A theory of affirmative action in college admissions.
Fu, Qiang
I. INTRODUCTION
Race-conscious preferential admissions have been widely practiced
by selective colleges and universities to enhance minority
representation in higher education. For example, the College of Arts and
Sciences at the University of Michigan automatically added 20 .points
(out of a possible 150 points) to a minority applicant's score in
its rating system. Harvard University has an "unofficial lift"
scheme, which also targets minority applicants. However, controversy has
surrounded affirmative action ever since its inception. For instance,
California, Texas, and Florida have already terminated the use of
race-conscious admissions at state-funded institutions. This debate
culminated in the recent Supreme Court ruling regarding admissions
procedures at the University of Michigan, which endorsed admissions
rules that took into account race as a qualifying characteristic.
Unfortunately, positive studies on this issue have been scarce
relative to the high profile of the debate. According to Holzer and
Neumark (1999), theoretical studies of the efficiency of affirmative
action on education are "virtually nonexistent." Some have
argued that affirmative action is merely a patronage program and
necessarily results in "mediocracy" rather than meritocracy.
In the debate on affirmative action practices in college admissions, a
major criticism is that affirmative action designed to create diversity
comes at the cost of academic quality. A competing view, offered by
those opposed to affirmative action, is that it weakens school
applicants' incentives to achieve academic excellence. For
instance, Justice Thomas wrote in his opinion in Grutter v. Bollinger that "there is no incentive for the black applicant to continue to
prepare for the LSAT once he is reasonably assured of achieving the
requisite score." Supporters of this practice tend to emphasize the
importance of diversity and the positive influence of diversity on the
pedagogical environment (Steele, 1990). These views, however, do not
fully recognize the incentive structure behind affirmative action
admissions rules. It is unclear how a college-admissions rule affects
high school students' incentives to achieve academic excellence,
which adds to their human capital stock and future productivity.
The process of college admissions by and large resembles a contest
in which contestants exert costly effort in order to win a limited
number of prizes. In the context of college admissions, to compete for a
limited number of seats in the incoming class, college candidates have
to present their academic credentials (such as GPA and SAT score) to the
admissions officer. To win the seat, high school students have to invest
in their human capital, which improves the academic performance, whereas
the academic investments are costly and nonrefundable regardless of the
outcome--for example, the tuition, the money spent on books, the salary
paid to tutors, the time and energy, and so on. All of these features
may be approximated by an all-pay auction mechanism.
We propose a simple theoretical framework that models the process
of college admissions as an all-pay auction, to investigate two major
questions: Is there any theoretical rationale for an affirmative action
admissions rule? How do such rules affect college candidates'
incentives to invest in academic effort? Two candidates--one a minority
and the other a nonminority--simultaneously choose their academic
efforts (human capital investments) to compete for a seat in a college.
We show that an academic quality--oriented college prefers to adopt an
admissions rule that scales up the test score of the minority relative
to the nonminority. Although this rule is designed purely to maximize
the expected academic quality of the incoming class, it turns out to
favor the minority and create ethnic diversity. We show that the unique
equilibrium (affirmative action) admissions rule creates a positive
"cross-group interaction" between college candidates'
incentives to make educational effort. As a consequence, a pro-minority
rule levels the playing field and leads both candidates to exert higher
academic effort. The results therefore reconcile the commonly assumed
conflicts between academic quality and ethnic diversity. Paradoxically,
however, we show that the nonminority candidate responds to the
pro-minority admissions rule more aggressively than the minority, which
tends to widen the existing racial test-score gap.
A growing literature has emerged that investigates the effect of
affirmative action on agents' incentives to invest in human
capital. Most of these studies are built on the theory of statistical
discrimination, such as Phelps (1972). In a job assignment model, Coate
and Loury (1993) find that affirmative action, represented by a mandated
equal assignment rate, exerts mixed effects on minority workers'
incentives. By contrast, Moro and Norman (2003) find a negative
externality between the two groups' incentives: affirmative action
may increase the minority workers' incentive to invest in learning
but diminish the nonminority's. Furstenburg (2003) explicitly
models affirmative action in the context of college admissions. He shows
that a college may adopt an affirmative action admissions rule to
enhance the academic quality of its class. He also identifies a negative
externality that parallels Moro and Norman (2003), which implies that
affirmative-action narrows the racial test score gap.
In contrast to this strand of the literature, we adopt a
contest-theoretic approach to model the college admissions process,
which yields a positive "cross-group" interaction. A handful
of theoretical studies have recognized the resemblance between college
admissions and contests. For example, Fernandez and Gali (1999) compare
the efficiency of tournaments (placement exams such as SAT) with markets
as allocative mechanisms. Amegashie and Wu (2004) model college
admissions process as all-pay auctions and examine the selection effects
of this system. However, neither of these studies concerns itself with
affirmative action. In a laboratory setting, Schotter and Weigelt (1992)
find that affirmative action may increase the total output of a
tournament. A recent study by Fryer and Loury (forthcoming) shares some
of the features of my model. They use a tournament model to investigate
the categorical redistribution in a winner-take-all market and show that
optimally designed tournaments naturally involve
"handicapping."
We model racial inequality by assuming that attending college
creates differential returns across college candidates. The inferior
return on the minority's investment in human capital may result
from various factors. First of all, the investment in human capital may
be unfairly rewarded in the labor market. On the other hand, the unfair
labor market may not be real but may exist out of perception. If the
minority holds pessimistic expectation toward reward in the labor
market, the incentive to invest on human capital is also impaired.
Although most studies assume that the minority and nonminority bear
differential human capital investment costs, my model does not lose its
bite on the potential difference in this regard, because higher learning
costs simply reduce the net return.
This article is organized as follows. Section II sets up the model.
Section III shows the equilibrium outcome and discusses the incentive
content of affirmative action. Section IV concerns the impacts of
admissions rule on minority representation and the racial test-score
gap. Section V presents a concluding remark.
II. A MODEL OF COLLEGE ADMISSIONS
This model involves two college candidates indexed by i = M, N, who
compete for one seat at a college. One candidate, M, is minority,
whereas the other candidate, N, is nonminority. The admissions game
proceeds as follows. At the beginning of the game, the college announces
its admissions rule. The screening is primarily based on
candidates' scores in a standardized college-entrance test. Upon
observing the admissions rule, college candidates determine how much
academic effort to spend preparing for the test. The academic efforts
are converted to their scores, [q.sub.M] and [q.sub.N], in the test.
Finally, the college observes their test scores and admits one of them
into the incoming class according to the rule announced before.
The College
The college is concerned with the academic quality of its student
body. A better-qualified incoming class builds up the college's
reputation and increases its value. The objective of the college's
admissions office is to maximize the expected academic quality of the
admitted student, which is represented by the expected test score (Q) of
the accepted candidate.
The admissions decision is primarily based on candidates' test
scores. However, the college may take into account a candidate's
identity as a qualifying characteristic. The college has the flexibility
to assign a weight [alpha.sub.i] [member of] (0, [infinity]) to a
candidate i's test score. As a consequence, candidate i receives a
rating [[alpha.sub.i][q.sub.i] in the college's assessment system.
Candidate is admitted if i's rating is higher than the
competitor's, that is, [[alpha].sub.i][q.sub.i] >
[[alpha].sub.j][q.sub.j]. In the event that they tie, the seat is
randomly assigned to one of them. We normalize the weight assigned to
candidate N's test score to be 1 and the weight for candidate M to
be [alpha] [equivalent to] [[alpha].sub.M]/[[alpha].sub.N] [member of]
(0, [infinity].
The admissions rule is parameterized by [alpha], and the college
chooses the optimal [alpha] to maximize Q. The value of G represents the
ex ante preference of the college between candidates. When [alpha] >
1, the minority candidate's test score weighs relatively more than
that of the nonminority counterpart, which represents an
affirmative-action admissions mechanism. When [alpha] < 1, the
admissions rule is biased against the minority candidate. When [alpha] =
1, no characteristic other than test score matters in the admissions
decision, which represents a "color-blind" admissions scheme.
College Candidates
A candidate i privately values the admission at [V.sub.i] [member
of] (0, [infinity]), which represents the additional benefit that i
receives by attending college, such as higher income and social
recognition. By my assumptions, we have [V.sub.N] > [V.sub.M] > O.
A candidate i exerts academic effort [e.sub.i] to improve test score
[q.sub.i] in the standardized entrance test, which is taken by the
college as the primary screening criterion. A higher score increases the
likelihood that one is admitted, whereas such a score reduces the
competitor's chance. We assume that no innate ability difference
exists across candidates and that they are endowed with an identical
linear test-score production technology, given by [q.sub.i] = [e.sub.i].
This linear test score production function enables us to interchange the
notation q and e.
Although academic quality accrues to the college's value,
these candidates value only the benefit they may obtain by attending
college, whereas the academic effort they expend is costly. We assume
that the academic effort incurs a unit cost on its margin. Hence, a
candidate i receives [V.sub.] - [e.sub.i] as payoff if admitted, whereas
i receives - [e.sub.i] if rejected. Candidate M and N's payoff
functions, respectively, are as follows.
(1) [MATHEMATICAL EXPRESSION NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII]
(2) [MATHEMATICAL EXPRESSION NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII]
The asymmetry in [V.sub.i] may stem from two major sources. As
discussed before, because of the existence or the perception of racial
inequality in the labor market, the minority candidate may expect a
lower return from college education than a nonminority counterpart may
expect and therefore undervalue the higher education. Alternatively, the
differential return to college education may also arise if the minority
bears a higher marginal cost to achieve academic excellence, which is
assumed in a number of previous studies. Higher learning costs simply
reduce the minority candidate's return from education. Due to the
linear payoff structure, a model that assumes asymmetric costs is a
monotonic transformation of ours and produces equivalent results.
III. THE EQUILIBRIUM
To solve the admissions game in a backward fashion, we first
examine college candidates' strategies after they learn the
admissions rule. Then we find the college's choice that best
addresses its objective, taking into account candidates' responses.
College Candidates' Strategies
In my framework, the admissions process is abstracted as an all-pay
auction where college candidates enter their test scores as bids. The
equilibrium of a standard complete-information all-pay auction has been
thoroughly investigated by Hillman and Riley (1989), and Baye et al.
(1996). My approach is close to these two studies but allow the
auctioneer (the college) to unequally weigh bidders (college
candidates)' bids; that is, [alpha] [not equal to] 1.
As a standard property of complete-information all-pay auctions,
only mixed strategy equilibrium may exist in the admissions contest. The
form of the equilibrium in the subgame of admissions contest hinges on
the value of policy parameter [alpha]. When [alpha] <
[V.sub.N]/[V.sub.M], candidate N possesses an advantage against
candidate M. Because candidate M never bids more than valuation
[V.sub.M], candidate N can ensure winning if N exerts an effort
[e.sub.N] = [alpha][V.sub.M], as well as receiving a positive payoff
[V.sub.N]--[alpha][V.sub.M]. By way of contrast, if [alpha] >
[V.sub.N]/[V.sub.M], the college's preferential admissions rule
more than offsets candidate N's initial advantage. Consequently,
candidate M is able to secure the seat and extract positive rent as long
as M bids [V.sub.N]/[alpha], which is less than [V.sub.M]. To ease the
notation in my analysis, we define [theta] [equivalent to] [V.sub.N/]
[V.sub.M] > 1.
Let [F.sub.M] = [F.sub.M]([e.sub.M]) and [F.sub.N] =
[F.sub.N]([e.sub.N]) denote candidate M and N's equilibrium effort
distribution functions, respectively. Using standard technique--such as
that of Hillman and Riley (1989) and Baye et al. (1996)--we show the
following holds in the subgame of admissions contest.
PROPOSITION 1. For any at [alpha] [member of] (0, [theta]], there
exists a unique Nash equilibrium. Candidate N continuously randomizes
effort over the whole support [0, [alpha][V.sub.M], whereas candidate M
continuously randomizes effort over the support (0, [V.sub.M] and places
a probability mass at zero with a size
([V.sub.N]--[alpha][V.sub.M])/[V.sub.N]. The equilibrium effort
distribution functions are given by
(3) [F.sub.N]([e.sub.N]) = [e.sub.N]/[alpha][[V.sub.M],
(4) [F.sub.M]([e.sub.M]) = ([V.sub.N] - [alpha][V.sub.M] +
[alpha][e.sub.M])/[V.sub.N].
For any [alpha] [member of] [[theta], [infinity]), there exists a
unique Nash equilibrium. Candidate M continuously randomizes effort over
the whole support [0, [V.sub.N]/ [alpha], whereas candidate N
continuously randomizes effort over the support (0, [V.sub.N]] and
places a probability mass at zero with a size ([V.sub.M] -
[V.sub.N]/[alpha]) /[V.sub.M]. The equilibrium effort distribution
functions are given by
(5) [F.sub.N]([e.sub.N]) = ([V.sub.M] - [V.sub.N]/[alpha] +
[e.sub.N]/[alpha])/[V.sub.M],
(6) [F.sub.M]([e.sub.M]) = [alpha][e.sub.M]/[V.sub.N].
Proposition 1 characterizes the unique mixed-strategy Nash
equilibrium of the admissions contest for any given [alpha] [member of]
(0, [infinity]). (1) Proposition 1 states that when [alpha] <
[theta], the minority candidate always has a positive probability to
"drop out"; that is, [e.sub.M] = 0. This probability decreases
with [alpha] and reduces to zero once [alpha] = [theta]. Intuitively,
when [alpha] [member of] (0, [theta]], a greater [alpha] increases the
marginal return of candidate M's academic effort, which improves
the incentive to expend academic effort and participate in the
competition. By contrast, when [alpha] [member of] ([theta],
[infinity]), only the nonminority candidate drops out of the competition
with positive probability. Intuitively, an admissions rule with [alpha]
> [theta] excessively favors the minority candidate. Thus, a greater
[alpha] further dampens the incentive of the initially advantaged
nonminority candidate and drives one to drop out.
The College: The Equilibrium (Affirmative Action) Admissions Rule
In the first stage of the game, the college picks its admissions
rule, represented by the value of [alpha]. Having characterized the
equilibrium plays of college candidates for any admissions rule, we may
explicitly find out the college's choice that maximizes the
expected test score of the admitted student, which is given by
(7) Q = E[Pr([e.sub.n] > [alpha][e.sub.M])[e.sub.N] +
Pr([alpha][e.sub.M] > [e.sub.N])[e.sub.M]] =
E[[F.sub.M]([e.sub.N]/[alpha])[e.sub.N]] +
E[[F.sub.N]([alpha][e.sub.M])[e.sub.M]].
By Proposition 1, when [alpha] [member of] (0, [theta]], we have
(8)[MATHEMATICAL EXPRESSION NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII]
When [alpha] [member of] [[theta], [infinity]), we have
(9) [MATHEMATICAL EXPRESSION NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII]
In summary,
(10) [MATHEMATICAL EXPRESSION NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII]
By my assumption, it is in the college's sole discretion to
choose any [alpha] [member of] (0, [infinity]) that best fits its
objective. As discussed before, affirmative action takes place if the
chosen policy parameter [alpha] exceeds 1. We show in the appendix that
Q, the expected test score of the admitted student, is continuous on
[alpha] and strictly increases with a when [alpha] [member of] (0,
[theta]], while strictly decreases when [alpha] [member of] [[theta],
[infinity]). Hence, the following obtains.
THEOREM 1. In the unique equilibrium of the game, an academic
quality-oriented college adopts an (affirmative action) admissions rule
with [[alpha].sup.*] = [theta] > 1, which (uniquely) maximizes the
expected test score of the admitted student.
By Theorem 1, affirmative action endogenously arises as the unique
outcome of the game. Theorem 1 establishes that the equilibrium
admissions rule that best addresses the interest of the college turns
out to take the form of affirmative action, although we do not
explicitly assume that the college concerns the ethnic diversity of its
student body. It follows that the academic quality of the college tends
to be compromised if affirmative action is banned in admissions practice
and the college adopts a color-blind admissions rule ([alpha] = 1).
The Incentive Effects of Affirmative Action
We show that the unique equilibrium admissions rule, which is
designed to foster academic quality, turns out to favor the (weaker)
minority candidate and allows the admissions not to be awarded to the
better-scoring candidate. To provide more intuition for the seemingly
counterintuitive results, we consider how candidates' effort (test
score) strategies respond to the change in the admissions rule. We
define [[??].sub.M] and [[??].sub.N] to be the expected academic efforts
expended by candidate M and N, respectively. By Proposition 1, when
[alpha] [member of] (0, [theta]], we have
(11) [MATHEMATICAL EXPRESSION NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII]
and
(12) [MATHEMATICAL EXPRESSION NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII].
When [alpha] [member of] [[theta], [infinity]), we have
(13) [MATHEMATICAL EXPRESSION NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII]
and
(14) [MATHEMATICAL EXPRESSION NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII].
PROPOSITION 2. The equilibrium (affirmative action) admissions
rule--that is, [[alpha].sup.*] = [theta]-uniquely maximizes both
candidates' expected academic efforts.
We illustrate by Figure 1 how candidates' academic efforts
respond to varying [alpha]. Both [[??].sub.M] and [[??].sub.N] are
strictly increasing functions of [alpha] when [alpha] [member of] (0,
[theta]] but strictly decreasing functions of [alpha] when [alpha]
[member of] [[theta], [infinity]). Increasing [alpha] encourages both
candidates to expend more effort until it reaches [theta]. By contrast,
once at exceeds [theta], a greater [alpha] makes both candidates reduce
their efforts. Proposition 2 therefore obtains.
[FIGURE 1 OMITTED]
My result brings forth a different flavor than that of models based
on statistical discrimination theory, such as those proposed by Moro and
Norman (2003) and Furstenburg (2003). Moro and Norman argue that with
affirmative action in place, the initially discriminated group has a
stronger incentive to invest for skills, whereas the initially dominant
group has a weaker incentive. Furstenburg finds a similar effect in
regard to how affirmative action influences the cross-group human
capital distribution. In contrast to the negative cross-group
externality, my model unveils a different aspect of the cross-group
interaction resulting from affirmative action. We find that college
candidates' incentives to exert academic effort may positively
interact with each other.
Consider the case [alpha] [member of] (0, [theta]], where both
[[??].sub.M] and [[??].sub.N] increase with at. This result reflects two
effects. One is a direct effect. Intuitively, a greater [alpha]
increases the marginal return of the minority candidate's academic
effort and therefore encourages one to expend more effort. The other is
an indirect effect. As the minority candidate expends more effort, the
nonminority candidate is forced to increase effort in response to a more
aggressive competitor. As a consequence, an increase in [alpha] within
this range improves both candidates' incentives.
By contrast, once [alpha] exceeds the critical value [theta], this
cross-group interaction reverses the effects of affirmative action on
candidates' incentives. In this instance, the predominant
preference awarded to the minority dampens the nonminority
candidate's incentive. The minority candidate is therefore allowed
to reduce effort in the face of a less-competitive rival.
This particular type of strategic interaction gives rise to my
findings. The academic quality of the incoming class (the expected test
score of the admitted candidate) is maximized if and only if the
admissions rule perfectly offsets the initial advantage of the
nonminority candidate; that is, [[alpha].sup.*] = [theta] (=
[V.sub.N]/[V.sub.M]). The fully leveled playing field escalates the
competition between the two candidates and invites both of them to exert
more academic efforts. This overall gain in academic efforts makes the
expected score of the winner rise, even though the better-scoring
candidate may not necessarily be accepted.
IV. DISCUSSION
Given the equilibrium specified here, it is now possible to explore
the ramifications of affirmative action in regard to other important
issues. We first examine how the equilibrium (affirmative action)
admissions rule affects the minority representation in the college. We
then apply my results to investigate whether affirmative action widens
or narrows the long-existing racial test-score gap.
Minority Representation and Diversity
My main result, Theorem 1, rationalizes the widespread practice of
race-conscious preferential admissions in selective colleges. However,
one major argument of those who advocate affirmative action is that it
enhances the minority representation in higher education. My model
provides insights in this regard. We consider the minority
representation in terms of the expected winning probability of the
minority candidate, denoted by [P.sub.M]. We denote by [P.sub.N] the
expected winning probability of the nonminority candidate. We illustrate
candidates' likelihoods of winning as functions of the admissions
policy parameter [alpha].
Figure 2 shows that [P.sub.M] strictly increases with [alpha],
whereas [P.sub.N] strictly decreases with [alpha]. Minority
representation does increase under the equilibrium (affirmative action)
admissions rule, as compared to the case where affirmative action is
banned and only color-blind admissions ([alpha] = 1) take place. This
result is not surprising, given that a huge bulk of empirical evidence
has revealed that affirmative action has significantly enhanced the
minority enrollment in colleges. Yet it is interesting to note that the
downward-sloped curve of [P.sub.N] and the upward-sloped curve of
[P.sub.M] intersect in the unique equilibrium of the game with
[[alpha].sup.*] = [theta].
[FIGURE 2 OMITTED]
THEOREM 2. "Equal chance": The equilibrium admissions
rule--that is, [[alpha].sup.*] = [theta]--uniquely equalizes the
expected probabilities of winning between the minority and nonminority
candidates; that is, [P.sub.M]([theta]) = [P.sub.N]([theta]) = 1/2.
Theorem 2 states that the admissions rule designed to improve the
academic quality of a college naturally results in "equal
chance" between the minority and nonminority college candidates.
The college's demand for academic quality is not in conflict with
the interest in a diversified student body ("equal
representation") but rather coincides with it. Hence, my results
reconcile the seeming tension between academic quality and diversity
(equity).
Racial Test Score Gap
This framework allows us to examine how affirmative action
admissions affect the racial test-score gap. My results show that
affirmative action creates stronger incentive for both candidates to
acquire educational benefit. However, what remains is whether the
preferential admissions rule helps the minority candidate catch up with
the nonminority in education attainment. The racial test-score gap has
long been existing. A number of empirical studies, such as that by Neal
and Johnson (1996), have found that racial gaps in test score or skills
may account for a significant portion of the racial wage differential.
Understanding racial test-score gap may substantially contribute to
social policymaking that attempts to reduce racial inequality. In fact,
should the racial test-score gap be closed, the race-conscious
preferential admissions would no longer be a compelling means to enhance
the minority representation in higher education. Nevertheless, do
affirmative action admissions narrow the gap or widen it?
We consider the test score gap as the expected test score
differential between the nonminority candidate and the minority
candidate. We set the case of no affirmative action as the natural
benchmark. In the benchmark case, the college does not have the freedom
to practice preferential admissions and simply adopts a color-blind
admissions rule with [alpha] = 1. Define K([alpha]) = [[??].sub.N] -
[[??].sub.M] as the expected test score gap between the nonminority
candidate and the minority candidate. By equations 11 and 12, the
equilibrium test-score gap [K.sup.*] K([theta]) is given by
(15) [K.sup.*] = [theta][V.sub.M]/2 - [theta][V.sup.2.sub.M]
/2[V.sub.N] = ([V.sub.N] - [V.sub.M])/2.
The test score gap in the benchmark case is given by
(16) K(1) = ([V.sub.M]/[V.sub.N]) x [([V.sub.N] - [V.sub.M])/2].
PROPOSITION 3. Racial test-score gap widens under the equilibrium
(affirmative action) admissions rule as compared to the case of
color-blind admissions ([alpha] = 1).
[K.sup.*] is greater than K(1) because [V.sub.M] < [V.sub.N]. We
show that affirmative action admissions rule ([[alpha].sup.*] = [theta]
> 1) results in a greater test score differential. Affirmative action
improves both candidates' incentive to acquire more education, yet
the nonminority candidate N responds more aggressively, even though the
minority candidate is the targeted beneficiary of this policy practice.
In short, my results imply that the preferential admissions rule alone
does not close racial test-score gap but widens it. This finding is
testable and has been evidenced by empirical observations: "Since
1988, the racial gap in college admissions tests has actually become
wider, and there is no compelling evidence that any improvement is in
the offing"; see Austen-Smith and Fryer (forthcoming).
V. CONCLUDING REMARK
This study sets forth a stylized theoretical framework for
examining the incentive effects of affirmative action in college
admissions. Although diversity is the most commonly stated rationale by
policymakers who support affirmative action, we have shown that an
affirmative action admissions rule may endogenously arise in equilibrium
even when colleges are solely interested in fostering academic quality.
We find that the equilibrium rule designed to maximize the academic
quality of the college achieves equal representation and improves the
incentives of both minorities and nonminorities to invest in academic
effort (human capital). The results reconcile the perceived tension
between academic quality and diversity and rationalize the prevalent and
persistent practice of affirmative-action admissions procedure in
selective institutions.
My finding confirms the conventional wisdom that placing a handicap
on the stronger contestant escalates the competition and boosts
performance. This reveals an important feature of the incentive
structure behind preferential admissions procedures. The positive
strategic interaction between two candidates enables the affirmative
action practice to induce both of them to increase their efforts, as
well as level the playing field.
The main result has strong policy implications. It is essential for
a policymaker to understand the incentive structure underlying an
affirmative-action policy proposal. Even though preferential admissions
can be a powerful incentive mechanism that enhances the value of a
college, it does not narrow but widen the racial test-score gap. We
predict that affirmative action alone will not help reduce racial
inequality in education attainment. The policy maker needs additional
policy tools for achieving this objective. One such alternative might be
programs designed to reduce the marginal cost of academic effort by
minorities--such as scholarships, special classes, and additional
funding toward public schools in minority communities. The model
suggests that such practices may maximize the quality of the college and
achieve equal representation while eliminating the test score gap.
This study leaves tremendous room for future extensions. First of
all, the emphasis is the partial equilibrium incentive effect of
affirmative action at the college admissions level and does not consider
general equilibrium effects in the labor market. It would be interesting
to extend the model in this manner to examine how affirmative action at
the college admissions level affects future productivity and social
welfare. Second, my approach involves a single college and mainly
applies to selective institutions. Another interesting extension would
be to allow multiple colleges of different tiers to compete for a fixed
pool of students and to examine how the structure of the education
market contributes to the formation of colleges' admissions rules.
APPENDIX
PROOF OF THEOREM 1
Proof When [alpha] [member of] (0,[theta]],
(17) [MATHEMATICAL EXPRESSION NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII].
Because [alpha] < [theta], (17) [greater than or equal to]
([V.sub.M/6[V.sub.N]) x (3[V.sub.N] + 2[V.sub.M] - 2[V.sub.N] =
([V.sub.M/6[V.sub.N] x ([V.sub.N] + 2[V.sub.M]) > 0.
When [alpha] [member of [[theta], [infinity]),
(18) [MATHEMATICAL EXPRESSION NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII].
Because [alpha] [greater than or equal to] [theta], (18) [less than
or equal to] ([V.sub.N]/[[alpha].sup.2][V.sub.M]) x ([V.sub.M]/3 -
[V.sub.N]/3 - [V.sub.M]/2) < 0.
So far we show that Q monotonically increases with a when [alpha]
[member of] (0, [theta]] and decreases with [alpha] when [alpha] [member
of] [[theta], [infinity]). In addition, because [lim.sub.[alpha][up
arrow][theta]]Q = [lim.sub.[alpha][up arrow][theta]]Q = ([V.sub.N] +
[V.sub.M])/3, we conclude that Q is continuous on [alpha]. It follows
that Q is uniquely maximized by [[alpha].sup.*] = [theta].
PROOF OF PROPOSITION 2
Proof [lim.sub.[alpha][up arrow]][[??].sub.M] =
[lim.sub.[alpha][down arrow][theta]][[??].sub.M] = [V.sub.M]/2;
[lim.sub.[alpha][up arrow][theta]][[??].sub.N] = [lim.sub.[alpha][down
arrow]][[??].sub.N] = [V.sub.N]/2. So [[??].sub.M] and [[??].sub.N] are
both continuous.
By equations 11 to 14, [[??].sub.M] and [[??].sub.N] increase with
et when [alpha] [member of] (0, [theta]] and decrease when
[alpha][member of] [[theta], [infinity]).
PROOF OF THEOREM 2
Proof When [alpha] [member of] (0, [theta]], we have
(19) [MATHEMATICAL EXPRESSION NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII].
Hence, [P.sub.N] = E[Pr([e.sub.N] > [alpha][e.sub.M])] = 1 -
E[Pr([alpha][e.sub.M] > [e.sub.N)] = (2[V.sub.N] -
[alpha][V.sub.M])/2[V.sub.N].
When [alpha] [member of] [[theta], [infinity], we have
(20) [MATHEMATICAL EXPRESSION NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII].
Hence, [P.sub.N] = E[Pr([e.sub.N] > [alpha][e.sub.M])] = 1 -
E[Pr([alpha][e.sub.M] > [e.sub.N])] = [V.sub.N]/2[alpha][V.sub.M].
First, we show [lim.sub.[alpha][up arrow][theta]][P.sub.M]([alpha])
= [lim.sub.[alpha][down arrow][theta]([alpha]) = [P.sub.M]([alpha]) =
1/2 = [P.sub.N]([alpha] = 1 - [P.sub.M]([alpha]). Hence, [P.sub.M], as
well as [P.sub.N], is continuous on [alpha]. By equations 19 and 20,
[P.sub.M] strictly increases with [alpha], whereas [P.sub.N] strictly
decreases with [alpha], which implies [P.sub.M] [??] [P.sub.N] iff
[alpha] [??] [theta]. Hence, [[alpha].sup.*] = 0 uniquely equalizes
[P.sub.M] and [P.sub.N].
REFERENCES
Amegashie, J. A., and X. Wu. "Self-Selection in Competing
All-Pay Auctions." Working paper, University of Guelph, 2004.
Austen-Smith, D., and R. J. Fryer. "The Economics of Acting
White." Quarterly Journal of Economics, forthcoming.
Baye M. R., D. Kovenock, and C. G. de Vries. "The All-Pay
Auction with Complete Information." Economic Theory, 8, 1996,
291-305.
Coate, S., and G. C. Loury. "Antidiscrimination Enforcement
and the Problem of Patronization." American Economic Review, 83,
1993, 92-98.
Fernandez, R., and J. Gali. "To Each According to ... ?
Markets, Tournaments, and the Matching Problem with Borrowing
Constraints." Review of Economic Studies, 66, 1999, 799-824.
Fryer, R. G., and G. C. Loury. "Affirmative Action in
Winner-Take-All Markets." Journal of Economic Inequality,
forthcoming.
Furstenberg, E. "Affirmative Action, Incentives, and the
Black-White Test Score Gap." Working paper, College of William and
Mary, 2003.
Hillman, A. L., and J. G. Riley. "Politically Contestable
Rents and Transfers." Economics and Politics, 1, 1989, 17-39.
Holzer, H. J., and D. Neumark. "Assessing Affirmative
Action." Journal of Economic Literature, 38, 2000, 483-568.
Moro, A., and P. Norman. "Affirmative Action in a Competitive
Economy." Journal of Public Economics, 87, 2003, 567-94.
Neal, D. A., and W. R. Johnson. "The Role of Premarket Factors
in Black-White Wage Differences." Journal of Political Economy,
104, 1996, 869-95.
Phelps, E. "The Statistical Theory of Racism and Sexism."
American Economic Review, 62, 1972, 659-61.
Schotter, A., and K. Weigelt. "Asymmetric Tournaments, Equal
Opportunity Laws and Affirmative Action: Some Experimental
Results." Quarterly Journal of Economics, 107, 1992, 511-39.
Steele, S. The Content of Our Character. NY: St. Martin's Press, 1990.
Thomas, C. Opinion in Grutter v. Bollinger, 2003, 30.
(1.) It seems unnatural to have college candidates randomize their
academic efforts. My results, however, can be interpreted in light of
the remarkable Harsanyi purification theorem. According to the theorem,
the original game with perfectly known payoffs can be viewed as a limit
of a sequence of games with payoff perturbation. If the random
perturbation is revealed only to the player, then, for almost every
realization of the payoff, the incomplete-information game yields a
unique pure-strategy equilibrium that approximates the mixed-strategy
equilibrium of the original game. In other words, the original mixed
equilibrium can be considered as a limit of the pure-strategy
equilibrium of any "close-by" perturbed game. Thus, we may
understand my model without "forcing" college candidates to
randomize. The seeming randomization of efforts in the equilibrium can
result from the perturbed payoffs among candidates. Although one player
takes pure action, the other player may still view his or her action as
being drawn from a distribution because of the uncertainty associated
with his or her "type" (payoff) (Reny et al., 2002).
QIANG FU, I am grateful to Michael Baye and Gerhard Glomm for their
advice. I have also benefited from useful comments from Rick Harbaugh,
Tilman Klumpp, John Maxwell, Peter Norman, Massimo Morelli, James
Walker, George Furstenburg, Robert Becker, Rajiv Sethi, Eric Eyster,
Johannes Muenster, and all participants at Public Economic Theory 2004
Peking Conference and Indiana University Economic Seminar. I owe special
thanks to an anonymous referee and the editor Dennis Jansen for detailed
comments and suggestions on an earlier version of this article.
Fu: Assistant Professor, Department of Business Policy, National
University of Singapore, Singapore 119752. Phone 65-6516-3775, Fax
65-6779-5059, E-mail bizfq@ nus.edu.sg