MAJORITARIAN MANAGEMENT OF THE COMMONS.
Buchanan, James M. ; YOON, YONG J.
YONG J. YOON [*]
This article analyzes usage of a common property resource,
"the commons," under collectivization as compared with more
familiar privatization institutional arrangements. Particular emphasis
is on majority decision rules. When separate majority coalitions may
authorize simultaneous usage of a common resource, total value is
dissipated, but the interdependencies introduced by possible membership
in differing coalitions to an extent reduce the incentives for
exploitation. The formal analysis is analogous to that familiar in
Cournot-Nash duopoly-oligopoly models but with differing efficiency
implications. The argument has relevance for differential-benefit public
spending from general tax sources, as well as other applications. (JEL
D7, H00, 02)
I. INTRODUCTION
The operation and management of common property resources,
"the commons," have been exhaustively examined in economics
and political science, both in formal analyses and in practical
application. [1] However, the full range of institutional alternatives
has not been covered, even at a level of stylized interaction models.
Our purpose in this article is to fill in at least some of the gaps here
and, specifically, to examine the predicted results that emerge when
usage decisions are collectivized under majoritarian voting rules. To
our knowledge, this analysis has not been undertaken.
We shall, in section II, first summarize the classic analysis along
with the familiar institutional reform suggested as a solution to the
"tragedy." This solution, "privatization," is
analyzed under several institutional variants in section III. We then
shift attention, in section IV, to arrangements under which usage of the
commonly shared resource or facility is chosen by some predesignated
collective decision rule.
Specifically, we concentrate analysis on the predicted results in
several majority rule environments. We analyze thoroughly the case in
which different majority coalitions make usage decisions separately and
simultaneously. The analysis incorporates recognition on the part of any
member of a specific majority of the prospect for membership in
alternative majority coalitions. We demonstrate that instead of full
dissipation the level of usage that emerges in the limit is structurally
analogous to the outcome in the Cournot-Nash duopoly model, even if the
efficiency implications differ in the two settings.
II. THE CLASSIC MODEL SUMMARIZED
The familiar "tragedy of the commons" lends itself to
stylized illustration. An immobile but renewable resource exists (a
common pasture, aquifer, fishing ground) and has economic value if used
effectively through the application of units of complementary mobile
resources that are themselves valued in their alternative market
opportunities. There are no assigned ownership rights to the immobile
resource or facility. Free and open access may dissipate most or even
all of the potential value.
Consider Figure 1. The productivity of mobile complementary
resource units, as applied elsewhere in the economy (e.g., steers grazed
on the open range, beyond the commons) is set at w, a value assumed
constant. The quantity of such inputs applied on the commonly used
facility is measured along the abscissa. In Figure 1, the marginal and
average productivity curves for the units of applied complementary
resource are shown as MP and AP. Total value is maximized when [Q.sub.m]
units are applied, at which point marginal product values are equalized
as between this usage and other opportunities. The maximal value of the
commonly used resource is the area under the MP curve above w.
If entry to usage is open, and if the institutional structure is
such as to allow for decentralized decisions on the part of many
potential users, rational choices made separately will generate a full
behavioral equilibrium at [Q.sup.*], where "average" product
per unit of the complementary resource is equalized as between the
commons and other uses. [2] The commons is overutilized in the sense
that its capacity to generate positive value is fully dissipated. In the
limit, the economy, in the aggregate, generates the same value with and
without the existence of the resource.
The institutional reform that is suggested to be required to
generate efficient usage is summarized under the word privatization.
Assignment of rights of ownership will shift the incentive structure.
The assigned owner will find it advantageous to restrict usage of the
facility to the profit-maximizing level. In the illustration, all users
will he charged a price (or shadow price) of (y - w) per unit of
complementary resource, thereby generating equilibrium usage at
[Q.sub.m]. A single owner of the facility, or a single person (group)
assigned exclusive rights of usage, has an incentive to operate the
facility optimally (through internal shadow pricing or external pricing)
because the interdependencies among the separate units applied to the
facility are brought within the single decision calculus.
Note that the familiar model embodies only two alternative
equilibria: (1) complete dissipation under open access ([Q.sup.*]) and
(2) fully efficient usage ([Q.sub.m]) under private ownership. Open
entry, consequent on the absence of ownership, along with monopoly or
single ownership with rights of full exclusion, are the only two
institutional arrangements normally considered. [3]
III. MULTIPLE USERS
In this section, we analyze institutional arrangements in which
usage of the shared facility is not open to all who might desire access,
but, at the same time, rights of usage are not assigned to a single
person or to a single group within which incentives are perfectly
aligned.
Consider, first, a modified "privatization" arrangement
that assigns rights to two selected persons. Each of these persons is
allowed to apply as many units of the complementary resource to the
facility as she desires. The designated "owners" may apply
units directly or they may sell permits to others, thereby securing
rents.
What level of usage will emerge in this institutional structure?
When rights to use the facility are granted simultaneously to two
persons (groups) rather than only one, only part of the
interdependencies are internalized. Total usage will be extended beyond
that level that meets efficiency criteria but will remain below the
level that defines total value dissipation. [4]
The characteristics of interaction in the two-person model are
structurally similar to those in the stylized setting of Cournot-Nash
duopoly. In the two-person commons usage equilibrium, each user gets an
equal share in the value generated on the commons, although less than
one-half of the maximum value that a fully efficient operation would
ensure. The similarity to Cournot duopoly is formal rather than
substantive because the efficiency implications differ. In the classical
duopoly-oligopoly model, increases in the number of independently acting
firms reduce the efficiency loss from market restriction. In the commons
analogue, increases in the number of independently acting users increase
the efficiency loss from overutilization.
A similar construction may be carried out on models where more than
two parties are assigned rights to use the commonly shared facility.
Comparable analyses can be applied for larger numbers of users. [5]
An Illustrative Algebraic Model
Assume a simple linear production function for which the average
product is given by AP = k - X where k is a constant and X is the number
of units of mobile resources applied to the commons. A monopolist
(single owner) recognizes the interdependence among units and maximizes
rent by setting MP(X) = k - 2X = w, where w is the product generated per
unit of mobile resource applied in other uses (assumed constant). Net
rent for the monopolist is [(k - w).sup.2]/[2.sup.2].
Now suppose there are two "owners" (players). Following
an approach analogous to the standard Cournot-Nash, the variable under
control of each person is the number of units of mobile resources
([X.sub.i]). Given [X.sub.2], player 1 chooses [X.sub.1] to maximize the
rent, average product times her own input: Max (K - [X.sub.1] -
[X.sub.2]) [X.sub.1] where K = k - w. the first-order condition is
[X.sub.1] K/2 - [X.sub.2]/2. The symmetric solution is [X.sub.1] =
[X.sub.2] = K/3 and the aggregate rent is 2[K.sup.2]/9. With the same
aggregate production function, when there are n users, the symmetric
solution is [X.sub.i] = K/(n + 1) and the total rent is [nK.sup.2]/[(n +
1).sup.2]. Note that this value approaches zero as n approaches
infinity. [6]
As the simple illustrative model suggests, the potential aggregate
surplus (the productivity of the commonly used facility) asymptotically
approaches zero as the numbers of persons assigned rights of open access
increase. Note, however, that, for any finite number of assigned rights
owners, some share of the externalities will be internalized. The
emergent solution will approach but never attain the position depicted
at [Q.sup.*] in Figure 1, where all of the resource value is dissipated
through overusage. This position [Q.sup.*] is attained, however, when no
person or group is explicitly assigned rights to use the common
facility, but when all persons (groups), that is, anyone, may have
access. In this setting, any productivity above that available to mobile
resources elsewhere in the economy (w) will tend to attract users, no
one of whom will find it rational to restrict usage due to
internalization of external Diseconomies. [7]
IV. COLLECTIVE DETERMINATION OF USAGE
To this point, discussion has been preliminary to our primary
purpose, which is to analyze those settings in which, for any reason,
privatization is not implemented, even though the inefficient overusage
consequent on open access is acknowledged. Consider, then, the situation
where the choice of levels of usage of the common facility is explicitly
collectivized; usage levels are determined only on collective decisions
made by specified rules.
Our ultimate motivation for extending the commons metaphor to this
application rests on the central idea that democratic politics, as it
operates, allows members of majority coalitions to impose external
diseconomies on general taxpayers. Government actions emerge from
separately formed fiscal coalitions rather than from a monolithic
collectivity. The general tax base is subject to simultaneous
exploitation by majority coalitions of differing composition.
To isolate the differences that may be attributed to institutional
structures, as such, it is first necessary to ensure that the basic
economic relationships remain invariant. Recall the classic model in
sections II and III. There exists an immobile, renewable resource that
becomes productive of value if usage is restricted below the level that
open or free access would generate. Persons, in their private
capacities, will use the commons to secure the value added to their
privately owned complementary resource units that are applied to the
facility. There is no "publicness" in the benefit streams
sought by those who use the commons, whether or not the number of users
is restricted.
This feature of the model must be retained, as the decisions on
usage are shifted from individual users to collective institutions. The
values that emerge from usage of the commons are separable as among
users. The rule for making collective decisions will then determine not
only the level of usage of the commonly shared facility but also the
distribution, among users, of the surplus value that the commons
produces. To refer again to the familiar illustrative example, it is as
if coalitions of users, chosen by the operation of the collective
decision rule, are allowed to place jointly owned steers on a common
pasture. We assume that within any decisive coalition, members share
symmetrically in the surplus value, with no spillover benefits to those
outside the coalition, who remain, necessarily, nonusers. Within the
authoritative group incentives are perfectly aligned among individuals.
This assumption allows us to simplify our analysis and focus on
institutional structure and to ignore the incentive problems that may
arise among asymmetrically situated users.
Alternative Decision Rules in the Single-Choice Model
The simplest possible model where usage of the commons can be
settled is by a single choice. Initially, assume that a single person is
to be granted exclusive authority to make usage decisions for the
collectivity. Under the stylized assumptions of the model, the
designated decision maker will secure for him-or herself the full value
of benefits. Rational choice will dictate that usage of the commons be
restricted to that level that maximizes rent, thereby ensuring overall
efficiency in resource allocation.
Suppose, now, that, instead of a single dictator, the collective
decision rule is one of simple majority. Usage of the commons takes
place only on the decision made by a majority of the community
membership, any initial majority that happens to be organized. Because
we are in a one-choice model, however, any majority, once formed, will
have an incentive to use the facility so as to maximize rent. The only
difference between this model and that of the single person dictatorship
lies in the distribution of value. In the majority setting, all members
of the coalition share in this value surplus. Individuals that are not
coalition members do not have access.
The allocative result remains unchanged no matter what the required
size of the coalition that is charged with authority to make collective
decisions, including the rule that requires consent of all members of
the polity. [8] In the limiting case, unanimity, all persons share in
the surplus that the existence of the commons makes possible.
Alternative Decision Rules When Many Choices Are Possible
We may now examine settings that allow simultaneous choices to be
made separately, as authorized by a political decision structure. (The
budget process under majoritarian democracy offers an example.) If the
collective decision rule dictates that usage decisions may be made by
anyone, acting separately, the full "tragedy of the commons"
is present in the sense that all of the value potential of the facility
is dissipated. (The size of a decisive coalition is one in this case.)
As the collective decision rule becomes more inclusive, thereby allowing
usage decisions to be made only by coalitions of persons authorized to
take collective decisions, we can trace the relationships between the
size of decision-making coalitions and the total share of potential
value that is dissipated. This share of efficiency loss decreases as the
size of the decision-making coalitions increases. [9]
The interesting case to be examined in detail here is that which
allows differing majority coalitions, separately, to make usage
decisions. A practical fiscal example that comes to mind is that in
which special spending interest, combined in separate logrolling coalitions, exploit the general tax base. [10] In political reality,
many such coalitions might be formed. But it is analytically useful to
remain with the stylized model and suppose, initially, that only two
majority coalitions may be organized and that each coalition will be
allowed to use the commons at will. It is as if the separate coalitions
become separate "persons" who are assigned simultaneous rights
of usage.
Consider, then, the calculus of a member of one of these coalitions
as concerns separable usage of the commons by that coalition. If the
reference person knows that he or she will not be a member of the other
majority, the solution is analogous to that under privatization when two
person are assigned rights of usage. As noted earlier, the problem is
structurally similar to the classic Cournot-Nash models. Each decision
unit, in this case, each majority coalition, will internalize one-half
of the external diseconomies resultant from increments to usage rates.
Suppose, now, however, that the reference person is in a position
of neutrality or anonymity with respect to membership in the second
coalition. That is, it is as if the second coalition is to randomly
organized from among all members of the polity. The person then faces
the probability of one-half of being a member of the other majority.
[11] (To be more accurate, the probability depends on the size of
polity. Appendix A provides a rigorous derivation of this result.)
The usage decision of the reference person of the first coalition
can be formulated using the illustrative algebraic model introduced in
section III. The average productivity relationship of the commons is P =
K - X, where P is the average product, and X is the aggregate quantity,
divided between the two coalitions, X = [X.sub.1] + [X.sub.2]. Given
[X.sub.2], the reference person of the first coalition chooses
[X.sub.1], to maximize the rent [PX.sub.1] + [PX.sub.2]/2; the
productivity of mobile resource applied in other uses is assumed to be
zero. The necessary condition for rent maximization is K - [X.sub.1] -
[X.sub.2] - ([X.sub.1] + [X.sub.2]/2) = 0; the solution is [X.sub.1] =
K/2 - 3[X.sub.2]/4, and the symmetric equilibrium is [X.sub.1], =
[X.sub.2] = 2K/7. The result emerges from the simultaneous usage
decisions made by two separate majority coalitions. Aggregate usage is X
= 4K/7, which is less than the duopoly analogue quantity of 2K/3 but
larger than the monopoly (efficient) output K/2. That is, K/2 [less
than] 4K/7 [less than] 2K/3.
Note that efficiency is increased over that attained in the duopoly
analogue case. Externalities are internalized in two different channels,
which we may call the productivity externality and the membership
externality.
Only the productivity externality is internalized in the duopoly
analogue case.
By relaxing the assumption of only two coalitions, we may postulate m majority coalitions. [12] The individual member of any coalition, say,
coalition I, will prefer to apply [X.sub.1] units of mobile inputs,
given [X.sub.2],..., [X.sub.m], so as to maximize the effective rent,
(1) (K - [X.sub.1] - [X.sub.2] - ... - [X.sub.m])
x [[X.sub.1] + ([X.sub.2] + ... + [X.sub.m])/2].
The necessary condition for maximization is
(K - [X.sub.1] - [X.sub.2] - ... - [X.sub.m])
- [X.sub.1] - ([X.sub.2] + ... + [X.sub.m])/2 = 0,
and the symmetric solution is
[X.sub.1] = [X.sub.2] = ... = [X.sub.m] = 2K/(3m + 1);
the aggregate quantity is
X = [mX.sub.1] = 2mK/(3m + 1).
As the number, m, of majority coalitions increases, the aggregate
quantity X approaches the duopoly analogue equilibrium 2K/3 instead of
full dissipation K, which is predicted when the polity fails to
internalize productivity externalities. The reference person who knows
that all possible majority coalitions will be organized and authorized
to dictate collective action will recognize that he or she will be a
member of one-half of these coalitions. He or she will internalize
one-half of the externality of usage in his or her rational choice
calculus, there by generating a result equivalent to that reached when
two separated but symmetrical decision units hold usage rights. See
Appendix B.
Our analysis is based on the stylized model that satisfies the
sufficient conditions for existence and uniqueness of Nash
equilibrium--the revenue function is strictly concave. See Watts (1996)
for a general discussion on this issue.
V. UNCERTAINTY INTRODUCED
To this point, we have assumed that, although we have allowed for
probabilistic determination of any person's position in the
majoritarian models, genuine uncertainty, as such, has not been
incorporated into the decision calculus. But how may a person who holds
membership in an already organized majority coalition incorporate a
fully "rational" expectation that a specific number of
alternative majorities will be formed and authorized to make usage
decisions and, further, that he or she will really have a probability of
one-half of attaining membership in any such coalition? How can a
"rational" internalization of externalities take place?
There are two separate dimensions along which degrees of
uncertainty may be measured: (1) the probability of membership in
majority coalitions, and (2) the number of coalitions that will be
organized and authorized to make collective decisions concerning usage
of the commonly shared facility. These dimensions can be related, one to
the other, in a geometric representation as in Figure 2, which
incorporates the simple algebraic relationships introduced earlier.
The probability, h, of membership in majority coalitions is
measured along the ordinate; aggregate usage of the commons, X, is
measured along the abscissa. As the algebraic models indicate, efficient
(monopoly) usage of the commons is achieved when the probability of
being decisive is unity. If the reference person, whose decision
calculus is under examination, knows with certainly that he or she will
be a member of any decisive coalition that may be formed, his or her
choice will embody an internalization of all of the interdependencies of
commons usage; he or she will prefer to operate the facility efficiently
(at K/2 in Figure 2), regardless of the number of differing coalitions
that may be authorized to make decisions.
Suppose, however, that membership in coalitions is uncertain for
the reference person. Suppose she knows only that she holds membership
in one authoritative coalition; she remains uncertain both as to the
number, m, of other coalitions that may be authorized to utilize the
commons and as to the probability that she will, personally, be a member
of any other coalitions that may become authoritative.
The general model may be constructed, in which individuals may
assume a probability h of becoming a coalition member, and h can vary
over the whole range of probability, 0 [less than] h [less than] 1. We
assume that individuals know the number, m, of coalitions to be
organized. Later we relax this assumption.
Given the decisions [X.sub.i] of other coalitions, the current
majority coalition chooses [X.sub.1] to maximize the rent,
(2) (K - [X.sub.1] X')([X.sub.1] + hX'),
where X' = [X.sub.2] + ... + [X.sub.m]. The first-order
condition is K - [X.sub.1] - X' - ([X.sub.1] + hX') = 0; the
symmetric solution, [X.sub.1], and the aggregate usage, X, are,
(3) [X.sub.1](h,m) = K/[2+(1+h)(m-1)]; X(h,m) = mK/[2+(1+h)(m-1)]
The general characteristics of the symmetric solution for different
values of m and h are, as noted, depicted in Figure 2.
We may consider several stylized submodels, some of which we have
already introduced. Suppose that the reference person expects to be a
member of any majority coalition with a probability of one-half (h =
0.5). In this setting, we may array the set of positions along the
horizontal line drawn from one-half on the ordinate in Figure 2. The
extreme position, at T, represents the position discussed earlier, where
each and every possible majority is authorized to use the commons but
where the individual expects to be a member of each coalition with the
probability of one-half. The preferred degree of utilization of the
commons is analogous to the Cournot-Nash duopoly analogue equilibrium,
as is elaborated in Appendix A. [13] In the simple algebraic model,
usage of the commons is determined at 2/3 of that level reflecting full
dissipation of all value, whereas the efficient exploitation of the
facility is at 1/2 this level.
Note that, so long as the individual's expectations embody a
"fair chance" (or better) prospect (i.e., optimism), the
aggregate usage of the facility will lie between the duopoly-analogue
solution (at 2K/3 in Figure 2), and the monopoly-analogue solution (at
K/2 in Figure 2). Internalization of the interdependencies will cause
the reference person to act so as to generate usage rates below the
duopoly analogue solution in all cases.
With majority decision rules, a higher usage level will emerge only
if individuals' expectations concerning membership in alternative
coalitons are pessimistic, that is, if probabilities of being a member
of alternative coalitions are placed at less than one-half. Consider the
most extreme limit here. The individual who is a member of a current
majority does not expect to be a member of another majority with any
probability above zero. In this case, differing levels of usage may be
measured along the abscissa, as determined by the expected number of
alternative coalitions to be formed. If, for example, only one
alternative majority coalition is anticipated, although the reference
person holds no prospect at all of membership, the duopoly analogue
solution appears. Full dissipation of the facility will be generated if
the reference individual expects many other (unspecified number of)
majority coalitions to be organized and authorized to use the commons.
So far we have assumed that individuals make accurate assessment of
the number, m, of majority coalitions that are expected to be organized
and authorized to make simultaneous decisions on commons usage. If m is
uncertain, the reference person of a current majority coalition must
make usage decisions without knowing the number of simultaneous
coalitions that will jointly exploit the commons. In this setting, for
any given probability (h) of membership in alternative majorities,
increases in the expected number of coalitions will decrease individual
rates of usage of the common facility. Realized usage will, of course,
depend on the number of coalitions actually organized.
VI. ALTERNATIVE DECISION RULES IN TEMPORAL SETTINGS
To this point, we have limited analysis to models in which
decisions to use the commons are made for one period only, without
consideration of the choice settings in subsequent periods. Introduction
of a temporal dimension will not be important if the usage of the
commonly shared resource is, itself, temporally concentrated in a single
period, that is, if the resource fully renews itself each period (e.g.,
the pasture grass grows back each spring) while the decision authority
is invariant over a sequence of periods.
Suppose, however, that there exist intertemporal as well as
intratemporal interdependencies in usage of the commons. The addition of
a unit of the complementary resource to the facility will reduce the
productivity of all units both currently and also in subsequent periods.
In this setting, any dilution in ownership or decision authority,
currently or intertemporally, will guarantee inefficient depletion of
value. [14]
What will be the pattern of results if the collective decision
authority, in each separate period, is lodged in a single simple
majority coalition, any such coalition that is organized? Consider the
position of a person who finds himself a member of an initial coalition,
who thereby has a claim to a symmetric share of any surplus value
generated during that period by applying units of the complementary
resource inputs to the commons. He knows that, in each and every
subsequent electoral period, a differing majority may be decisive, but
he knows that there is some probability that he will be a member of such
a majority in any designated period.
But how will a member of the majority coalition incorporate
interperiod externalities into a rational calculus? It seems clear that
some share of the intertemporal externalities will be internalized. On
the other hand, because only a share of the intertemporal
interdependencies will be internalized, the level of usage will be
higher for the initial periods than that which would emerge under
permanent location of decision authority. The value of the commonly used
facility will, to an extent, be "mined" through early period
excess usage. The precise relationships will, of course, depend on the
importance of the intertemporal relative to the intratemporal
externalities.
The usage decision can be formulated similarly to the algebraic
model introduced in section III. As an illustration, consider a commons
that lasts two periods; steers need two periods to mature, and usage
(and value distribution) is lodged in sequential majorities. The
sequential interaction is analogous to the Stackelberg duopoly. The
reference member of the first majority coalition chooses [X.sub.1] to
maximize the effective rents,
(4) Maximize (K - [X.sub.1] - [X.sub.2])[X.sub.1] + [hV.sub.2],
where h = 0.5 is the probability that the reference person will
belong to the second majority coalition, and [V.sub.2] is the surplus
that a new coalition will enjoy. Given [X.sub.1], the rent is
(5) [V.sub.2]([X.sub.1]) = Max (K - [X.sub.1] -
[X.sub.2])[X.sub.2],
where [X.sub.2] is the choice variable for a new majority. Solving
the maximization in (5), we obtain the usage and rents as a function of
[X.sub.1]:
(6) [X.sub.2]([X.sub.1]) = (K - [X.sub.1])/2
[V.sub.2]([X.sub.1]) = [[(K - [X.sub.1])/2].sup.2].
Substituting the results into (4), we solve recursively: [X.sub.1]
= 3K/7 and [X.sub.2] = 2K/7. The total usage (2K/3) is higher than the
case of permanent ownership (K/2) and also higher than that of two
simultaneous majorities (4K/7). This result is equivalent to the
Cournot doupoly analogue that was analyzed in section III. In the
Stackelberg game analyzed here, the leader internalizes the response of
the follower in productivity externality. As the leader increases usage
rate, half of his gain is transferred from the follower, and this
transfer is one-half of the loss to the follower. But the membership
externality internalizes half of the loss from the follower. The gain
and loss will cancel each other out, and the leader behaves like an
independent simultaneous duopolist.
These results may be generalized to models that embody more than
single choices within each period. As the earlier analysis demonstrated,
increases in the number of authorities in any single period will
increase the rate of overutilization of the common resource. If we
introduce temporal elements in usage, the overusage in any given period,
with the number of decision authorities fixed, will further increase
value dissipation.
VII. GENERALIZATIONS AND CONCLUSIONS
We have analyzed the usage of a commons with differing institutions
of decision making, with particular emphasis on collective management
under majority decision rules. Even within this set, we have not fully
exhausted all possible structures, but perhaps the analyses have been
sufficiently extensive to suggest further developments. Also, we have
not, even for the particular models examined, fully developed the formal
analyses that might add rigor to the comparative treatment.
We have not attempted to identify those settings in which
collectivized management of commonly shared resources seems more likely
to emerge than the more familiar privatization alternatives. One set of
relevant examples here might be those situations where "the
commons" itself is not normally considered as an economic resource.
Geographic location offers the obvious example of the island of Bali,
where separable private ownership of land parcels may generate results
akin to the familiar "tragedy," measured in lost opportunity
value.
Buchanan: Advisory General Director, Center for Study of Public
Choice, MSNIE6, Buchanan House, George Mason University, 4400 University
Drive, Fairfax, VA 22030. Phone 1-703-993-2327, Fax 1-703-993-2334,
E-mail jburgess@gmu.edu
Yoon: Senior Research Associate, Center for Study of Public Choice,
George Mason University, 4400 University Drive, Fairfax, VA 22030. Phone
1-703-993-2332, Fax 1-703-993-2334, E-mail yyoon@gmu.edu
(*.) Helpful comments on earlier drafts were offered by Roger
Congleton, Tyler Cowen, Robert Tollison, Elinor Ostrom. and anonymous
referees.
(1.) The issues have been central in the development of welfare
economics for almost a century, especially since Pigou's analysis
of decreasing returns industries, along with early criticisms. See Pigou
(1912, 1920), and Knight (1924). The specific theory of common property
resource management received seminal treatment in papers by Gordon
(1954) and Scott (1955). The term tragedy of the commons was introduced
by Hardin (1968). Ostrom (1990) fully discussed the literature and, in
particular, examines alternative institutional means through which
common property resources have been, in fact, managed.
(2.) With a linear relationship, [Q.sup.*] = 2[Q.sub.m]. Full
dissipation (at [Q.sup.*]) is reached at a position where [Q.sup.*]
[greater than] 2[Q.sub.m] when the productivity curves are concave
upward and vice versa.
(3.) A partial exception is provided by some analyses of management
of local commons which discuss self-governance by asymmetrically
situated users. See Ostrom and Gardner (1993) and Seabright (1993).
(4.) We assume that Coase-like contracts between the parties are,
for some reason, impracticable. There will, of course, exist mutual
gains from such contracts that, if implemented, will generate the
efficient result.
(5.) Moulin (1995) and Watts (1996) offer analyses of the classic
commons model as analogous to Cournot-Nash oligopoly. Levhari and Mirman
(1980) use the Cournot-Nash model to analyze intertemporal usage of a
fishing stock with natural growth. Gardner et al. (1992) derive the
symmetric Nash equilibrium in commons usage in game theory formulation.
(6.) For a nonlinear production function, a unique Nash equilibrium
still exists if revenue is a strictly increasing concave function. See
corollary 1 in Watts (1996).
(7.) In any stylized open-access equilibrium, a finite number of
users will exist. If these users are assigned definitive rights of
usage, to the exclusion of potential entrants, some reduction in usage
will occur because of internalization of production externalities. In
addition, incentives will be established for the emergence of pairwise
exchanges of usage rights between sets of users. Both effects reduce
overusage. A practical example is offered by the Icelandic fishing
industry. Overinvestment in boats generated overfishing with no net
returns. A proposal to assign rights exclusively to current boat owners
was politically unacceptable because of an unwillingness to allow
current owner to secure the positive rents promised by reduction in
fleet size. This information is supplied by Dr. Hannes Gissurarson,
University of Iceland, occasional consultant to the fishing industry.
(8.) See Walker et al. (1997) for an interesting experiment on
collective management of a commons under varying decision rules. The
experiment was limited to the single-choice setting, and the focus of
interest is on convergence toward efficiency in usage under majority
rule and unanimity.
(9.) The relationship here is fully analogous to that between
"external costs" and the size of the decision-making
coalition, as analyzed in Buchanan and Tullock (1962). Their analyses
were not, however, placed in the common property setting as such.
(10.) See Wagner (1992).
(11.) The model becomes analogous to an interesting variant of the
Cournot-Nash duopoly setting in which the single owner of one firm has a
one-half probability of being the owner of the second firm.
(12.) We may treat the problem as being analogous to an oligopoly
setting in which the owner of a single firm has a one-half probability
of being the owner of any other firm. See Appendix 1 for further
discussion on the one-half probability.
(13.) A direct proof can be obtained by using equation (3). If h
equals 0.5 in equation (3), then as m grows without bound, X(0.5,
[infinity]) = 2K/3. For a Cournot duopoly, h = 0 and m = 2, and X(0, 2)
= 2K/3. Appendix 2 provides a general proof.
(14.) Aizenman (1992) formulates an intertemporal commons model
with reference to separate national issuing authorities in a monetary
union.
REFERENCES
Aizenman, J. "Competitive Externalities and the Optimal
Seigniorage." Journal of Money, Credit, and Banking, 24(1), 1992,
61-71.
Buchanan, J. M., and G. Tullock. The Calculus of Consent: Logical
Foundations of Constitutional Democracy. Ann Arbor: University of
Michigan Press, 1962.
Gardner, R., E. Ostrom, and J. Walker. "Covenants with and
without a Sword: Self-governance Is Possible." American Political
Science Review, 86, 1992, 404-17.
Gordon, H. S. "The Economic Theory of a Common-Property
Resource: The Fishery." Journal of Political Economy, 62, 1954,
124-42.
Hardin, G. "The Tragedy of the Commons." Science, 162,
1968, 1243-48.
Knight, F. H. "Some Fallacies in the Interpretation of Social
Cost." Quarterly Journal of Economics, 38, 1924, 582-606.
Levhari, D., and L. Mirman. "The Great Fish War: An Example
Using a Dynamic Cournot-Nash Solution." Bell Journal of Economics,
11, 1980, 322-34.
Moulin, H. Cooperative Microeconomics: A GameTheoretic
Introduction. Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1995.
Ostrom, E. Governing the Commons: The Evolution of Institutions for
Collective Action. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1990.
Ostrom, E., and R. Gardner. "Coping with Asymmetries in the
Commons: Self-Governing Irrigation Systems Can Work." Journal of
Economic Perspectives, 7(4), 1993, 93-112.
Pigou, A. C. Wealth and Welfare. London: Macmillan, 1912.
-----. The Economics of Welfare. London: Macmillan, 1920.
Scott, A. D. "The Fishery: The Objectives of Sole
Ownership." Journal of Political Economy, 63, 1955, 116-24.
Seabright, P. "Managing Local Commons: Theoretical Issues in
Incentive Design." Journal of Economic Perspectives, 7(4), 1993,
113-34.
Wagner, R. "Grazing the Federal Budgetary Commons: The
Rational Politics of Budgetary Irresponsibility." Journal of Law
and Politics, 9,1992, 105-19.
Walker, J., R. Gardner, A. Herr, and E. Ostrom. "Collective
Choice in the Commons: Experimental Results on Proposed Allocation Rules
and Votes." Working paper, Workshop in Political Theory and Policy
Analysis, Indiana University, 1997.
Watts, A. "On the Uniqueness of Equilibrium in Cournot
Oligopoly and Other Games." Games and Economic Behavior, 13, 1996,
269-85.
APPENDIX A
PROBABILITY OF MEMBERSHIP
For a reference person of the current coalition, the probability of
becoming a member of other majority coalitions depends on the size of
polity. For instance, for a five-member polity, a majority coalition
requires three persons, and there are ten possible coalitions in total:
C(5,3) = (5 x 4 x 3)/(3!) = 10. A reference person belongs to six
coalitions: C(4, 2) = 6. Thus, the probability for him to belong to
other coalitions is (6-1)/(10-1) =5/9 [greater than] 0.5.
As the size of polity increases, however, the probability converges
on one-half. Let 2m + 1 be the number of polity, then the number of
possible majority coalitions is equal to the number of different ways of
choosing m + 1 out of 2m + 1 members
C(2m +1, m +1) = C(2m +1, m) = P(2m +1, m)/m!,
where P(2m + 1, m) is the permutation of ordering m out of 2m+1
objects, and the m factorial, m!, is, m times (m - 1) times (m - 2), and
so on, until 1. The formula for permutation is
P(n,r) = n(n-1)...(n-r+1).
The number of majority coalitions of which the reference person of
the current coalition becomes a member is
C(2m, m) = P(2m, m)/m!,
and the probability, p, of this person becoming a member of another
majority coalition is p = [C(2m, m) - 1]/[C(2m + 1, m + 1) - 1].
Approximately,
p = C(2m, m)/C(2m + 1, m +1)
= (m + 1)P(2m, m)/P(2m +1, m +1)
= (m + 1)(2m)(2m - 1)... (2m - m + 1)
/(2m + 1).. . (m + 1)
= (m+1)/(2m+1),
which converges to one-half in the limit.
APPENDIX B
MANY MAJORITY COALITIONS ARE ANALOGOUS TO COURNOT DUOPOLY
In the text we consider the scenario in which different majority
coalitions are authorized to make usage decisions separately. Each
person in a majority coalition recognizes that, with probability
one-half, she will be a member of every other possible coalition. (See
Appendix A, where the one-half probability is discussed.) The reference
person will rationally internalize one-half of the negative external
effect caused by marginal extension of usage. We show that, in the
limit, the reference person behaves analogously to a duopolist in the
symmetric Cournot-Nash solution.
Majority Coalitions
Let P(X) denote the average product when aggregate usage is X. Each
coalition, say coalition 1, tries to maximize the revenue P(X)([X.sub.1]
+ X'/2) where [X.sub.i] denotes usage rates by coalition i and
X' = X - [X.sub.1] = [X.sub.2] + ... + [X.sub.m]. The first-order
condition is
(B1) P(X)[dX.sub.1] + (X/2 + [X.sub.1]/2)dP = 0.
Marginal change in [X.sub.1] causes changes in the average product
P through aggregate usage X. The external effect, caused by a marginal
change [dX.sub.1], is XdP and is denoted by dE : dE = XdP. Then the
first-order condition in the symmetric equilibrium becomes
(B2) P(X)[dX.sub.1] + dE/2 + dE/(2m) = 0,
where the second term, dE/2, is the membership externality, and the
third term, dE/(2m), is the productivity externality. Both are
internalized for allocation decision.
For large number m, less and less productivity externalities are
internalized and, in the limit, the first-order condition becomes
(B3) P(X)[dX.sub.1] + dE/2 = 0.
Cournot Duopoly
We interpret the average product function above as the demand
relation faced by the duopolists. Quantity demand is X and P(X) is the
price. A duopolist tries to maximize her surplus, P(X)[X.sub.1], where X
= [X.sub.1] + [X.sub.2], and the first-order condition is P(X)[dX.sub.1]
+ [X.sub.1]dP = 0. In a symmetric equilibrium, [X.sub.1] = X/2 and the
first-order condition will satisfy
(B4) P(X)[dX.sub.1] + (X/2)dP = P(X)[dX.sub.1] + dE/2 = 0.
The duopolist internalizes the productivity externality dE/2.
The first-order conditions (B.3) and (B.4) assume the identical
form, and it is no surprise that they imply analogous behavior.
[Graph omitted]