AUCTIONS OF COMPANIES.
HANSEN, ROBERT G.
ROBERT G. HANSEN [*]
Auctions of companies are conducted in ways that contradict received auction theory The major puzzles are: (1) sellers restrict the
number of bidders; (2) sellers restrict the number of bidders; (3)
bidders are screened by an initial round of nonbinding bids; and (4)
bidders offer--and sellers sometimes accept--preemptive bids. Puzzles
(1), (2), and (4) are explained by assuming that some information
concerning the company can, if released, reduce the value of the
company. Puzzle (3) is explained as a way for sellers to select the
highest-valued bidders; equilibrium is maintained by using the initial
bids to set a reserve price for the final bidding round.
(JEL D44, D82, G34)
I. INTRODUCTION
From 1989 to 1998, 19,593 private companies were reported to be
bought and sold in the United States, many through an auction process.
The total value of these transactions was in excess of $315 billion. [1]
In addition, from 1989 to 1998, there were 13,134 reported divestitures
of divisions, subsidiaries, or product lines; the value of these
transactions was in excess of $900 billion. Perhaps not surprisingly, an
industry of advisors/auctioneers exists to facilitate these
transactions, and the institutional framework by which auctions of
companies are conducted has become somewhat standardized. The purpose of
this article is to apply auction theory to explain this standardized
institutional framework. The article proceeds as follows: section II
describes the standardized process used for selling private companies or
divisions of public companies; points out how these practices conflict
with certain aspects of received auction theory; and presents initial
arguments that explain the rationality of the practic es. In section
III, a more formal model is developed to show how some of the standard
corporate auction practices can be explained. Section IV deals with what
may be the most intriguing institutional practice--the use of
preliminary, nonbinding indications of interest. Section V concludes the
article with a preliminary discussion of entry fees and preemptive bidding.
II. THE "TYPICAL" AUCTION PROCESS AND CONSISTENCY WITH
AUCTION THEORY
The typical process for selling a private company or division of a
public company runs as follows. [2] Upon making the decision to sell,
the selling company will retain (or will already have retained) an
advisor who will serve as de facto auctioneer. The auctioneer, drawing
on knowledge of the selling company, will draw up a preliminary list of
potential bidders; this list will probably include competitors,
suppliers, customers, and acquisition-oriented conglomerates or
leveraged buyout houses. The advisor will also exercise his judgment at
this time as to whether or not a prospective bidder will be willing and
able to complete a transaction at a "satisfactory" price. If a
negative judgment is made, that potential bidder will likely be excluded
from further participation. The remaining prospective bidders will
receive a very cursory description of the selling company and will be
offered a more in-depth offering memorandum if they sign a
confidentiality agreement. Although the first cursory description may no
t even include the selling company's name, the offering memorandum
will be quite detailed, including the sort of information that would
typically be in a public corporation's Securities and Exchange
Commission 10K filing as well as traditionally confidential information on current issues at the selling company, overview of costs, plans for
market and product developments, and so on. The next step is for the
prospective bidders to submit preliminary, nonbinding "indications
of interest" for the selling company. These indications will be
either a number or a range of numbers that are supposed to represent
"bidders' first approximations of their estimates of the value
of the target." [3] The preliminary indications are then used by
the auctioneer to further reduce the number of bidders who will proceed
further: "Only the top bidders on their list are permitted to go
forward" [4] Although the screening is clearly not as
straightforward as the preceding passage presumes, there is no doubt
that the likelihood of ad mittance to the next round increases with the
preliminary bid--even though that bid is nonbinding. [5]
Since explaining this institutional practice of requiring
submission of preliminary, nonbinding indications of interest is a
primary purpose of this paper, it is important to establish that the
practice is indeed common. Besides the references to Macy (1990), I have
spoken with numerous investment bankers who confirm that a round of
preliminary indications of interest is standard practice. A
representative quote is as follows: "When our firm is engaged by a
selling company to conduct an auction, we always ask potential buyers to
submit preliminary, nonbinding indications of interest. These
indications are typically ranges of values, and those potential buyers
with low ranges are more likely to be excluded from the ensuing auction
than buyers with higher ranges, ceteris paribus. This is standard
practice at all investment banks with which I am familiar." [6] I
have also reviewed two documents from major New York City investment
banks that spell out a typical auction process. The process as described
in these documents is entirely consistent with the description given
here.
For those potential buyers who sign confidentiality agreements and
are qualified by their preliminary indications, the next round of the
selling process ensues with more extensive dissemination of information.
This process includes visits with and presentations by senior management
of the selling company; plant and site visits; and review of financial,
legal, and other documents that are assembled by the selling company and
its advisor in a "data room." Information released in this
phase of the selling process is quite detailed and definitely of use to
potential buyers in their valuation of the selling company. Some of the
headings in one investment bank's "Information Request"
(given to the selling company to prepare for visits with potential
buyers) are as follows:
* Other market trends, including changes in unit pricing
* Historical and projected volume of units sold for each major
product and/or product line
* A descriptive list of the company's key customers, which
includes dollar amount and percentage of sales attributable to each, and
special concessions given
* Description of any products and/or product lines presently in
development stage, including expected dates of introduction, results of
any testing, and expected financial results
* Description of each major component of cost-of-sales and a
detailed list of direct general, selling, and administrative expenses
attributable to each major product
* Description of the terms of any long-term supply contract or any
other major commitment regarding the purchase of raw materials
* Major items of equipment and facilities used in the production
process, including age and condition, total available production
capacity, and amount of capacity used
* Specialized projected income statements for the next five years
by product and/or product line and by geographic region
Although much of this information will be presented in the offering
memorandum in a way designed by the selling company's advisor,
original documents (for example, internal accounting data and actual
supply contracts) will be available in the data room for review by
potential buyers.
It is important to note that although the information given to
potential buyers is extensive, it is not complete. Throughout the
auction process, potential buyers may ask for information that the
selling company will view as too confidential to reveal. The divestiture manual I reviewed notes this and adds that such information will
generally be "that which is believed to be advantageous to
competitors, or cost information believed to threaten relations with
suppliers or employees."
The final step in the auction is for bidders to submit sealed bids
for the purchase of the company. Because these bids may not be purely
cash bids, choosing the best bid might represent a valuation problem for
the selling company. Also, it is important to note that any time during
this process a bidder might make a preemptive bid to short-circuit the
sale. The most likely time for a preemptive bid, however, is before the
last round of intensive information gathering.
There are aspects of this auction process that are interesting as
they stand, but the process calls more strongly for explanation because
it conflicts with standard results in auction theory and/or with what
would appear to be rational behavior on the part of bidders. More
explicitly, let me arrange the stylized facts of the auction process in
this manner:
Stylized Fact #1: Sellers restrict the number of bidders.
Stylized Fact #2: Sellers restrict the flow of information to
bidders.
Stylized Fact #3: Sellers choose the set of final-round bidders by
staging an initial round of nonbinding bidding; the probability of
getting into the final round increases with the initial round bid.
Stylized Fact #4: Bidders sometimes offer preemptive bids that
sellers sometimes accept.
Stylized Fact #1 contradicts a basic tenet of auction theory:
having more bidders increases the expected selling price. Although there
are auction models where it pays the seller to restrict bidders by
charging entry fees, these do not explain the practice observed in
corporate auctions because no entry fees are charged in these auctions.
[7] Also, standard auction models imply an optimal reserve price for the
seller that implicitly limits the number of bidders (those with value
less than the reserve price will not bid) but the limitation in these
models is passive: bidders elect to participate or not; they are not
told by the seller that they cannot participate, In the absence of entry
fees, existing auction models give no rationale for excluding bidders.
Stylized Fact #2 contradicts a result by Milgrom and Weber (1982)
on prices and information that has been conveniently restated by McAfee
and McMillan (1987): "The seller can increase his expected revenue
by having a policy of publicizing any information he has about the
item's true value." [8] The intuition for this
price-increasing effect is that divulging information tends to reduce
the variance of bidders' value estimates, and this variance gives
bidders the incentive to strategically reduce their bids. Yet in
corporate auctions we see sellers purposely withholding relevant
information.
Stylized Fact #3 is difficult to understand in the face of bidder
rationality. If getting into the final round has any value at all (and
it cannot be negative, for the bidder could always elect to drop out),
then why not bid high enough in the first round to ensure participation
in the final round? But if everyone does this, the initial round bidding
must escalate indefinitely, and the seller would not be able to use the
initial-round bids to select bidders any more efficiently than random
selection. Perhaps the most commonly heard rationale for existence of
equilibrium is that "reputation effects" keep bidders from
bidding "too high." But for many bidders an auction of this
sort is likely to be a one-shot affair, so concern over reputation
should be minimal. Also, determining when "cheating" has
occurred--when a bidder opportunistically bids high just to get in the
final round--must be extremely difficult; after all, the initial round
bids must be nonbinding to allow for the possibility that, after seeing
m ore information, a bidder decides the company is worth less than he or
she originally thought. Yet bids in these initial rounds do appear to
represent some measure of a bidder's valuation, and sellers do
select bidders on the basis of their initial-round bids.
Stylized Fact #4--preemptive bidding--contradicts a finding by
Riley and Samuelson (1981) that the seller cannot improve expected
revenue by employing multiple rounds of bidding. [9] Preemptive bidding,
after all, can be thought of as another initial round of bids; the
seller stands ready to accept a bid in this initial preemptive round if
it is high enough. Although it may seem profitable for a seller to use
multiple rounds, with declining reservation prices, it turns out that
after accounting for how bidders will behave in the initial round (i.e.,
they will bid low because they anticipate a next round), the
seller's expected revenue will actually decline with such a scheme.
Yet we see preemptive bids made and accepted.
In this article, I argue that the overall process by which
companies are sold represents a balance between the benefits of getting
more bidders and of releasing more information against what I term the
competitive information cost. The idea is very simple: to accurately
value a selling company, a potential buyer needs more than just
projections or summary statistics, such as aggregate sales, profits, or
valuations done by third parties. Because many potential buyers will be
involved in the same industry as the selling company (as a competitor,
supplier, or customer) the question will often be how the selling
company will fit in with the buyer's existing operations. Thus,
financial details on products and product lines, geographic distribution
of sales, research and development plans, state of production
facilities, and contracts with suppliers, customers, and employees, will
be critical--just the sort of information noted above as being in a
typical information request. Information such as the "recipe"
for a product would probably not be critical to a buyer's
valuation, for the effect of the recipe can be seen in summary
statistics, such as sales data, and the recipe itself would be available
on conclusion of the purchase. Where the product is sold, to whom, and
for how much will be much more important, for a buyer may want to get,
for example, a marketing/distribution network that is complementary to
its own network.
The problem, however, is that the information relevant to an
accurate valuation may also be valuable to potential buyers in their
role as competitors, suppliers, or customers of the selling company.
Releasing information to a set of potential buyers that includes
competitors, suppliers, and customers may in fact reduce the value of
the selling company. This is what I refer to as the competitive
information effect: a negative relationship between the amount of
information given out, the number of bidders that information is given
out to, and the selling company's value to any one of the bidders.
[10] Given this, the selling company will find it optimal to limit both
the number of bidders and the amount of information it divulges; this
explains Stylized Facts #1 and #2. Furthermore, the seller will increase
profits if he can limit the number of bidders in a way that screens Out
low-valued bidders and admits high-valued bidders. I find that an
initial round of nonbinding bids can serve this purpose if the selle r
also uses the initial-round bids to set a reserve price for the
final-round auction. In this way, bidders are discouraged from bidding
too high in the first round: the higher the bid in the first round (for
any bidder) the higher the reserve price in the final round, and hence
the lower the expected profits for the bidder. [11] Indeed, it turns out
that the seller can elicit honest revelation of bidders' initial
value estimates by a suitable choice of functional relationship between
initial round bids and the final round reserve price.
This idea is just a formalization of a basic business tenet that I
believe most people would subscribe to: "When buying something, do
nothing to make the seller think that the item is worth a lot to
you." In either a negotiated or auction context, if the seller
believes that the item is worth a lot to a buyer, then the seller will
generally find it optimal to raise the reservation price or to bargain
harder. Thus, bidders in the initial round of a corporate auction must
balance the benefits of a higher bid (increased probability of entry in
the final round) against the costs (increased reserve price in the final
round). Of course, there are certain conditions that must hold for an
equilibrium to obtain; these are detailed below.
The final issue is that of preemptive bidding. Preemptive bidding
can also represent rational equilibrium behavior for bidders and the
seller in the presence of a competitive information cost. If the cost of
releasing information in the final round is large, then the seller may
find it better to accept any preemptive bid exceeding a critical level.
In doing this, the seller forgoes the benefit of price determination via
auction but also forgoes the value reduction due to information
disclosure. [12]
I turn to a more formal model for explaining the restrictions
placed on number of bidders and disclosure of information (Stylized
Facts #1 and #2). The following section will deal with preliminary
indications of interest--Stylized Fact #3.
III. A FORMAL MODEL FOR MANAGEMENT OF BIDDERS AND INFORMATION
DISCLOSURE
A. Assumptions on Bidders, Valuations, and Information
There will be N potential bidders for the company being sold. A
bidder's value for the company being sold will depend on both a
bidder-specific variable (the bidder's type) and on a common
state-variable that defines the condition of the selling company's
assets.
More formally, I make the following assumptions.
Assumption 1. Bidder's value for the selling company is given
as
(1) Value to bidder i = V([x.sub.i]; z)
where V(*) is a common valuation function; [x.sub.i] [epsilon] [x,
x] is a variable denoting the bidder's type known only by bidder i,
and z [epsilon] [z, z] is a random state variable, with probability
distribution G(z), known by bidder i only after purchase of the company.
Bidder i therefore has an ex ante expected value for the selling company
given as
(2) Bidder i's Prior E[V.sub.i]([x.sub.i]) Expected Value
= [integral] V ([x.sub.i]; z)dG(z).
Each bidder views his competitors' types as independent draws
from a probability distribution [functions of x]. [13]
Assumption 2. The seller has observations y = ([y.sub.1],...,
[y.sub.N]) on N random variables ([y.sub.1], ... [y.sub.N] that are also
correlated with z. If the seller discloses m of these observations to
the bidders, the bidder would update his beliefs on z using the
conditional probability distribution G(z\[y.sub.1], ..., [y.sub.m]).
In words, then, a bidder's valuation depends on a component
[x.sub.i], that is independent and specific to himself and on a
component z that is common to everyone but unknown. Bidders begin with
no information on z, but the seller has potential to give them
considerably more by disclosing all or part of his information
([y.sub.1],... ,[y.sub.N]). The seller's information can be thought
of as that which he puts into the data room and which he provides
through plant visits and management meetings.
There are two other characteristics to this seller's
information set that are crucial, however. First, I assume that
disclosure of the seller's information to more than just the
winning bidder has the effect of reducing the value of the selling
company to all of the bidders. As discussed above, the rationale for
this is that much of the seller's information is of a competitive
nature so that its disclosure to nonowners would lessen the economic
viability of the company. The second characteristic is a logical
corollary to the first: that the seller's information is itself of
value to the bidders. That is, if the seller's information is
competitive in nature, then the bidders would be willing to pay to get
it.
In more formal terms:
Assumption 3. If ([y.sub.1],..., [y.sub.m]) is observed by n
bidders, then the net value of the selling company to bidder i becomes
(3) Net value to bidder i
= V([x.sub.i], z) - f(n, m)
where [partial]f/[partial]n [greater than] 0 and
[partial]f/[partial]m [greater than] 0.
Assumption 4. The competitive value to bidder i of observing
([y.sub.1],... ,[y.sub.m]) is d. Thus, all bidders place the same value
on the information. [14]
B. Expected Sales Prices and the Optimal Number of Bidders and
Information Disclosure
The expected price that the seller receives if it auctions the
company will depend on m, its information disclosure; n, the actual
number of bidders; and the auction rule (open, sealed bid, etc.) used.
In the example that follows shortly, I will assume an open auction, but
the results of the article are not at all dependent on the specific
auction form used.
Because of the way information is assumed to affect valuations--it
simply reduces every bidder's value by the fixed amount f(n, m)--
it is straightforward to show that for any auction rule used, the
competitive information cost reduces the seller's proceeds by
exactly f(n, m). It will therefore be convenient to talk about the gross
sales price as the price before considering the competitive information
effect and the net sales price as being the gross price less f(n, m).
The gross expected price will be denoted as [E.sub.A] (p\n, m), where
the subscript A is simply a reminder that the expected price will depend
on the auction rules used.
Following well-known results in auction theory, we know that having
more bidders raises the gross expected price, so if [n.sub.1] [greater
than] [n.sub.2], then
(4) [E.sub.A](p\[n.sub.1],m) [greater than or equal to]
[E.sub.A](p\[n.sub.2],m).
Another well-known result in auction theory is that disclosure of
information also raises the expected price. Some benefit to the seller
of information disclosure is critical to the analysis here in order to
create a tension between disclosure versus withholding of information by
the seller. (If there is no benefit to the seller of disclosing
information, and if there is any cost at all to disclosure, then no
disclosure would be the best policy. This certainly conflicts most
strongly with observed practice.) Although the intuitive reasons for the
price-enhancing effects of disclosure are clear, the effect is assured
only with certain valuation and informational assumptions--if the
[x.sub.i] variables and z were affiliated, and if V([x.sub.i]; z) had
certain features, as in Milgrom and Weber (1982). As will be made clear
below, we do not wish to constrain the V([x.sub.i]; z) function in the
way that would ensure the price-enhancing effect of disclosure. This
said, the assumptions we make do not preclude a pri ce-enhancing effect
of information and in the numerical example provided a price-enhancing
effect does exist. Also in this regard, there is another very important
legal benefit to sellers from disclosing information: withholding
relevant information could be grounds for a claim of fraud. This legal
aspect by itself would create the tension between the benefits and costs
of disclosure at the heart of this article.
We will then assume that disclosure of information has a (gross)
benefit to the seller: if [m.sub.1] [greater than] [m.sub.2] then
(5) [E.sub.A](p\n, [m.sub.1]) [greater than or equal to]
[E.sub.A](p\n, [m.sub.2]).
With this groundwork established, the institutional facts of how
companies are sold are easy to justify. Although adding more bidders
does increase the "gross" expected selling price, the net
price--after subtracting the information cost--may actually decline.
Indeed, because it is likely that the gross selling price increases at a
decreasing rate in the number of bidders, there is likely to be an
interior optimum with the actual number of bidders less than the total
available. Similarly, as the seller reveals more information, the
marginal benefit of disclosure is likely to fall, so that there will be
an optimum level of disclosure that is less than complete.
Two extreme cases are worth mentioning at this point, for they
emphasize that the explanation given here for the "typical"
auction process assumes a significant but not overwhelming importance of
the competitive information cost. At one extreme, there would be little
or no competitive information cost, so the optimal policy for the seller
would be to have as many bidders as possible and to disclose fully. At
the opposite extreme, the competitive information cost would be so high
that the most attractive option for the seller would be to negotiate
solely with one bidder but to give complete information. Because only
the sole bidder receives the information, there is no cost to giving him
everything, and this is likely to increase the price that can be
negotiated. Thus, with companies where disclosure of even little
information could reduce the value of the company significantly, we
should not be surprised to see negotiated one-on-one sales. Section V
discusses this idea further along with the related one of p reemptive
bidding.
IV. SCREENING BIDDERS VIA AN INITIAL ROUND OF BIDDING
A. Introduction
In the previous section it was suggested that an interior optimum
exists for the number of bidders, but no mechanism was given for how the
actual bidders would be selected. We now inquire as to whether the
seller can somehow select final bidders in an efficient fashion,
selecting the ones of better type (higher prior expected value,
[EV.sub.i]). One approach would be to qualitatively evaluate the
potential bidders, focusing on how they might evaluate the selling
company. The goal here would be to try to choose those bidders that have
the most "synergy" with the selling company, that is, are most
likely to place a higher value on it.
Although this kind of screening undoubtedly does occur, my focus
here is on another process that could be complementary to the
qualitative screening: screening bidders through the use of an initial
round of nonbinding bids. My argument is that the selling company
commits itself to set a reserve price in the final round of bidding that
depends (positively) on the bids received in the initial round. Because
bidders' expected profits are decreasing in the reserve price, this
imposes a cost of bidding high in the first round. [15]
Furthermore, the cost imposed by a higher reserve price falls most
heavily on bidders with lower ex ante expected values, for they are more
likely to have a value that is less than the reserve price. This induces
low-valued bidders to put in lower first-round bids than bidders with
higher ex ante expected values, thereby creating a positive relation
between initial-round bids and ex ante expected values. Choosing the
highest initial-round bids then will ensure the seller of having a set
of final-round bidders with the highest ex ante expected values--and to
the extent that higher ex ante values lead to higher ex post values,
this will maximize the final selling price.
B. An Illustrative Example
Before proceeding to a general model showing the equilibrium of the
first-round auction, it will be useful to develop a very simple example
of a two-stage auction that clearly shows the principles at work. The
example will also highlight the importance of one assumption concerning
the interaction between information and bidder's valuations.
This example will have five potential bidders, with each bidder
being characterized by their type. Type will take on one of two values,
call them HI and LO. There will also be a state variable, which will
also take on one of two values. Table 1 shows how type and state
together determine a bidder's valuation (their value for the
company being sold).
We assume that bidders' types are privately known and that the
probability of any bidder being HI or LO is 1/2. The state variable is
meant to cover the economic conditions of the company being sold; state
will be unknown to the bidders ex ante but will be revealed by the
seller in the second round of the auction through disclosure of
proprietary information. Ex ante, bidders believe each state to be
equally likely. Thus, HI bidders have an expected value of the company
of 110, whereas expected value for LO type bidders is 105.
Note that this set-up fits the general assumptions described above.
Value to a bidder is V([x.sub.i]; z) where [x.sub.i] is type and z is
the state variable.
A very important aspect of these assumptions is that the ranking of
bidder's valuations depends upon the state. As already noted (see
note 13), this is unusual in auction theory. It is also critical for
equilibrium in the model. For both of these reasons, the rationale for
the underlying assumptions deserves discussion.
Let me turn first to why the assumption is critical for the
model's equilibrium. This article argues that preliminary,
nonbinding bids can reveal useful information to the seller (the
bidder's types--HI or LO) if there is a cost to the bidders of
dishonest reporting. The cost being considered works through the setting
of the reserve price in the final round: High initial bids lead to
higher reserve prices. For this mechanism to work, all bidders must see
the possibility of positive expected profits in the final round;
otherwise an increase in the reserve price could have no impact. Yet in
received auction theory, the bidder of lowest type ex ante knows they
will always be the lowest-valued bidder and must therefore have zero
expected profit. [16]
With the assumptions here, neither a HI or LO bidder knows ex ante
that they will be the low-valued bidder on disclosure of the state
variable--ranking of the bidders' valuations is state-dependent.
Both types of bidders therefore have the potential for positive expected
profit in the final-round auctions, and there is therefore the ability
of a reserve price mechanism to reduce that expected profit and induce
honest revelation through initial bids.
More important than just the preservation of an equilibrium, the
assumption on state/valuation interaction is economically reasonable,
and it has implications for efficiency in auctions.
On the assumption's reasonableness, note that all that is
being assumed is that the state variable affects bidders differentially.
Both types view state-2 as being better than state-1, but HI-type
bidders view state-I more unfavorably and state-2 more favorably than
LO-type bidders. Put differently, HI-types are more sensitive to the
state variable. From a general point of view, different utility
functions could give rise to these valuation differences. In the context
of corporate auctions, the different types of bidders could reasonably
lead to valuations that exhibit such differences. Suppose the
state-variable corresponds to the fundamental financial viability of the
selling company, and suppose a HI-type bidder is another industrial firm
while a LO-type bidder is a leveraged buyout house specializing in
corporate restructuring. An industrial buyer might well be more
sensitive to underlying financial viability, having a very high
valuation if the company is solid and a very low valuation if the
company is not viable. Or, to take another example, suppose the state
variable corresponds to an underlying resource or marketing capability
of the selling company. State-1, for example, could be a poor state of
new product development, while state-2 could be new products almost
ready for market. If new products are very important for a HI-type
bidder, they would naturally have a valuation that was more sensitive to
that state variable.
Numerous other situations could be envisioned: the state-variable
could correspond to the state of management talent, geographic
distribution of marketing and distribution resources, capacity
utilization of plants, etc. For all of these variables, it would seem
reasonable, if not likely, for bidder's valuations to respond
differently.
Another view on the assumption being made further supports its
economic rationale and its importance to economic efficiency. As pointed
out, an implication of the interaction between state and value
interaction is that the identity of the highest-valued bidder depends
upon the state. Again, from a general utility/preference point of view
this would not seem surprising: who is the highest-valued user of a
resource cannot be ascertained without knowing the state
(characteristics) of the resource itself. But in regard to economic
efficiency, there is now a social value to information disclosure that
is absent in received auction models (for an extreme example, consider
the common-value model, where information has no allocative role to play
since all bidders have the same valuation no matter the state). That
information in auctions can be important to allocative efficiency seems
intuitively appealing, but it cannot be unless the identity of the
high-valued bidder depends upon the state. [17]
Proceeding then with analysis of a two-stage auction under those
assumptions, we assume that in the initial round each bidder puts in a
nonbinding bid of either 105 or 110. [18] The actual value of the bids
is immaterial, but we choose them to equal the two bidders' ex ante
expected values. Five initial bids will be received, and the seller will
select the four highest to proceed into the second and final round. Ties
will be broken randomly. Before the final round, the seller discloses
proprietary information that reveals the state variable; in the final
round bidders therefore know their valuation (still privately). The
final-round auction will be an open auction (for ease of computing prices and profits). Most important, there will be a reserve price in
the final round that depends on the initial bids: The reserve price will
equal 80 if three or fewer initial bids come in at 110, but the reserve
price will jump to 90 if four or more initial bids come in at 110.
With these auction rules, LO-type bidders will elect to put in a
bid of 105 in the initial round and HI-type bidders will put in an
initial bid of 110. Thus, the auction elicits honest revelation of
bidders' ante expected values. LO-types do not mimic HI-types
because the expected increase in the reserve price from a high initial
bid affects the LO-types too much. To confirm this equilibrium, we must
check that honest revelation is optimal for both types. This
verification entails assuming that all other bidders are following the
proposed equilibrium strategy and seeing if unilateral defection pays
for one bidder.
First consider a HI-type. A HI-type can earn profit in the final
round only if he or she is the only HI-type. Assuming equilibrium
behavior by the other bidders, this implies that the other four bidders
must all be LO-types, and it also implies that the reserve price will be
80 in the final auction. By not honestly revealing in the initial round,
this HI-type would only forfeit a certainty of entry into the final
round in the one instance where he could make a profit, for if he
dishonestly reported 105 in the initial round, he would be
indistinguishable from the other four LO-types. And there is absolutely
no benefit in other situations for an initial bid of 105: Although this
would reduce the reserve price in some cases, there were already zero
expected profits in those cases because of the presence of other
HI-types. A HI-type is therefore strictly better off with an initial bid
of 110.
Next consider a LO-type bidder. A LO-type, by bidding 110 instead
of 105 in the initial round, may increase the likelihood that they get
into the final-round auction. The only case, however, where a LO-type
can make a profit is when they are the only LO-type in the final round.
By bidding 110 in the initial round rather than 105, a LO-type can
increase the likelihood that he or she gets into those final-round
auctions with three HI-types (with two LO-types and three HI-types, a
defecting LO-type assures entry in the final round.) The problem is that
with four initial bids of 110 in these cases, the reserve price becomes
90, eliminating the possibility of a LO-type making a profit. Thus,
there is only a net cost to bidding 110 instead of 105, and a LO-type
will honestly report his ex ante valuation in the initial round. (There
are other cases where defection by a LO-type increases their likelihood
of entry into the final round, but with other LO-types present in the
final round, there is no profit in these ca ses.) [19]
In this example, then, the seller can select four out of five
bidders to receive additional proprietary information and participate in
a final round auction. The two-stage process limits the number of
bidders in the final round so as to reduce potential for value
destruction through disclosure of competitive information, and it
ensures that the higher-valued bidders are selected--a HI type is always
selected over a LO type. [20]
C. A More General Formulation
Let me turn then to a more general characterization of this process
of screening bidders via an initial round of nonbinding initial bids.
The model will be set up as an honest revelation game; we will determine
the actions that the seller must take to elicit as initial bids the true
initial expected values from the bidders. There will be N potential
bidders, each of whom has a valuation function as described earlier. The
seller asks for initial bids [b.sub.i] from each bidder. The seller is
committed to a reserve price policy according to
(6) r = h([b.sub.1]) + ... + h([b.sub.N])
where [b.sub.i] is the i-th bidder's initial bid. The seller
also commits to an entry policy that specifies a relationship between a
bidder's initial bid and the likelihood of that bidder being
admitted to the final round. This relationship will be described by the
function p(b), where p(b) is the probability of final-round entry given
an initial bid of b. It is assumed that p(b) is increasing in b.
Initial round bids will be chosen by bidders to maximize
(7) Bidder i's expected profit
= p([b.sub.i])(E([[pi].sub.i]\[EV.sub.i], [b.sub.i]) + d)
where [EV.sub.i] is bidder i's ex ante expected value, itself
a function of the bidder's type [x.sub.i];
E([[pi].sub.i]\[EV.sub.i], [b.sub.i]) is bidder i's expected profit
in the final round conditional on his type and initial bid; and d is
expected value of information to bidder released in final round.
Equation (7) is a compressed version of the typical bidder's
overall expected profit. It is important to note that E([[pi].sub.i]) is
itself a function of [b.sub.i], for [b.sub.i] affects the expected
reserve price in the final round and the reserve price affects expected
profit. Taking the first derivative of equation (7) with respect to
[b.sub.i] and setting to zero, we have
(8) (dp([b.sub.i]))/(d[b.sub.i])(E([[pi].sub.i]\[EV.sub.i],
[b.sub.i]) + d) + p([b.sub.i])(dE([[pi].sub.i]\[EV.sub.i],
[b.sub.i]))/(d[b.sub.i]) = 0
or
(9) (dE([[pi].sub.i]\[EV.sub.i], [b.sub.i]))/(d[b.sub.i]) =
(-dp([b.sub.i])/d[b.sub.i](E([[pi].sub.i]\[EV.sub.i], [b.sub.i]) + d))
/(p([b.sub.i]))
Equation (8) has a simple interpretation. The first term represents
the marginal benefit of raising the initial bid: A higher bid increases
the probability of receiving (E([[pi].sub.i]\[EV.sub.i], [b.sub.i]) +
d). The second term of (8) depicts the marginal cost of raising the
initial bid: p([b.sub.i]) multiplied by the reduction in final-round
expected profit due to the expected higher reserve price. Note that the
marginal cost of bidding higher will be decreasing in [EV.sub.i]: For
higher-value bidders, the impact of a higher reserve price is lower.
Thus, bidders with higher [EV.sub.i] will choose to put in higher
initial bids because the marginal cost of higher bids is lower. [21]
To elicit honest revelation, that is, [b.sub.i] = [EV.sub.i], the
seller must set p(b) and r = h([b.sub.1]) + ... h([b.sub.N]) such that
equation (9) holds for all values of [EV.sub.i] when bidders set
[b.sub.i] = [EV.sub.i]. If we make the substitution [b.sub.i] =
[EV.sub.i] in (9), and assume for now an arbitrary p(b) function, then
equation (9) becomes a first-order differential equation that, when
solved, yields the h(b) function that elicits honest revelation. This
can be seen by noting that Leibniz's Rule allows us to write
(10)(dE([[pi].sub.i]\[EV.sub.i], [b.sub.i]))/(d[b.sub.i])
= E[(d[[pi].sub.i]([EV.sub.i], [b.sub.i]))/(d[b.sub.i])]
= E[((d[[pi].sub.i]([EV.sub.i],
[b.sub.i]))/(dr))((dr)/(d[b.sub.i]))]
= (dh)/(d[b.sub.i])E[([d[[pi].sub.i]([EV.sub.i], [b.sub.i]))/(dr)]
where the last step is made possible from the definition r =
h([b.sub.1]) + ... + h([b.sub.N]), so that dr/d[b.sub.i] =
dh/d[b.sub.i], and this is independent of other bids.
Thus, we can rewrite equation (9) (with the honest revelation
condition [b.sub.i] = [EV.sub.i]) as
(11) (dh([b.sub.i]= [EV.sub.i]))/(d[b.sub.i])
= [(-dp([b.sub.i] = [EV.sub.i]))/(d[b.sub.i])
x [E([[pi].sub.i]\[EV.sub.i], [b.sub.i] = [EV.sub.i]) + d])
/[p([b.sub.i] =
[EV.sub.i])E[(d[[pi].sub.i]([EV.sub.i],[b.sub.i]=[EV.sub.i]))/(dr)]]
Equation (11), a first-order differential equation, is the main
incentive-compatibility constraint for the direct revelation game for
the first-round auction. For a given p(b), equation (11) can be solved
to yield the h(b) function, which will induce each bidder to report his
true prior expected-value, [EV.sub.i], as his first-round bid. Note that
dp/db is assumed to be positive and d[[pi].sub.i]/dr must be negative,
hence dh/db must be positive: The reserve price increases with the
initial bids. As is often true in auction theory, it is not possible to
analytically solve (11) for the general form of the h(b) function. [22]
However, as the example illustrates, reserve price functions consistent
with incentive compatibility can be found for specific cases.
One important caveat remains to be explored, however, that will
further develop the incentive-compatibility constraints for this model.
I have implicitly assumed that all bidders find an interior optimum
according to equation (11). This may not always be the case. Suppose a
bidder considered raising his initial bid beyond [b.sub.i] = [EV.sub.i].
Doing so increases the expected reserve price and reduces expected
final-round profits, E([[pi].sub.i]\[EV.sub.i], [b.sub.i]). There may
come a point where a bidder's expected final-round profit goes to
zero as higher initial bids are contemplated. If this occurs, then
higher initial bids serve to increase overall expected profit, for they
simply increase the chance of getting the competitive information value,
d. In such a case, the bidder would have to compare overall expected
profit with initial bid [b.sub.i] = [EV.sub.i] (a local maximum) to
overall expected profit with initial bid [b.sub.i] = b, where b is the
highest possible initial bid, in order to determine the overall best
bid. (Overall expected profit in the latter case will be just p(b)d.)
Figure 1 can be used to develop the condition that ensures that the
corner solution [b.sub.i] = b does not yield greater overall profit to
any bidder than [b.sub.i] = [EV.sub.i]. This analysis also tells us
something about how much the seller can differentiate between bidders in
regard to their entry into the final round.
When bidding [b.sub.i] = [EV.sub.i], an arbitrary bidder has
overall expected profit p([b.sub.i] =
[EV.sub.i])(E([[pi].sub.i]\[EV.sub.i], [b.sub.i] = [EV.sub.i]) + d),
denoted as point B in Figure 1. Let us suppose for ease of exposition
that p(b) is linear. Then in considering higher initial bids, this
bidder finds that at some bid [b.sup.*], his final round expected
profit, E([[pi].sub.i]\*) becomes zero (because of the implied increase
in reserve price); after this point, his overall expected profit
increases linearly with [b.sub.i]. At the highest feasible initial bid,
his overall expected profit would be p(b)(d), indicated by point C in
the diagram. For the seller to elicit honest revelation, we must have
the following inequality hold for all possible [EV.sub.i] in addition to
the main incentive-compatibility constraint (equation 11):
(12) p([b.sub.i] = [EV.sub.i])(E([[pi].sub.i]\[EV.sub.i], [b.sub.i]
= [EV.sub.i]) + d) [greater than or equal to] p(b)d
Equation (12) illustrates once again the importance of all bidders
having positive expected profits in the final-round auction, when they
honestly bid their initial expected value. If some bidders did not have
positive expected profits, then (12) could not hold and this bidder
would find it most profitable to put in an initial bid equal to b just
to ensure getting into the final round to capture the value of the
information to be released in that round.
Equation (12) can also be viewed as a restriction on the p(b)
function, or more intuitively, on how discriminating the seller can be
with his screening policy. Consider a bidder with the lowest possible
[EV.sub.i], who in equilibrium must submit an initial bid equal to this
minimum expected value and therefore have the lowest probability of
entry into the final round. For this initial bid to indeed be the global
optimum for the bidder, equation (12) must hold. To make (12) hold, the
seller may have to flatten the p(b) function, that is, make the
difference between p(b) and p(b) smaller. Such a flattening will
eliminate the incentive for this bidder to deviate from honest
revelation. However, doing so also reduces the discrimination inherent
in the initial round of bids, for a low-valued bidder becomes relatively
more likely to gain admittance to the final round.
V. DISCUSSION
This article does not claim that the observed set of auction
practices is the single best mechanism for selling a company, only that
the set of practices yield a net selling price in excess of what an
unrestricted auction (in terms of bidder participation) would yield if
the competitive information cost is sufficiently high. Although the
practices seem to be reasonable in these terms, they should be compared
to at least one other set of practices that might yield similar if not
improved results: Instead of screening bidders via initial round bidding
that produces no revenue by itself, why should the seller not ask
bidders to submit cash bids for the right to see the second round of
information and get into the final bidding round? The seller could then
select only those bidders who bid above a certain amount, thereby
accomplishing a reduction in the set of bidders; the seller would also
receive revenues directly from this initial round auction.
There are several possible explanations for why entry into the
final round is determined via a preliminary round of bidding rather than
via entry fees. One likely explanation has to do with
incentive-compatibility on the part of the selling company. With
screening accomplished via initial bids, the seller gets no revenue
unless he carries through with the final auction. If screening is
accomplished via entry fees, the selling company would receive
significant revenues even before selling the company. There is certainly
the possibility that some companies would entertain the option of
beginning an auction process only to collect entry fees. [23] Another
problem with entry fees relates to the optimal number of bidders in the
final round. If entry fees are used to get the same number of final
bidders as nonbinding bids, then there will necessarily be less overall
expected profit for the bidders--with the same number of bidders in the
final round, profits in that stage must be the same, but entry fees have
alrea dy been paid. This decrease in expected profits for bidders will
have to impact some decisions made by bidders on an ex ante basis. A
likely area of impact is how much effort will be put into evaluation of
the company in the initial round. If bidders put less resources into
initial evaluations, then screening via entry fees will be less
efficient at selecting final-round bidders and the selling company may
be worse off overall.
Returning to another issue mentioned previously, corporate auctions
are sometimes short-circuited by one bidder offering a preemptive bid.
Generally, these bids will take this form: A bidder will indicate a
range of prices that they are willing to pay for the selling company,
subject only to review of certain information. As quid pro quo, the
selling company must then negotiate exclusively with the preempting
bidder; in particular, the selling company must not disclose any more
information to other bidders.
This last point is what makes dealing with only one bidder
potentially mutually beneficial: the competitive information effect can
be avoided by disclosing the information to only one bidder. If the cost
of disclosure is high, the seller should weigh the price-enhancing
effects of an auction against the value destruction due to disclosure.
Having only one bidder may well be optimal, [24] and it could be that it
is one of the bidders, through a preemptive bid, who forces the seller
to consider the trade-off.
Several outstanding questions concerning preemptive bids remain,
however. If the seller agrees to disclose to only one bidder and
negotiate exclusively with that bidder, what keeps that bidder from
behaving opportunistically ex post (offering a final price outside the
lower range of the preemptive bid); how should the seller choose which
bidder if any to negotiate with exclusively; and should the selling
company move to a more formal "preemptive" auction, asking
bidders to submit nonbinding bids for the right to negotiate
exclusively? As preemptive bids certainly do occur, the general topic
would be a rich one for further research.
Hansen: Norman W Martin 1925 Professor of Business Administration
and Senior Associate Dean, Tuck School, Dartmouth College, Hanover, NH
03755. Phone 1-603-646-2079, E-mail Robert.hansen@dartmouth.edu
(*.) Many of the ideas in this paper were generated when the author
worked as a consultant with LEK Consulting. The research was given
financial support by the Tuck Associates. I would like to thank the
editor, an anonymous reviewer, Rajesh Aggarwal, and participants at the
Tuck School Finance/Economics workshop for useful comments.
(1.) Mergerstat Review, 1999. I purposely exclude tender offers for
entire publicly traded companies as the auction process for such
transactions is not as structured as for private transactions.
(2.) Much of my information on this process derives from my
experience as a management consultant. Macy (1990) contains a
description of some aspects of the process. I also have on file two
documents produced by investment banks that describe the divestiture
process.
(3.) Macy (1990), 95.
(4.) Macy (1990), 95.
(5.) Bidders themselves will also choose to not participate in the
auction; such self-selection can occur at any stage of the process.
Presumably bidders will opt out when they perceive the costs of
participating as being greater than the expected benefits. Thus, there
is an implicit a priori equilibrium along the lines of French and
McCormick (1984), wherein the number of potential bidders who
participate in each step of the auction process is endogenously determined. Although this aspect of the process is not modeled here, the
idea is important, for it implies that there is not an unlimited number
of willing bidders and that bidders who enter the process have positive
expected profit.
(6.) Quote by Alex Fuchs of Morgan Stanley & Co., Inc.
(7.) In the model of French and McCormick (1984), for instance, a
seller could increase revenues by charging an entry fee and thereby
restricting the number of bidders, but it would never pay the seller to
restrict bidders without an entry fee. See also the discussion in Macy
(1990).
(8.) McAfee and McMillan (1987), 722.
(9.) Bulow and Klemperer (1996) show that an auction of a company
is always preferable to a negotiation so long as the auction attracts at
least one additional bidder. They do not, however, consider the
potential cost of releasing proprietary information, which is the
crucial assumption of this article. From discussions with investment
bankers, the decision to negotiate rather then auction does seem to
hinge on the existence of proprietary information that, if released,
could damage value.
(10.) For a competitive information effect to exist, the selling
company and the bidders must be competing on some front, and that
competition must be imperfect due to uncertainty. Disclosure of
information in the auction process can then affect that competition,
benefiting the bidders and destroying value of the selling company. Many
game-theoretic models of competition involving the selling company and
bidders would yield a competitive information effect. One possibility
would be the following: Envision the selling company as procuring inputs
via a sealed bid process. If one of the input suppliers finds out
another supplier's current bid (through the selling company's
disclosure), it could use that information to its advantage and the
selling company's disadvantage. Entry models could also yield a
competitive information effect. One of the bidders could be considering
entry into one of the selling company's product markets. In many
entry models, the profitability of entry depends on the incumbent's
cost. If disclosure during the auction reveals the selling
company's costs, that information could be profitably used by a
competitor. Other scenarios are readily envisioned: disclosure of
expansion/capital expenditure plans of the selling company could lead a
competitor to alter its own plans accordingly; disclosure of new
marketing programs or product developments could let a competitor
prepare competitive responses; and disclosure of profitability by
geographic region could help a new competitor free-ride on the selling
company's marketing efforts (by focusing its own efforts in those
areas revealed to be most profitable and avoiding the unprofitable
markets).
(11.) This mechanism works only if all bidders, even those with the
lowest ex ante valuation, have positive expected profits in the final
round auction. This is not the case in the standard auction model. The
assumptions laid out below do allow all bidders to have positive
expected profits; besides permitting equilibrium to hold in the model
here, the assumptions that lead to positive expected profits for all
bidders are of interest on their own.
(12.) Fishman (1988, 1989) also addresses the issue of preemptive
bidding, but his analysis differs from mine. In Fishman's models,
preemptive bidding arises out of a desire by one bidder to deter other
bidders from investing in information concerning the target.
Fishman's analysis and mine share the prediction that it will be
high-valued bidders who make successful preemptive bids.
(13.) Though this set-up is similar to that of Milgrom and Weber
(1982), it differs in that no restrictive assumptions are placed on the
V([x.sub.l]; z) function. In particular, Milgrom and Weber assume that
the V(*) function is nondecreasing in all its variables. This precludes
reversals in the ranking of bidders' valuations: if [x.sub.i]
[greater than] [x.sub.j], then V([x.sub.i]; z) [greater than]
V([x.sub.j]; z) for all z. As will be seen below, it is critical in the
model here that the ranking of bidders' valuations depend on the
state. The model as set up bears some resemblance to "almost
common-values" assumptions--see, for instance, Klemperer (1998). In
"almost common-values" auctions one bidder is given a slight
valuation advantage. In the model here, one bidder will be given a
slight advantage; the additional twist is that which bidder has the
advantage depends on the state.
(14.) It would be more realistic to have d as an increasing
function of m and, possibly, a declining function of n. These changes
would complicate the model but would not alter the essential
conclusions.
(15.) A higher reserve price with unchanged bidding strategies
lowers expected profits by reducing each bidder's probability of
winning. A higher reserve price will, at least with sealed bids, also
lead all bidders to increase their bids (conditional on expected
valuations). Thus, the new equilibrium bid strategy also implies lower
expected profits for bidders. The chance that the item remains unsold,
of course, means that the seller's expected revenue does not
increase monotonically with the reserve price. See Riley and Samuelson
(1981).
The issue of commitment by an auctioneer is important--see, for
example, the extensive discussion by McAfee and McMillan (1987, 703-04).
In a first-price sealed-bid auction, a setter has incentive to renege on the stated policy of selling to the highest bidder at his bid, for upon
seeing the highest bid the seller could (theoretically) infer the
bidder's true value and demand a price equal to that value. (More
practically, the seller would at least know that the winner would be
willing to pay something more than the received bid.) All auction theory
assumes that auctioneers can commit to a set of auction rules. I follow
in this tradition by assuming that the auctioneer commits to a reserve
price policy that is based on information revealed by the bidders in the
first round. Although it might be true that the auctioneer could profit
from reneging on his commitment and using the information revealed in a
more opportunistic fashion, I assume that long-term considerations by
the auctioneer (in my case, investmen t banks) prevent this. It should
also be noted that the reserve price policy I propose is rational for
the seller, if the seller is presumed to not know the distribution
function of bidders' values: an ex post optimal reserve price will
be higher, the higher are bidders' values. See Riley and Samuelson
(1981).
(16.) See, for example, Milgrom and Weber (1982) and the discussion
of that model in note 13.
(17.) As a further twist on this, it is easy to see that with
assumptions that permit ranking of valuations to depend on the state,
disclosure of information may reduce the seller's expected price.
In the example, and with just two bidders, one HI and one LO, expected
price in a second-price auction is 105 without disclosure of state and
is 100 with disclosure. Thus, a tension exists between a seller's
revenue and economic efficiency in relation to disclosure of
information.
(18.) For clarity of presentation, we ignore in the example both
the strategic information cost and the competitive value of information
to bidders. The strategic information cost is implicit for that is why
the seller wants to restrict bidders. The competitive value of
information could exist, so long as it was not too great, and the
equilibrium would still hold.
(19.) An important characteristic of the example is that LO-types
win against HI-types in State 1, which is the low-value state for both
types of bidders. Because the reserve price is binding only in the
low-value state, this causes the LO-types to put in the lower
initial-round bids.
(20.) The last question would be whether, in this example, the
seller is indeed better off with the two-stage procedure than with just
selling without disclosure but with all five bidders. The first thing to
note here is if there is a legal cost to nondisclosure, then the
two-stage procedure could definitely be better. Without a legal cost to
nondisclosure, the question comes down to any price-enhancing effect of
disclosure and any benefit to selection based on initial bids. In this
example, there is a price-enhancing effect of disclosure; in the absence
of a reserve price, the sellers expected revenue is higher with four
bidders and disclosure than with five bidders and no disclosure.
However, the reserve price affects this, for in some instances the
seller does not sell the item (this occurs in state 1 with at least four
HI bidders, so the reserve price is 90.) The seller is better off with
the two-stage procedure (versus nondisclosure but five bidders) so long
as the value of the selling company to the se ller is at least 63.33 in
state 1. It is also of interest to note that because of the
expected-value differences between the bidder types, random selection of
four bidders is worse than selection based on initial bids.
(21.) Note that with the model as formulated, there is no
possibility of a bidder having a high [EV.sub.i] simply because he got a
high signal for the unknown state variable z. That is, in the model, all
bidders start with common information on z. In a more general
formulation, bidders could start with private information on z; this
would allow for the interesting possibility of selecting bidders through
initial bids who are just overestimating value--the classic
winner's curse.
(22.) In Hansen (1988) for example, comparison of different auction
rules is accomplished entirely through comparison of the differential
equations that define equilibrium bidding strategies. No general
solution of the differential equations is required and, indeed, would
add little to the understanding of the model.
(23.) One must note that problems in commitment plague almost any
auction rule. The point here is just that entry fees would create one
more level to the selling company's commitment.
(24.) As a simple example, suppose with two bidders in the final
auction the net price would be $0.70 (think of this as a gross expected
price of $1 reduced by a competitive information effect of $0.30). If by
negotiating with only one bidder the seller could avoid the competitive
information effect and receive (net) anything greater than $0.70, then
negotiating with one bidder would be optimal.
REFERENCES
Bulow, J., and P. Klemperer. "Auctions vs. Negotiations."
American Economic Review, 86(1), 1996, 180-94.
Cramton, P., and A. Schwartz. "Using Auction Theory to Inform
Takeover Regulation." Journal of Law, Economics and Organization,
7, 1991, 27-53.
Fishman, M. J. "A Theory of Preemptive Takeover Bidding."
Rand Journal of Economics, 19(1), 1988, 88-101.
-----. "Preemptive Bidding and the Role of the Medium of
Exchange in Acquisitions." Journal of Finance 44(1), 1989, 41-57.
French, K. R., and R. E. McCormick. "Sealed Bids, Sunk Costs,
and the Process of Competition." Journal of Business 57(4), October
1984, 417-41.
Hansen, R. G. "Auctions with Endogenous Quantity." Rand
Journal of Economics, 19(1), 1988, 44-58.
-----. "Socially Productive Information and Expected Prices in
Auctions." Tuck School mimeo, 1991.
Hirschleifer, J., and J. G. Riley. The Analytics of Uncertainty and
Information. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1992.
Klemperer, P. D. "Auction Theory: A Guide to the
Literature." Journal of Economic Surveys, 13(3), 1999, 227-60.
Klemperer, P. D. "Auctions with Almost Common Values."
European Economic Review, 42, 1988, 757-69.
Macy, J. R. "Auction Theory, MBOs and Property Rights in
Corporate Assets." Wake Forest Law Review, 25, 1990, 85-119.
McAfee, P. R., and J. McMillan. "Auctions and Bidding."
Journal of Economic Literature, 25(2), 1987, 699-738.
Milgrom, P., and R. J. Weber. "A Theory of Auctions and
Competitive Bidding." Econometrica, 50(5), 1982, 1089-1122.
Reece, D. K. "Competitive Bidding for Offshore Petroleum
Leases." Bell Journal of Economics 9(2), 1978, 369-84.
Riley, J. G., and W. F. Samuelson. "Optimal Auctions."
American Economic Review, 71(3), 1981, 381-92.
Type, States, and Valuations
State
Bidder Type 1 2
HI 80 140
LO 90 120