the FS model of income inequality aversion.
Model (2) is the model of purely selfish preferences and is
equivalent to (1) with two linear restrictions on the coefficients:
[a.sub.3] = [a.sub.4] = 0.
Model (3) is Harsanyi's model of social preferences and is
equivalent to (1) with two linear restrictions on the coefficients:
[a.sub.3] = [a.sub.4] = [a.sub.3].
These relationships allow us to use a likelihood ratio test to
evaluate the linear restrictions implied by (2) and (3) with respect to
the unrestricted model of (1). In each case, the likelihood ratio test
statistic is distributed [chi square], with df equal to the number of
restrictions (df = 2).
REFERENCES
Aim, J. "Tax Compliance and Administration." in Handbook
on Taxation, edited by W. B. Hildreth and J. A. Richardson. New York:
Marcel Dekker, Inc., 1998, 741-68.
Aim, J., B. R. Jackson, and M. McKee. "Fiscal Exchange,
Collective Decision Institutions, and Tax Compliance." Journal of
Economic Behavior and Organization, 22, 1993, 285-303.
Aim, J., G. H. McClelland, and W. D. Schultze. "Changing
Social Norm of Tax Compliance by Voting." Kyklos, 52, 1999, 141-71.
Andreoni, J.. B. Erard, and J. Feinstein. "Tax
Compliance." Journal of Economic Literature, 36(2), 1998, 818-60.
Bagnoli. M., and M. McKee. "Voluntary Contribution Games:
Efficient Provision of Public Goods." Economic Inquiry, 29(2),
1991, 351-66.
Bicchieri, C., and J. Zhang. "Ultimatum Behavior: Fairness
Preferences or Fairness Norms?" Working Paper, Carnegie Mellon,
Department of Philosophy, 2004.
Bolton, G. E., and A. Ockenfels. "ERC: A Theory, of Equity,
Reciprocity, and Competition." The American Economic Review, 90(1),
2000, 166-93.
Brosnan, S. F., and F. B. M. de Waal. "Monkeys Reject Unequal
Pay." Letter to Nature, 425, 2004, 297.
Camerer, C. F. "Progress in Behavioral Game Theory."
Journal of Economic Perspective, 11(4), 1997, 167-88.
Charness, G., and M. Rabin. "Understanding Social Preferences
with Simple Tests." The Quarterly Journal of Economics, 117(3),
2002, 817-69.
Davis, D. D., and C. A. Holt. Experimental Economics. Princeton,
NJ: Princeton University Press, 1993.
Eichenberger, R., and F. Oberholzer-Gee. "Rational Moralists:
The Role of Fairness in Democratic Economic Politics." Public
Choice, 94(1-2), 1998, 191-210.
Engelmann, D., and M. Strobel. "Inequality Aversion,
Efficiency, and Maximin Preferences in Simple Distribution
Experiments." The American Economic Review, 94(4), 2004, 857-69.
Fehr, E., and K. M. Schmidt. "A Theory of Fairness,
Competition, and Cooperation." The Quarterly Journal of Economics,
114(3), 1999, 817-68.
Frohlich, N., and J. A. Oppenheimer. Choosing Justice: An
Experimental Approach to Ethical Theory. Berkeley: University of
California Press, 1992.
Gemmell, N., O. Morrissey, and A. Pinar. "Tax Perceptions and
Preferences over Tax Structure in the United Kingdom." The Economic
Journal 114, 2004, 117-38.
Greene, W. H. Econometric Analysis. 5th ed. New York:
Prentice-Hall, 2002.
Gvth, W., R. Schmittenberger, and R. Tietz. "Ultimatum
Bargaining Behavior A Survey and Comparison of Experimental
Results." Journal of Economic Psychology, 11(3), 1990, 417-49.
Harsanyi, J. "Cardinal Utility and the Theory of
Risk-Taking." The Journal of Political Economy, 61, 1953, 434-35.
--. "Cardinal Utility, Individualistic Ethics, and
Interpersonal Comparisons of Utility in Welfare Economics." The
Journal of Political Economy, 63, 1955, 302-21.
Hite, P. A., and M. L. Roberts. "An Experimental Investigation
of Taxpayer Judgments on Rate Structure in the Individual Income Tax
System." Journal of the American Taxation Association, 13(2), 1991,
47-63.
Hoffman, E., K. McCabe, K. Shachat, and V. Smith.
"Preferences, Property Rights, and Anonymity in Bargaining
Games." Games and Economic Behavior, 7(3), 1994, 346-380.
Hsiao, C. Analysis of Panel Data. 2nd ed. New York: Cambridge
University Press, 2003.
Kahneman, D., J. L. Knetsch, and R. Thaler. "Fairness as a
Constraint on Profit Seeking: Entitlements in the Market." The
American Economic Review, 76(4), 1986, 728-41.
Kramer, G. H. "On a Class of Equilibrium Conditions for
Majority Rule." Econometrica, 41 (2), 1973, 285-97.
Ledyard, J. "Public Goods: A Survey of Experimental
Research," in Handbook of Experimental Economics, edited by J. H.
Kagel, H. John, and A. E. Roth. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University
Press, 1995, 111-94.
Lewis, A. "Perceptions of Tax Rates." British Tax Review,
1978, 358-66.
McCaffery, E. J., and J. Baron. "Masking Redistribution (or
Its Absence)." Research Paper No. 04-09, Institute for Law and
Economics, University of Pennsylvania Law School, 2004.
McFadden, D. "Econometric Analysis of Qualitative Response
Models," in Hamlbook of Econometrics, Vol. 2, edited by Z.
Griliches, and M. Intriligator. Amsterdam: North Holland, 1984,
1395-1457.
Rawls, J. A Theory of Justice. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University
Press, 1971.
Roth, A. E., V. Parsnikar, M. Okuno-Fujiwara, and S. Zamir.
"Bargaining and Market Behavior in Jerusalem, Ljubljana,
Pittsburgh, and Tokyo: An Experimental Study." The American
Economic Review, 81(5), 1991, 1068-95.
Sheffrin, S. M. "Perceptions of Fairness in the Crucible of
Tax Policy," in Tax Progressivity and Income Inequality, edited by
J. Slemrod. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1994, 309-34.
(1.) See, for example, Bolton and Ockenfels (2000), Camerer (1997),
Charness and Rabin (2002), Frohlich and Oppenheimer (1992), and Ledyard
(1995). There is substantial evidence suggesting that social preferences
influence behavior in a variety of environments. Kahneman, Knetsch, and
Thaler (1986) find that social preferences influence firm-pricing
policies; Guth, Schmittenberger, and Tietz(1990) find that social
preferences influence outcomes in ultimatum bargaining games; and
Bagnoli and McKee (1991) show that social preferences influence public
goods experiments, to name just a few. To be fair, there is some
evidence suggesting that fairness considerations may not be important in
other environments, such as Fehr and Schmidt (1999) and Roth et al.
(1991).
(2.) Gemmell, Morrissey, and Pinar (2004) and Lewis (1978) use
survey data to uncover individual preferences for progressive tax
structures. Hite and Roberts (1991) use experiments to investigate
preferences for the degree of tax progressivity, and McCaffery and Baron
(2004) investigate the effects of framing on preferences for progressive
taxation. Sheffrin (1994) provides a comprehensive review of papers in
this area.
(3.) By efficiency, we mean maximizing the sum of individual
payoffs.
(4.) ES provide some evidence based on sessions in which the
subjects know their position in the income distribution and are required
to sacrifice to achieve greater equity and/or efficiency. However, these
experiments are mentioned only in passing to test the robustness of
results obtained from their canonical experiments with role uncertainty,
and the decision maker's own payoff is unaffected by the choice of
distribution.
(5.) Eichenberger and Oberholzer-Gee (1998) provide experimental
evidence that is consistent with the argument that behavior is fairer in
a political sphere because social norms can be observed through voting
behavior, which is nearly costless to observe.
(6.) Inequality is disadvantageous when a reference individual
earns more than the person evaluating the outcome. Advantageous
inequality arises when the reference individual makes less than the
evaluator.
(7.) One feature of this model is the potential for high
correlation among the three terms. We discuss the empirical implications
of this correlation below.
(8.) Since learning may occur, we perform a statistical test for
"round" effects. As discussed below, the test rejects round
effects at conventional levels of significance. However, repeated game
effects, such as "cooperative" choices, should not be of
concern because the nine participants in each of our experimental
sessions vote anonymously. Further to ensure that cooperation is not a
determinant of behavior we include Treatment 3, as described
subsequently. In this treatment, participants do not know the outcome of
the majority vote each round until the conclusion of the session.
(9.) To establish a consistent pretax payoff distribution across
the nine sessions, it is necessary to choose a fixed number of
participants for each session. We eliminate the possibility of a split
majority or 50-50 vote by requiring an odd number of subjects. We
settled on nine participants in order to provide anonymity among the
participants on the one hand and to limit the total cost of the
experiments on the other.
(10.) Some critics question the relevance of insight provided by
experiments with student subject pools. If the average person behaves
differently from university students, we should be cautious in drawing
inferences about the general population. Davis and Holt (1993, 17)
provide some evidence that the behavior of subjects drawn from other
populations is not markedly different from the behavior of student
subjects.
(11.) Of course, people may behave differently when their income is
earned rather than endowed. In particular, people may be more
predisposed to fairness when endowed. Hoffman et al. (1994) provide
experimental evidence that first movers in dictator and ultimatum games
offer less when the first mover is decided by the higher score on a
general knowledge test.
(12.) In Treatments 4 and 5, we simulate the excess burden of
progressive taxation by using two tax regimes that are not revenue
neutral, as discussed below.
(13.) During the experiments, we used the more neutral terms Tax 1
and Tax 2 rather than lump-sum tax and progressive tax to refer to the
two tax regimes in order to avoid unintentionally biasing the responses.
(14.) Clearly. we are concerned in this study with outcome
fairness. By using majority voting to decide the outcome, we have
invoked a process, which we believe to be widely accepted as process
fair. However, it would be interesting in future research to examine the
sensitivity of the results reported here to alternative decision rules
such as supermajority or weighted voting schemes. There is a related
literature that examines process fairness. For example, in a series of
laboratory experiments, Aim, Jackson, and McKee (1993) find that there
is a relationship between lax compliance and the decision mechanism used
for the allocation of tax revenues. In a related study, Alto,
McClelland, and Schultze (1999) find that allowing participants to
choose the enforcement regime may affect a social norm for tax
compliance.
(15.) As part of the empirical analysis described subsequently, we
include dummy variables for the rounds and find no evidence of a round
effect.
(16.) Participants are paid $2 for timely arrival to the
experimental session and $2 for completion of a postexperiment
questionnaire. Thus, while the average after-tax earnings in the
revenue-neutral treatments are $22.50, the average compensation is
$26.50, with a range of $6.50-$46.50.
(17.) In a strict sense, removing the "veil of ignorance"
only removes the uncertainty regarding one's income. Uncertainty
remains as to how others will vote, and we cannot rule out an effect on
voting from this type of uncertainty. However, uncertainty regarding how
others will vote is equally present behind the "veil of
ignorance."
(18.) In Treatment 2, the median-payoff participant is decisive in
80% of the trials and in only 55% of the trials in Treatment 3. The
median voter hypothesis predicts that the decisive voter should be the
median-payoff participant. For an equilibrium to exist under majority
rule, preferences must be single peaked. Kramer (1973) shows that an
equilibrium may not exist under majority rule if the commodity or policy
space is multidimensional. In the current context, at least some of the
participants exhibit a concern for their own payoff as well as for the
payoffs of others, meaning that the policy choice among alternative tax
structures is multidimensional. Therefore, the assumptions of the median
voter hypothesis may not be satisfied in the current setting and thus
apply in collective choice regarding redistributive policies. This may
have important implications for ES's experimental design in which
the median-payoff participant is the sole decision maker. We would like
to thank an anonymous referee for bringing this issue to our attention.
(19.) As the excess burden of the distortionary progressive tax
increases, we observe that the number of people voting for the
progressive tax (Tax 2) decreases. This suggests that there may be a
downward sloping demand for fairness. This is an interesting issue for
further study.
(20.) As described previously, efficiency is measured by the sum of
the individual payoffs.
(21.) Appendix 2 includes a proof of the proposition that the
change in the sum of total payoffs is a linear combination of changes in
own payoff, disadvantageous inequality, and advantageous inequality.
(22.) [DI.sub.i] and [AI.sub.i] are as defined previously in
Section 1.
(23.) We also used as an alternative measure of efficiency a dummy
variable taking the value of 1 for Treatments 4 and 5, which are not
revenue neutral. Inferences are similar to those reported subsequently.
(24.) Greene (2002), for example, shows that the assumption of unit
variance is an innocent normalization. Also, Hsiao (2003) provides an
excellent discussion of discrete choice as well as fixed- and
random-effects models.
(25.) For the random-effects model, the likelihood (for an
independent unit i) is expressed as an integral, which is computed in
STATA using Gauss-Hermite quadrature. STATA recommends that the fitted
model be evaluated for sensitivity to the chosen number of quadrature
points. As a rule of thumb, if the coefficients do not change by more
than a relative difference of 0.01%, then the choice of quadrature
points does not significantly affect the outcome and the results may be
confidently interpreted. When we change the number of quadrature points
by [+ or -] 4 points, our estimates do not change by more than the
indicated 0.01%.
(26.) The results of Treatment 1 are not used to estimate these
models. To calculate the regressors in these models, we need a reference
payoff. Because pretax income is unknown to the subjects before voting
in Treatment I, the choice of reference income for the calculations of
the regressors is not obvious. In any event, the regressors would be
identical for any choice of reference income. For example, the expected
payoff is an obvious candidate to serve as the reference income.
However, the regressors would be identical for every observation for
this or any other choice of reference income in Treatment 1.
(27.) To test for learning or order effects, we include individual
dummy variables for each round, dropping the dummy variable for Round 5.
This vector of estimated coefficients is statistically insignificant,
and the other results are virtually identical to those in Table 5. We
also estimate the regressions in Table 5 with a dummy variable for
gender (female = 1). This estimated coefficient is statistically
insignificant at conventional levels. These results are available from
the authors upon request.
(28.) Like a conventional [R.sup.2] in the context of ordinary
least squares, McFadden's pseudo-[R.sup.2] increases as the number
of regressors in the model increases. Accordingly, we adjust the
likelihood ratio index by subtracting K, the number of regressors in the
model, from the numerator of the index. See McFadden (1984) and footnote d of Table 5 for further details.
(29.) We estimate variants of the regressions reported in Table 4
by including a dummy variable for Treatment 3. The estimated coefficient
of this dummy variable is statistically insignificant at conventional
levels. We also estimate all three models on the 315 observations from
Treatments 2, 4, and 5. Again, these estimates are nearly identical to
those reported in Table 5. This supports our conclusion in the previous
section that there does not appear to be any attempt to signal
cooperation in Treatments 2, 4, and 5 when the majority vote is
announced after each trial. These results are available from the authors
upon request.
(30.) As previously discussed, there is nearly exact
multicollinearity among the regressors of the FS model. A recommended
remedy for near-exact multicollinearity is to increase the sample size.
Tellingly, the significance level of the estimated coefficient of Dl
increases when the sample size increases from 315 observations (p =
0.312) to 450 observations (p = 0.115). This suggests that a further
increase in the sample size may result in a statistically significant
estimate. These results are available from the authors upon request.
(31.) If norm-based explanations of social preferences are
ultimately shown to be the origin or source of social preferences, it
may be possible to identify the distribution of social preferences using
observable characteristics of the individuals making up that population,
such as gender, country of origin, religious affiliation. If, on the
other hand. social preferences have an evolutionary basis, then it may
not be possible to identify the distribution of social preferences using
observable characteristics of the population.
LUCY F. ACKERT, JORGE MARTINEZ-VAZQUEZ, and MARK RIDER *
* The views expressed here are those of the authors and not
necessarily those of the Federal Reserve Bank of Atlanta or the Federal
Reserve System. The authors gratefully acknowledge the financial support
of the Federal Reserve Bank of Atlanta and the International Studies
Program of Georgia State University. The authors thank Aye Chatupromwong
and Budina Naydenova for research assistance, and Francisco Arze, Ann
Gillette, Bryan Church, Govind Hariharan, Luc Noiset, Paula Tkac, and
Roy Wada for helpful discussions and comments.
Ackert: Professor. Michael J. Coles College of Business, 1000
Chastain Road, Kennesaw State University, Kennesaw, GA 30144. Phone
770-423-6111, Fax 770-4993209, E-mail: lackert@kennesaw.edu; and
Research Department, Federal Reserve Bank of Atlanta, 1000 Peachtree
Street NE, Atlanta, GA 30309-4470.
Martinez-Vazquez: Professor, Andrew Young School of Policy Studies,
Georgia State University, 14 Marietta Street, Atlanta, GA 30303. Phone
404-651-3989, Fax 404-651-4449, E-mail: jorgemartinez@gsu.edu
Rider: Associate Professor, Andrew Young School of Policy Studies,
Georgia State University, 14 Marietta Street, Atlanta, GA 30303, Phone
404-651-1687, Fax 404-651-4449, E-mail: mrider@gsu.edu
TABLE 1 Experimental Design
Vote before Results of Vote
or after Reported after
Treatment Sessions Income Revealed? Each Round?
1 1-3 Before Yes
2 4-6 After Yes
3 7-9 After No (a)
4 10-11 After Yes
5 12-13 After Yes
Number with Higher
Amount of Head After-Tax Payoff
Treatment Tax ($) with Head Tax
1 7.50 4 out of 9
2 7.50 4 out of 9
3 7.50 4 out of 9
4 2.50 7 out of 9
5 5.00 5 out of 9
(a) The result of each round of voting is with held from the
participants until the conclusion of all five rounds to control for
the potential influence on individual voting of observing whether
others are "cooperating" by voting for the progressive tax.
TABLE 2
Tax Structures
Tax I: Head Tax ($)
Pretax Income (S) Tax After-Tax Payoff
Panel A: Treatments 1 through 3 (Sessions 1-9)
10.00 7.50 2.50
15.00 7.50 7.50
20.00 7.50 12.50
25.00 7.50 17.50
30.00 7.50 22.50
35.00 7.50 27.50
40.00 7.50 32.50
45.00 7.50 37.50
50.00 7.50 42.50
Total 67.50 202.50
Panel B: Treatment 4 (Sessions 10-11)
10.00 2.50 7.50
15.00 2.50 12.50
20.00 2.50 17.50
25.00 2.50 22.50
30.00 2.50 27.50
35.00 2.50 32.50
40.00 2.50 37.50
45.00 2.50 42.50
50.00 2.50 47.50
Total 22.50 247.50
Panel C: Treatment 5 (Sessions 12-13)
10.00 5.00 5.00
15.00 5.00 10.00
20.00 5.00 15.00
25.00 5.00 20.00
30.00 5.00 25.00
35.00 5.00 30_00
40.00 5.00 35.00
45.00 5.00 40.00
50.00 5.00 45.00
Total 45.00 225.00
Tax 2: Progressive Tax ($)
Pretax Income (S) Tax After-Tax Payoff
Panel A: Treatments 1 through 3 (Sessions 1-9)
10.00 0 10.00
15.00 2.00 13.00
20.00 3.00 17.00
25.00 4.00 21.00
30.00 7.50 22.50
35.00 11.00 24.00
40.00 12.00 28.00
45.00 13.00 32.00
50.00 15.00 35.00
Total 67.50 202.50
Panel B: Treatment 4 (Sessions 10-11)
10.00 0 10.00
15.00 2.00 13.00
20.00 3.00 17.00
25.00 4.00 21.00
30.00 7.50 22.50
35.00 11.00 24.00
40.00 12.00 28.00
45.00 13.00 32.00
50.00 15.00 35.00
Total 67.50 202.50
Panel C: Treatment 5 (Sessions 12-13)
10.00 0 10.00
15.00 2.00 13.00
20.00 3.00 17.00
25.00 4.00 21.00
30.00 7.50 22.50
35.00 11.00 24.00
40.00 12.00 28.00
45.00 13.00 32.00
50.00 15.00 35.00
Total 67.50 202.50
TABLE 3
Majority Voting
Number of Sessions with
Majority Voting for
Treatment Sessions Tax 1 Tax 2
(Head Tax) (Progressive Tax)
1 1-3 4 11
2 4-6 5 10
3 7-9 4 11
4 10-11 10 0
5 12-13 8 2
Percentage of Percentage of
Treatment Majority Vote Votes for Tax 1
1 0.64 0.40
2 0.56 0.44
3 0.55 0.44
4 0.81 0.81
5 0.54 0.56
TABLE 4
Voting by Income
Treatment 1 (Sessions 1-3)
Income Tax 1 (a) Tax 2 (b)
10 9 6
15 4 11
20 6 9
25 7 8
30 4 11
35 7 8
40 2 13
45 7 8
50 8 7
Total 54 81
Treatment 2 (Sessions 4-6)
Income Tax 1 Tax 2
10 1 14
15 0 15
20 0 15
25 0 15
30 7 8
35 13 2
40 13 2
45 11 4
50 14 1
Total 59 76
Treatment 3 (Sessions 7-9)
Income Tax l Tax 2
10 0 15
15 0 15
20 0 15
25 0 15
30 10 6
35 13 1
40 13 2
45 12 3
50 12 3
Total 60 75
Treatment 4 (Sessions 10-11)
Income Tax 1 Tax 2
10 2 8
15 3 7
20 9 1
25 10 0
30 10 0
35 10 0
40 10 0
45 9 1
50 10 11
Total 73 17
Treatment 5 (Sessions 12-13)
Income Tax 1 Tax 2
10 0 10
15 0 10
20 0 10
25 2 8
30 9 1
35 10 0
40 10 0
45 9 1
50 10 0
Total 50 40
(a) Tax 1 is a head tax.
(b) Tax 2 is a progressive tax.
TABLE 5
Random-Effects Probit Regressions of Voting
Independent Variable Purely Selfish Model
Constant -0.35114 (-1.85) *
Change in own after-tax 0.4804 (9.99) *** [0,1783]
payoff
Change in the sum of total --
after-tax payoffs
Change in disadvantageous --
inequality
Change in advantageous --
inequality
Number of observations 450
[chi square] test of the 13.69 ***
significance of the model
against the FS model
[chi square] test of the 99.74 ***
significance of the
regression
Estimated value of the -118.15
log-likelihood function
McFadden's adjusted -0.63042
pseudo-[R.sup.2]
Independent Variable SE Model
Constant -0.6153 (3.57) ***
Change in own after-tax 0.4814 (9.78) *** [0.1791]
payoff
Change in the sum of total 0.0191 * (1.85) [0,0071]
after-tax payoffs
Change in disadvantageous --
inequality
Change in advantageous --
inequality
Number of observations 450
[chi square] test of the 9.20 ***
significance of the model
against the FS model
[chi square] test of the 95.91 ***
significance of the
regression
Estimated value of the -116.41
log-likelihood function
McFadden's adjusted 0.6167
pseudo-[R.sup.2]
Independent Variable FS Model
Constant 1.9988 (2.24) **
Change in own after-tax 0.7006 (6115) *** [0.2722]
payoff
Change in the sum of total --
after-tax payoffs
Change in disadvantageous -0.2450 (-1.58) [-0.0953]
inequality
Change in advantageous -0.6172 (-3.50) *** [-0.2398]
inequality
Number of observations 450
[chi square] test of the --
significance of the model
against the FS model
[chi square] test of the 96.25 ***
significance of the
regression
Estimated value of the -111.81
log-likelihood function
McFadden's adjusted 0.6313
pseudo-[R.sup.2]
Notes: In the upper panel, estimated coefficients are reported first.
t-statistics for the, estimated coefficients are provided in
parentheses (), and the corresponding marginal effects in brackets [].
Although we do not report t-statistics for the marginal effects,
there is no change in significance for any of the variables.
A single asterisk (*) indicates that the estimate is significant at
the 10% level, a double asterisk (**) indicates significance at the
5% level, and a triple asterisk (***) indicates significance at the
1% level.
McFadden's adjusted pseudo-[R.sup.2] = 1 - (ln [??] - K)/ln [L.sub.0],
wherer ln[[L.sub.0]] is the maximized value of the log-likelihood
function computed with only a constant term, ln [[??]] is the maximized
value of the log-likelihood function for the model, and K is the number
of regressors (see footnotes 28 for further details).