Buying a dream: alternative models of demand for lotto.
Forrest, David ; Simmons, Robert ; Chesters, Neil 等
I. INTRODUCTION
Lotteries are pervasive phenomena worldwide. Lotto, the most
popular and widespread state lottery game, is a very simple numbers game
where individuals select a set of numbers in a given range and win
prizes according to how many numbers are guessed correctly. Wessberg
(1999) finds that, in the 1990s, world lottery sales grew by 9% on
average and some values of the highest prize (the jackpot) exceeded US
$20 million in Italy, Spain, and the United Kingdom with comparable
levels for state lotteries in the United States. Participation rates in
lotteries are high, in excess of 50% of the adult population in the
United Kingdom, according to King (1997), and span the whole
distribution of incomes. Over time, an increasing number of state and
national governments have opted to use lotto as an important source of
revenue.
Several economists have attempted to model lotto demand. Clearly,
different demand specifications have the potential to offer different
policy implications, for example for the level of taxation and take-out
to be imposed on consumers. The most popular empirical approach to lotto
demand takes the nominal price of a ticket as a unit value and then
examines variations in the "effective price" of a lottery
ticket, defined as one minus the expected value of prize payments per
ticket. Cook and Clotfelter (1993), Gulley and Scott (1993), Scott and
Gulley (1995), Walker (1998), Farrell et al. (1999), Purfield and
Waldron (1999) and Forrest et al. (2000b) all follow this approach. (1)
If the first (jackpot) prize is not claimed in a particular draw, then
the jackpot pool rolls over into the next draw. Such rollovers provide
the greatest source of variation in effective price. Variables
representing information on occurrence and size of rollovers can be used
as instruments to determine effective price in a two-stage approach to
modeling lotto sales.
This procedure for modeling time-series lotto demand is remarkably
successful. Lotto appears to exhibit a standard downward-sloping demand
curve in effective price-sales space and the derived effective price
elasticities of lotto sales vary plausibly around minus one. The fit of
the estimated equation is typically high. Sales, price, and rollover are
typically found to be stationary from unit root tests and particular
features such as time trend, structural breaks, and special events
surrounding particular lotto draws can be accounted for. Forrest et al.
(2000a) offer evidence that lotto players act rationally, making use of
the best information available given that they choose to wager in the
first place. (2) Farrell et al. (2000) show that their lotto demand
model, which follows the orthodox approach, appears to be robust to the
problem of "conscious selection," where players do not
necessarily select their numbers randomly but overselect particular
groups of numbers (memorable dates, birthdays, superstiti on, etc.).
In this article, we reestimate demand for U.K. National Lottery
(UKNL) tickets, bringing up to date the earlier work of Forrest et al.
(2000b), which only considered the first three years of play in the
United Kingdom. Although the traditional model still appears to perform
well, it is pertinent to question the underlying theory. The
"effective price" approach is grounded in expected utility
theory and runs foul of the classic problem facing analysis of any
wagering market: why do gamblers accept a manifestly unfair bet and yet
in many or most cases simultaneously reveal aversion to risk by
purchasing insurance? Why would risk-averse individuals buy lottery
tickets? We suggest that existing models of lotto demand are seriously
flawed in their treatment of this problem.
Rather than simply claim that our empirical evidence using the
traditional model is consistent with the theory of downward-sloping
demand for lotto, which it is at a simple level, we test this model
against a rival, using the UKNL as our particular case. Our rival model
of lotto demand does not rely on effective price as a driving force for
lotto demand. Instead, we take a more direct approach where the
motivation for purchase of lottery tickets is fun or pleasure from
gambling activity. Essentially, following a suggestion by Thaler and
Ziemba (1988), we hypothesize a consumption benefit to gambling and
lotto play in particular. Any consumption benefit from the act of
picking numbers, which in many lotteries can be chosen for the player by
a random number generator, seems likely to be limited as the game does
not require any skill. Nor is there likely to be a substantial
consumption benefit to be found in the process of the lottery draw
itself, although this is often displayed on national TV Any pleasure or
thrill from the tension in the period between actual play and draw is
likely to be dissipated by the long odds against winning the jackpot and
by the impersonal nature of the draw itself. Rather, we hypothesize that
the consumption benefit may be found in the prospect of "buying a
dream." This includes aspects such as imagining how one might spend
the lotto jackpot and how one might enjoy the pleasure of the act of
quitting one's job.
Consideration of a consumption benefit from gambling, then, leads
directly to the idea that demand for lotto is affected by size of
jackpot rather than by effective price. A higher jackpot represents more
fun, a better dream, and induces more lotto sales. This behavioral
effect of jackpot size on lotto demand has not been analyzed empirically
before. We show that this model performs well on its own terms and is
not dominated by the effective price model in a statistical sense, using
nonnested hypothesis testing on UKNL data. The support offered for
recognizing a role for the consumption benefit from gambling in the
specification of a model of lotto demand suggests that future work could
usefully apply this concept to the study of consumer demand for other
betting products.
The rest of the article proceeds as follows. Section II contrasts
the theoretical properties of the effective price and jackpot models,
focusing in particular on their ability to reconcile simultaneous
gambling and insurance behavior and establishes the models to be
estimated and describes the data to be used. Section III displays
results from the effective price model. Section IV presents the results
of, first, estimating the alternative jackpot model and then performing
nonnested hypothesis testing of the two models. Section V concludes.
II. ALTERNATIVE MODELS OF LOTTO DEMAND
For a given lotto draw, the effective price of a unit-value ticket
is one minus the expected value of prize receipts and is given by
(1) P = 1 - { (1/Q)[(A + [rho]Q) x (1 - exp(-[rho]Q)) + [summation over (j)] [[pi].sub.j]Q]},
where Q the level of sales, A is any amount added to the grand
prize pool by rollover or "superdraw" (when the organizers, as
in the U.K. case, guarantee to top-up the pool to a preannounced minimum
level), [rho] is the probability of winning a share in the jackpot prize
(approximately 1 in 14 million for the U.K.); and [[pi].sub.j]
represents the proportion of sales revenue paid into each of the lesser
prize pools. This effective price is the mathematically expected price a
buyer could calculate prior to the draw if he or she could predict Q
successfully and if all bettors choose numbers randomly.
In fact, the effective price is not known ex ante. Bettors must
form an expectation of what effective price will be. For example, it
will rationally be expected to be lower than usual if prize money has
been rolled over from a previous draw and will always vary with the
level of sales (the higher the number of tickets sold, the less the
chance of prize money being withheld because no one has won the grand
prize). The standard model is estimated by a two-stage process in which
stage 1 generates an expected effective price series to be included as a
regressor in the stage 2 demand (sales) equation. The coefficient on
expected effective price may then be used to estimate demand elasticity.
Probably the most fundamental problem associated with the effective
price model is that it represents buyer behavior as varying with the
(expected) amount of stake money returned to bettors in prize money with
no account taken of possible consumer preferences with regard to the
structure of prizes. The omission is serious. The claim of users of the
effective price model is that it can illuminate the question of whether
overall take-out may appropriately be altered. This question is
considered by Gulley and Scott (1993), Walker (1998), Farrell et al.
(1999), and Forrest et al. (2000b). Any recommendations are based
primarily on observing the past responses of bettors to improvements in
payout that were achieved almost entirely by augmentation (through
rollover or super-draw) of the pool for the jackpot prize. It cannot be
ruled out that the observed buyer response in fact depended on the
"price" variation coming via adjustment of the prospective
grand prize. It cannot safely be assumed that a given reduction in
steady-state takeout would yield the same consumer response if it were
implemented by raising all prizes rather than just the jackpot prize.
Skepticism concerning the effective price model is supported by a
unique episode in the history of the UKNL, in the draw for Saturday, 19
September 1998. On this occasion, Camelot declared a superdraw but added
the extra prize money from its own funds to the second-tier prize pool
rather than to the jackpot pool. In contrast to all other superdraw
"price" reductions (when the additional prize money had
augmented the jackpot pool), sales fell by 7.1% from the level of the
previous (Saturday) draw, notwithstanding a reduction in the effective
price from [pounds sterling]0.55 to [pounds sterling]0.28. This raises
the suspicion that the observed demand response to such price reductions
on other occasions was not to price per se but to the amount available
from the jackpot.
It is difficult to propose a consumer utility function that could
offer convincing underpinning of the effective price model. If buyers
treated lotto tickets as financial assets, they would be indifferent to
prize structure only if they were risk-neutral; but if they were
risk-neutral (or risk-averse) they would not take on patently unfair
lotto bets. This problem of why risk-neutral (or risk-averse) people
gamble and simultaneously take out insurance is endemic to the economic
analysis of all wagering markets, as shown by Sauer (1998). The classic
response, following Friedman and Savage (1948), is to propose a utility
function with concave segments at low and very high levels of wealth and
a convex segment at an intermediate range of wealth levels. The idea is
that individuals with low wealth will buy low probability/high payoff
prospects, such as lottery tickets, that potentially propel them into
much higher wealth levels where the convex shape applies, reflecting
risk-loving behavior. A variation of this model is to apply the convex
segment to current wealth and
propose gambling behavior as local risk preference. Hence, gamblers
are seen as locally risk-loving. One interpretation is that everyone
wants to be in a higher class of wealth and everyone has the same shape
of utility function, which is constructed around a point of inflection associated with the individual's current level of wealth. On this
argument, lotto play is seen as facilitating a transition to a much
higher level of wealth, which significantly alters an individual's
lifestyle.
But the Friedman-Savage explanation of gambling is not sufficiently
general. The argument needs to account for not only small stake/high
payout lotto games but also small stake/small payout forms of betting,
such as wagers in horse racing. The latter cannot be explained by
increasing marginal utility of wealth as, regardless of the shape of the
underlying function, utility will be approximately linear over the very
small range of wealth covered by the two possible outcomes of losing or
winning the bet.
A variation on the Friedman-Savage expected utility function has
been proposed recently by Garrett and Sobel (1999). This work was
inspired by the notion of Golec and Tamarkin (1998) that "bettors
favour skewness, not risk, at the horse track." Garrett and Sobel
appeal to the Friedman-Savage cubic expected utility function to justify
measures of skewness and variance, alongside mean, in a cross-section
model of sales across 216 online lottery games offered in the United
States by states or consortia of states in various periods. Application
of this approach to pari-mutuel lottery products is flawed due to the
presence of a series of mass points in the distribution of returns. The
true probability distribution of returns to a lotto ticket has a large
mass point at zero. In the case of the UKNL, there will be a further
mass point at [pounds sterling]10, the value of the fixed-odds element
in prize money (paid when three out of six numbers drawn are matched by
the bettor's entry). Beyond [pounds sterling]10, an y level of
return is in principle possible, depending on how many ticket-holders
meet the requirements for a share in the four large prize pools; there
will be local maxima at the mean prize levels corresponding to each of
these prize pools. In the context of such a complex distribution, it is
hard to envision what variations in a standard skewness measure would
signify.
It is possible to simplify the exercise as Garrett and Sobel do.
One can represent points on a probability distribution that show the
mean payouts for each prize pool with the corresponding probability of
holding a winning ticket in that prize pool. But this is a
hypergeometric distribution for which a measure of skewness, strictly
defined, does not exist, as Spanos (1993) shows. In any case, any
formulistic measure of skewness that may be calculated would be
incapable of distinguishing differential bettor responses to variation
in the expected value of different prize pools.
A model that moves us closer to consideration of the pleasures of
gambling is Conlisk (1993), who adds a "tiny utility of
gambling" to a conventional expected utility framework. Suppose
there are fair gambles in which G is won with probability p and L is
lost with probability 1 - p. In a fair gamble, pG = (1-p)L. Let U(W)
denote a utility of wealth function, with standard restrictions as for a
risk-averse individual. The preference function is
(2) E(G, p, W) = pU(W + G)+(1 - p) x U[W - pG/(1 - p)] +
[epsilon]V(G, p).
This is an augmented expected utility function where the additional
utility of gambling is given by [epsilon]V(G, p) and [epsilon] is a
nonnegative scale parameter. Given suitable restrictions on the taste
function, V(.), and for sufficiently small [epsilon], Conlisk (1993)
shows that there is a limit to the size of an acceptable gambling
prospect, so that small gambles are preferred to large ones and there is
a uniquely preferred size of gamble. Moreover, both the limit to
gambling and optimal size of gamble increase with wealth.
The Conlisk model does not represent a radical departure from the
conventional expected utility framework because it continues to view the
effective price or take-out as the price of that fun as proposed for
lotto for example by Walker (1998). Unfortunately, assuming demand for
lotto to be demand for a consumption good does not of itself legitimize the assumption that prize structure is unimportant for bettor behavior.
The utility function that has to be assumed for this to be true must not
have the amount of fun varying with the structure of prizes
corresponding to a given expected value of prize money. This, however,
is highly implausible because it suggests that the fun of a lotto ticket
is associated only with such pleasures as the selection of numbers, the
viewing of the draw on television, the checking of entries, and the
contemplation of "good causes" funded from the revenue from
the game.
A more direct view of why people buy lotto tickets is that they are
buying hope, as suggested by Clotfelter and Cook (1989), or buying a
dream. The chances of winning a large prize are known and understood to
be very remote. Walker (1998, 30) reports evidence from a U.K. Consumer
Association survey of over 2000 individuals that, on average,
respondents assessed correctly the probability of winning the jackpot
prize. Perhaps bettors do not really expect to win at all but enjoy the
dream (unavailable to nonpurchasers) of spending whatever is the largest
amount that could be won from holding the ticket. This raises the
possibility that variation in sales is driven primarily not by the
effective price, nor even by the jackpot component in expected value,
but rather by the prospective size of the jackpot pool, which defines
the largest amount that anyone could win (but which they would win only
if there were no other jackpot winners). (3) In the UKNL, players are
assisted by forecasts made by the operator on the l ikely size of the
jackpot pool; these are issued the day before the draw and, on casual
impression, seem to be reasonably accurate. We conjecture that sales are
dependent on the anticipated size of the jackpot pool and propose to
test the extent to which this hypothesis is able to explain past
variations in the sales of the UKNL more successfully than the hitherto
dominant effective price model.
III. ESTIMATION OF THE EFFECTIVE PRICE MODEL
The UKNL was launched in November 1994 with the Camelot Group as
operator under a seven-year franchise arrangement (since renewed); this
contrasts with the typical American state lottery, where the lottery is
operated by the state authority. Camelot's principal product is a
standard 6/49 lotto game initially played on Saturdays. The grand prize
is shared among ticket holders matching the six numbers drawn, and there
are lesser prize pools to be shared among those matching four or five
numbers or five plus an extra bonus number drawn as part of the game.
Fixed small prizes ([pounds sterling]10) are paid to bettors who have
chosen three out of the six main numbers. The grand prize is rolled over
into the jackpot pool at the next draw in the event of there being no
ticket-holders with six correct numbers. (4) Camelot introduced a second
weekly draw, on Wednesdays, in February 1997. Camelot also introduced a
third online game, Thunderball, in June 1999. Our sample period lies
between these two events, comprising 254 observations in total split
equally across the Wednesday and Saturday games. This allows us to model
lotto sales free of regime changes and avoids time-series modeling
complications from changes in the frequency of draws. We estimate demand
equations and price elasticities separately for Wednesday and Saturday
draws to illuminate the hitherto unconsidered question of whether the
similarity of regular-draw takeout between the two games is justified
within the context of a public policy goal of maximizing sales revenue
net of prizes. Summary statistics of data on effective price and sales
are provided in Table 1.
Our model, to be estimated by two-stage least squares (2SLS), may
be represented as follows, with labels in lowercase denoting natural
logarithms.
Wednesday Game
Stage 1: P
= f(constant, [q.sup.w.sub.t-1]. [Q.sub.s], TREND, [TREND.sup.2],
SUPERDRAW, ROLLOVER)
Stage 2: q
= g(constant, [q.sup.w.sub.t-1], [Q.sub.s], TREND, [TREND.sub.2],
SUPERDRAW, PRICE)
Saturday Game
Stage 1: P
= f(constant, [q.sup.w.sub.t-1], [Q.sub.w], TREND, [TREND.sub.2],
SUPERDRAW, DIANA, ROLLOVER)
Stage 2: q
= g(constant, [q.sup.w.sub.t-1], [Q.sub.w], TREND, [TREND.sup.2],
SUPERDRAW, DIANA, PRICE)
P is effective price calculated as above; q is the natural log of
the number (and pound value) of the tickets sold; [q.sup.w.sub.t-1] and
[q.sup.s.sub.t-1] are lagged dependent variables included to capture
persistence in sales; 5 and [Q.sub.s] or [Q.sub.w], as appropriate,
represents the level of sales in the immediately preceding draw (i.e.,
on the preceding Saturday if we are modeling demand for the Wednesday
game or on the preceding Wednesday if we are seeking to explain
variation in Saturday sales). [Q.sub.s] and [Q.sub.w] influence the
volume of sales in the next game because purchase, for example, on a
Wednesday, offers the opportunity to buy a ticket for the Saturday draw
at the same time, reducing the transactions cost of participation for
Saturday and insuring the bettor against forgetting or being unable to
visit a retail outlet later in the week. ROLLOVER represents the
principal source of variation in price and is the (pound) amount carried
over (not won) from the immediately preceding draw and a dded to the
jackpot pool in the current draw. It will lower effective price because
it represents prize money to which bettors in the current draw do not
contribute though the extent of this benefit to the purchaser of a
single ticket will be diluted as sales increase and spread the value of
this bonus money across more bettors (and potential winners of the
jackpot).
PRICE is the focus of interest in our demand equation, and the
estimated coefficient on this is used to calculate an elasticity of
demand with respect to take-out. The demand equations also include
variables to represent bettors' changing behavior over time and
their responses to exogenous events. Each demand equation includes a
trend term (TREND) and its square ([TREND.sup.2]). In the Saturday
demand equation TREND is expected to have a negative coefficient
reflecting the tendency of mature lottery games, observed by Miers
(1996) for example, to face increasing loss of interest from boredom or
disillusion with the game. In the Wednesday equation we predict a
positive coefficient on TREND because this was a new game at the
beginning of our data period and the role of this variable is to capture
the learning curve of bettors as they decided whether or not to become
regular players and (if so) remembered to buy a ticket. For consistency,
a quadratic trend is entered into both equations, but given the greater
ma turity of the Saturday game, we do not necessarily expect to find a
significant coefficient on [TREND.sup.2] there. SUPERDRAW is a dummy
variable that takes the value of one for specific draws guaranteed by
Camelot to reach a preannounced figure. DIANA is a dummy variable set
equal to one for the draw scheduled for Saturday, 7 September 1997, but
postponed to the next day because of the funeral of Diana, Princess of
Wales. (6)
Forrest et al. (2000b) captured the lower popularity of the
Wednesday game, suggested by Table 1, by means of a shift dummy. This
approach, followed in American studies by Gulley and Scott (1993) and
Scott and Gulley (1995), does not allow for possible differences in
slope coefficients between the two games. We tested the constraint that
all slope coefficients were equal between Wednesdays and Saturdays.
Using all 254 observations, we estimated an equation by 2SLS that
regressed the log of sales on independent variables (that appear in
either or both equations above), on a dummy variable set equal to one
for Wednesday draws and on a set of multiplicative variables formed by
multiplying each independent variable by the Wednesday dummy. The test
of the validity of the constrained model is then an F-test of the joint
significance of the estimated coefficients on all the multiplicative
variables. The test statistic was 56.55 (critical value, 5% level, 2.01)
and thus the validity of pooling the data in the contex t of the
effective price model was decisively rejected.
Accordingly, we report in Table 2, columns (1) and (2), demand
equations estimated separately for the Wednesday and Saturday games. Our
main interest is in how sensitive sales are to price, but some other
points of interest also stand out. The Saturday game experienced the
trend decrease in sales faced by many lotto games worldwide. The
quadratic trend term in the Saturday equation was insignificant,
indicating that Camelot has failed to arrest the rate of decline in
interest. We report the parsimonious form with [TREND.sup.2] removed. In
the Wednesday equation, the positive coefficient on TREND captures the
growth in sales as the new game was established; (7) but the (negative)
coefficient on [TREND.sup.2] allows one to estimate that interest in
Wednesday draws also began to decline after the 74th drawing, that is,
from June 1998. Thunderball was presumably Camelot's response to
these trends and, on the basis of U.S. experience, the future is likely
to be punctuated by attempts to renew bettor interest with new games and
perhaps joint ventures with other gambling media.
There is no evidence in the results that high sales on a Saturday
promote sales in the following Wednesday draw. By contrast, the positive
and significant coefficient on [Q.sub.w] suggests a carryover from
Wednesdays to Saturdays. This difference between the Wednesday and
Saturday draws is unsurprising. On Saturdays, participation is already
high and any increase in Saturday sales (e.g., when there is a rollover)
is likely to be mainly the result of existing bettors purchasing more
entries. (8) Thus, the change in the number of people visiting a sales
outlet on a rollover Saturday may be small and the stimulus to sales on
the following Wednesday from reduced transactions costs therefore
limited. By contrast, many UKNL customers appear to play on Wednesday
only when effective price is low and, on these occasions, they may
purchase a Saturday ticket at the same time. Saturday sales benefit to
the extent that there is then reduced loss from some customers being
unable to reach a sales outlet to make their usual purchase at the end
of the week.
The coefficient on SUPERDRAW measures any effect on sales over and
above that which works through the price variable. In a superdraw,
Camelot adds extra money to the prize fund, thereby reducing effective
price and boosting sales. The negative and significant coefficients on
SUPERDRAW indicate that sales are not raised as much as usual if any
decrease in effective price is achieved via this particular mechanism.
Given that the greatest price variance is associated with rollovers, the
appropriate interpretation of the coefficients on SUPERDRAW is that
customers are less sensitive to superdraw money than to rollover money.
Our focus of interest is the coefficient on the price term. The
highly significant and negative coefficients indicate that the demand
curve is downward sloping on both Wednesdays and Saturdays. Point
estimates for long-run elasticity on the two days are -1.04 and -0.88,
respectively. (9) Neither estimate is significantly different from -1 at
the 5% level of significance. There remains, though, some suspicion of
inelasticity in Saturday demand where the level of significance that
would allow one to conclude that price was too low to achieve (net)
revenue maximization is close to 6%.
One earlier study found a rather higher value of (absolute) price
elasticity for the UKNL. Farrell et al. (1999) obtained a point estimate
of long-run elasticity of -1.55. This result should be treated with
caution, however. Their study was based on 116 weekly observations from
the first draw on and was therefore influenced strongly by consumer
behavior in the first year of operation. During this time, the UKNL was
perhaps becoming embedded into national consciousness and consumers were
having to cope with adapting to new events, such as the first rollovers.
A particular problem is that the bulk of the variance in effective price
was generated by rollovers and the two double rollovers that occurred at
draws 60 and 63. In the early days of the UKNL, the potentially very
large prizes associated with rollovers, especially double rollovers,
attracted great publicity and made the lotto front page news. These
draws therefore benefited from a free advertising effect that may have
shifted demand; this would impart up ward bias to any estimate of demand
elasticity derived from the data from this period.
In contrast to the implications from Farrell et al. (1999), the
results here indicate that there is no scope for the lottery takeout to
be made more generous to consumers to increase the amount raised for the
good causes funds, into which at least 28% of bettors' stakes have
to be paid. There is the suspicion that the Saturday draw could even be
made a little less generous. From the viewpoint of the operator, there
is no doubt that much less generosity would be optimal. Marginal cost to
Camelot is at least 45p per ticket sold (good causes 28p lottery duty
l2p; retailer commission 5p). With this marginal cost and the current
mean level of sales and take-out, elasticity would have to be near to
-10 rather than -1 for the current price to be profit maximizing. The
restraint on takeout included in the lottery legislation is therefore
plainly binding. In fact, with our estimated demand functions, optimal
take-out for the operator would be in excess of [pounds sterling]6 on
both Wednesdays and Saturdays, implying a face value of a ticket of
about [pounds sterling]7 with current levels of prize payout. This
estimate should not be taken too seriously because it relates to an
effective price level well outside the range of values observed (and
influencing our regression results). Nevertheless, it is illustrative of
why the unusual U.K. franchise arrangement requires statutory regulation
of take-out levels.
Our results imply, then, that British lotto operates under
approximately unit-elastic conditions. However, it is likely that the
model overestimates steady-state demand elasticity. Because there have
been no permanent changes in take-out arrangements (and hence effective
price) since the inception of the UKNL, elasticity estimates are
generated from measuring consumer response to transitory changes in
effective price associated primarily with rollover and special
superdraws. One is therefore observing how consumers respond when the
product is "in a sale" rather than offered at a permanently
lower price. Some of the consumer response is therefore likely to
represent retiming of purchases (intertemporal substitution). Hence,
elasticity with respect to a permanent price change would be expected to
be lower than that found in our results. This implies that demand is
inelastic and that take-out should be increased if the only goal is net
revenue maximization. Analysis of this period contradicts the conclusion
of Farrell et al. (1999, p. 524-25) that the "pricing of the
product is not consistent with the regulator's objective and the
regulator could elicit greater sales if the take-out rate were reduced
and the prize pool increases."
IV. ESTIMATION OF THE JACKPOT MODEL
In the alternative jackpot model, we are interested in the extent
to which the total funds in the jackpot pool can account for past
variations in UKNL sales. Our rival model has the same structure as the
familiar effective price model detailed above. But Stage 1 now models
the determination of a new variable, J, which denotes the expected
jackpot prize pool, rather than P. In Stage 2, PRICE is replaced by a
variable, JACKPOT, which is the fitted value of jackpot, or expected
jackpot prize pool, from the Stage 1 regression.
In estimation, the 2SLS procedure is applied as before and the
supporting variables are unchanged. Table 2, columns (3) and (4),
display our results. All the previous conclusions regarding the
supporting variables remain unaltered apart from one substantive
difference. This concerns evidence of persistence in Saturday play as
well as Wednesday play for the jackpot model. A suggestive feature of
these new results overall is that there is a striking increase in the
value of adjusted [R.sup.2], particularly for the Saturday draw, when
PRICE is replaced by JACKPOT.
The estimates of point elasticity of demand with respect to
expected jackpot are 0.162 and 0.195 for the Wednesday and Saturday
draws, respectively. However, these raw numbers may be misleading
because the level of jackpot varies proportionally with sales in that
14p of each pound of sales revenue is paid into the jackpot pool.
Stripping out this endogenous effect (by approximation) gives a more
accurate indication of the interaction between the jackpot prize and the
demand for tickets. For each additional [pounds sterling]1 million paid
as jackpot, the model predicts additional revenue of [pounds
sterling]53,000 and [pounds sterling]22,000 in the Saturday and
Wednesday games, respectively, while holding the total prize pool
constant.
The standard effective price model and our alternative jackpot pool
model both appear to track bettor behavior reasonably well. We proceed
to test between the models, focusing on the larger Saturday game.
The two models are based on very different views of bettor
behavior. The traditional model has bettors gaining "fun" from
the game and, just as with most consumer goods, they choose to purchase
more fun when the price of that fun is reduced. The alternative model
takes the relevant price as the face value of a ticket (which is fixed)
and then represents sales as responding to any increase in the maximum
lotto prize on offer under the conditions of any particular draw.
Bettors are not concerned over whether a winning entry will receive the
whole of this prize because what they are paying for is a dream of being
able to spend whatever is the largest sum of money that a ticket could
bring them in the particular draw. Though the models are radically
different in their assumptions regarding what motivates bettors, as an
empirical matter any test between them is essentially a test of rival
functional forms (given a functional relationship between PRICE and
JACKPOT).
A test between the models is not straightforward. The hypotheses
are not nested in that one cannot be written as a restricted version of
the other. But it is not possible to estimate an encompassing model
because ROLLOVER serves as an instrument for both PRICE and JACKPOT.
Thus, attempting to nest artificially the two regression models results
in the collapse of the nested system. However, a procedure originally
devised by Cox (1961, 1962) and later developed by Pesaran (1974)
permits a test between nonnested hypotheses without the need for an
encompassing model and is of greater power than tests based on
artificial nesting.
The Cox statistic for testing the hypothesis that the effective
price model comprises the correct set of regressors and that the jackpot
model does not is -17.12 against a critical (5% level) of [+ or -] 1.96.
The effective price model is thus rejected when tested formally against
the jackpot pool model. The Cox statistic for testing the hypothesis
that the jackpot pool model comprises the correct set of regressors and
that the price model does not is 4.19 (5% critical value again [+ or -]
1.96). The jackpot model is likewise formally rejected when tested
against the effective price model.
There are four possible outcomes to a Cox test: rejection of one or
other model, rejection of neither (an inconclusive result) or rejection
of both. We have the last outcome. This signifies that the effective
price model would be added to by a model including the extra variable
representing jackpot pool. Traditional models are therefore
mis-specified and results are likely to suffer as a result of omitted
variable bias. Our proposed model likewise suffers from the absence of
effective price, which is unsurprising since a literal interpretation of
the model would (for example) imply that the [pounds]10 prizes could be
scrapped without an effect on sales so long as the jackpot pool were
maintained. However, it is perhaps suggestive that the rejection of the
effective price model is more decisive than that of the jackpot pool
model, indicating that our approach may capture a dominant driving force
behind why buyers purchase lottery tickets.
V. CONCLUSIONS
The primary focus in lotto demand studies in both the United States
and the United Kingdom has been on whether there was any change in
take-out that could be made that would increase the sums of money raised
for government or government-sponsored good causes. Given the franchise
arrangements in the UKNL, the take-out rate appropriate to the maximand
would imply a demand elasticity with respect to take-out of minus one.
Our study indicates that in neither the weekend nor the midweek lotto
game is this elasticity significantly different from minus one. However,
we identify biases that may imply that our estimates, like those of
previous authors, overstate elasticity. As a result we suspect from the
results of our applications of the traditional model that there is scope
for increasing the take-out rate, at least for the Saturday draw.
The traditional model we employ is, however, based on an
implausible assumption; that sales are related to the total prize pay
outs but not to the structure of prizes. Our alternative model focuses
on the maximum possible prize rather than any mathematically expected
value of prize associated with the purchase of a single ticket. Testing
this against the traditional model indicates decisively that previous
results of demand studies are unreliable in that jackpot considerations
indeed exert an influence over and above those of variations in
take-out. Policy makers would be well advised to attempt to preserve the
level of the jackpot pool if they were to attempt to increase take-out.
The importance of the headline jackpot also lends credibility to
any proposal to increase the difficulty of the game--for example, by
switching from 6/49 to 6/53 play--while preserving total prize money.
This would increase the incidence of rollovers and especially double
rollovers, creating the high headline prize figures, which appear to be
an important motivator of purchase. At the very least, these ideas are
worth exploring in further research covering several lotto games and
jurisdictions. Our alternative jackpot model provides a corrective to
any complacency that might result from findings in traditional North
American and British studies of unit- or near-unit elasticity and to any
implication drawn that lotto design and takeout are already nearly
optimal from the public policy perspective.
TABLE 1
Summary Statistics on Sales and Effective Price
Effective Price Sales
([pounds ([pounds
sterling]) sterling])
Wed Sat Wed Sat
Mean 0.544 0.527 29.057 m 59.258 m
SD 0.061 0.054 3.154 m 5.480 m
Minimum 0.293 0.288 25.035 m 50.221 m
Maximum 0.574 0.554 41.650 m 88.306 m
No. observations 127 127 127 127
TABLE 2
Demand Equations for Log (Sales) Using 2SLS
Variable (1) Wednesday (2) Saturday (3) Wednesday
CONSTANT 14.198 17.890 13.729
(12.96) ** (23.44) ** (16.63) **
[q.sup.w.sub.t-1] 0.213 0.180
(3.20) ** (3.50) **
[q.sup.w.sub.t-1] 4.10E-02
(1.11)
[Q.sup.w] 6.89E-09
(2.82) **
[Q.sup.s] 1.29E-09 1.39E-07
(0.85) (1.06)
TREND 2.89E-03 -1.12E-13 2.66E-03
(5.26) ** (10.57) ** (6.90) **
TREND (2) -2.01.E-05 -1.84E-05
(5.80) ** (7.54) **
SUPERDRAW -8.85E-02 -0.139 -6.14E-02
(5.49) ** (2.17) * (5.49) **
DIANA -0.220
(15.87) **
PRICE -1.507 -1.610
(10.73) ** (9.44) **
JACKPOT 3.22E-08
(14.24) **
Durbin h 1.71 1.68 1.71
[R.sup.2](adj.) 0.83 0.72 0.88
N 127 127 127
Variable (4) Saturday
CONSTANT 16.427
(35.45) **
[q.sup.w.sub.t-1]
[q.sup.w.sub.t-1] 6.89E-02
(2.86) **
[Q.sup.w] 3.39E-09
(3.04) **
[Q.sup.s]
TREND -8.78E-04
(13.40) **
TREND (2)
SUPERDRAW -6.70E-02
(2.75) **
DIANA -0.164
(32.84) **
PRICE
JACKPOT 1.94E-08
(18.79) **
Durbin h 1.68
[R.sup.2](adj.) 0.90
N 127
Note: Absolute values of t = statistics appear in parentheses.
* Denotes significance at 5%.
** Denotes significance at 1%.
(1.) An alternative measure of effective price is the reciprocal of
expected value, as used by Mason et at. (1997) in their study of lotto
demand in Florida.
(2.) Forrest et al. (2000a) analyze 188 U.K. National Lottery draws
and find that agents make full use of available information and, on
average, correctly forecast the level of sales. The expected price
series used in the second stage therefore carries some credibility as
the measure agents consider as part of their purchase decision. Similar
findings were obtained for U.S. state lotteries in Kentucky,
Massachusetts, and Ohio by Scott and Gulley (1995).
(3.) Variance in the size of the jackpot pool will be larger than
that in the jackpot component of the expected value of a ticket. For
example, if a rollover occurs, the increase in sales will raise the
expected number of winning ticket-holders entitled to a share of the
grand prize, and this will moderate the increase in the jackpot
component of the expected value of a single ticket.
(4.) There are no double rollovers in our sample period. The rules
of the UKNL game permit a triple rollover in the event that two
consecutive draws fail to yield a winner of the grand prize, but no
instance of this has so far occurred.
(5.) We experimented with six lags of the dependent variable to
capture a richer pattern of habit persistence, but lags of order two and
above were always jointly insignificant (in either effective price or
jackpot models). For convenience, we report only the parsimonious forms
of the equations with a single lag.
(6.) The drop in sales associated with this particular draw may
have stemmed from the somber public mood or from the closure of many
retail outlets on the Saturday (the main day for buying tickets) or from
the decision not to televise the postponed draw.
(7.) In Farrell et al. (1999), the initial spurt of interest
following the introduction of the UKNL was captured by a variable
representing the number of retail terminals available. They had no trend
term as such. However, the significance of TREND in the Wednesday
equation for a period when the sales network was already fully in place,
suggests that the constraint of limited outlets was not the whole story
behind the pattern of sales following the first launch of lotto.
(8.) Farrell and Walker (1999) used microdata to compare buying
patterns between four regular UKNL draws on the one hand and one double
rollover draw on the other. The proportionate increase in participation
in the rollover draw was less than the increase in the level of
respondents' purchases conditional on participation.
(9.) Elasticities are calculated as short-run elasticity divided by
one minus the coefficient on the lagged dependent variable, computed at
the sample means for effective price. Short-run elasticities were -0.82
and -0.84.
REFERENCES
Clotfelter, C. T., and P. J. Cook. Selling Hope: State Lotteries in
America. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1989.
Conlisk, J. "The Utility of Gambling." Journal of Risk
and Uncertainty, 6(3), 1993, 255-75.
Cook, P. J., and C. T Clotfelter. "The Peculiar Scale
Economies of Lotto." American Economic Review, 83(3), 1993, 634-43.
Cox, D. R. "Tests of Separate Families of Hypotheses, in
Proceedings of the Fourth Berkeley Symposium on Mathematical Statistics
and Probability, vol. 1. Berkeley: University of California Press, 1961,
pp. 105-23.
-----. "Further Results on Tests of Separate Families of
Hypotheses." Journal of the Royal Statistical Society, Series B,
125(2), 1962, 406-24.
Farrell, L, and t. Walker. "The Welfare Effects of Lotto:
Evidence from the U.K." Journal of Public Economics, 72(1), 1999,
99-120.
Farrell, L., G. Lanot, R. Hartley, and I. Walker. "The Demand
for Lotto: The Role of Conscious Selection." Journal of Business
and Economic Statistics, 18(2), 2000, 228-41.
Farrell, L., E. Morgenroth, and I. Walker. "A Time-Series
Analysis of U.K. Lottery Sales: Long and Short Run Price
Elasticities." Oxford Bulletin of Economics and Statistics, 61(4),
1999, 5 13-26.
Forrest, D., O. D. Gulley, and R. Simmons. "Testing for
Rational Expectations in the U.K. National Lottery." Applied
Economics, 32(3), 2000a, 3 15-26.
-----. "Elasticity of Demand for U.K. National Lottery
Tickets." National Tax Journal, 53(4), 2000b, 853-63.
Friedman, M., and L. J. Savage. "The Utility Analysis of
Choices Involving Risk." Journal of Political Economy, 48(4), 1948,
279-304.
Garrett, T. A., and R. S. Sobel. "Gamblers Favor Skewness Not
Risk: Further Evidence from United States' Lottery Games."
Economic Letters, 63(1), 1999, 85-90.
Golec, J., and M. Tamarkin. "Bettors Favor Skewness, Not Risk
at the Horse Track." Journal of Political Economy, 106(1), 1998,
205-25.
Gulley, O. D., and F. A. Scott, Jr. "The Demand for Wagering
on State-Operated Lottery Games." National Tax Journal, 45(1),
1993, 13-22.
King, J. R. B. "Participation in the National
Lottery--Evidence from the Family Expenditure Survey." Journal of
the Royal Statistical Society, Series A, 160(2), 1997, 207-12.
Mason, P. M., J. W Steagall, and M. M. Fabritius. "The
Elasticity of Demand for Lotto Tickets and the Corresponding Welfare
Effects." Public Finance Review, 25(5), 1997, 474-90.
Miers, D. "The Implementation and Effects of Great
Britain's National Lottery." Journal of Gambling Studies,
12(4), 1996, 343-73.
Pesaran, H. "On the General Problem of Model Selection."
Review of Economic Studies, 41(2), 1974, 153-71.
Purfield, C., and P. J. Waldron. "Gambling on Lotto Numbers:
Testing for Substitutability or Complementarity Using Semi-Weekly
Turnover Data." Oxford Bulletin of Economics and Statistics, 61(4),
1999, 527-44.
Sauer, R. D. "The Economics of Wagering Markets." Journal
of Economic Literature, 36(4), 1998, 2021-64.
Scott, F. A. Jr., and O. D. Gulley. "Rationality and
Efficiency in Lotto Markets." Economic Inquiry, 33(2), 1995,
175-88.
Spanos, A. Statistical Foundations of Econometric Modelling.
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1993.
Thaler, R. H., and W. T. Ziemba. "Anomalies-Parimutuel Betting
Markets: Racetracks and Lotteries." Journal of Economic
Perspectives, 2(1), 1988, 161-74.
Walker, I. "The Economic Analysis of Lotteries." Economic
Policy 13(27), 1998, 359-92.
Wessberg, G. "Around the World in 80 Games." Presentation
to the Intertoto Congress, Oslo, August 1999.
ABBREVIATIONS
2SLS: Two-Stage Least Squares
UKNL: United Kingdom National Lottery
Neil Chesters *
* We wish to thank David Gulley; Economic Inquiry editor William
Neilson; seminar participants at the 11th International Conference on
Gambling and Risk-Taking, Las Vegas, NV, and the 2nd International
Equine Industry Conference, Louisville, KY; and two anonymous referees
for helpful suggestions.
Forrest: Lecturer in Economics, Centre for the Study of Gambling
and Commercial Gaming, University of Salford, Salford, M5 4WT, UK. Phone
+44-161-295-3674, Fax +44-161-295-2130, E-mail d.k.forrest@salford.ac.uk
Simmons: Lecturer in Economics, Centre for the Study of Gambling
and Commercial Gaming, University of Salford, M5 4WT, UK. Phone
+44-161-295-3205, Fax +44-161-295-2130, E-mail r.simmons@salford.ac.uk
Chesters: Analyst, Dresdner Kleinwort Wasserstein, Riverbank House,
2 Swan Lane, London EC4R 3UX, UK. Phone +44-20-7475-4432, Fax
+44-20-7929-5761, E-mail neil.chesters@drkw.com