Payoff effects in information cascade experiments.
Anderson, Lisa R.
LISA R. ANDERSON (*)
I. INTRODUCTION
This article examines payoff effects in "information
cascade" experiments. (1) Cascade experiments provide a unique
environment to study errors because decisions are made publicly and in
sequence, allowing people to learn from the decisions of others.
However, there are no payoff interdependencies, so subjects are only
concerned with maximizing their own expected payoffs which cannot be
directly affected by the actions of others. This feature simplifies the
analysis of the decision making process and makes it possible to focus
more clearly on how subjects draw inferences from public decisions.
Furthermore, errors are recursive in the sense that mistakes made by
initial decision makers influence the decisions of those that come later
in the sequence. This study focuses on learning and errors by analyzing
data econometrically in a logistic error model.
Econometric methods have gained popularity as a way to examine
errors in experimental data. Harless and Camerer (1994) present a
maximum likelihood estimation method to test the predictive power of
various utility theories using data from 23 different experiments.
McKelvey and Palfrey (1995 and 1998) use the logistic structure to
estimate error rates with data from a variety of games. Palfrey and
Prisbrey (1997) use a similar structure with a probit model to estimate
error rates in a public goods experiment. The analysis presented here
differs from these previous econometric studies of experimental data in
the following way: in this model, errors are analyzed in a sequential
structure so the errors of others must be taken into account, but there
is no strategic element in the decision making process.
This study expands on the error analysis presented in Anderson and
Holt (1997) by examining error rates under different payoff conditions.
Smith and Walker (1993a) present a model of decision making in which the
effort of contemplating a decision is balanced against potential gains
in payoffs. In addition, they survey the experimental literature in
economics and psychology addressing the issue of payoff effects, and
they find mixed results. Some studies report a decrease in error rates
as payoffs increase. Others show little difference in results under
payoff and no payoff treatments. However, there is a consensus that
higher payoffs reduce the variance of decisions from the predicted
Outcome. Testing their own theory in the context of a first price
auction experiment, Smith and Walker (1993b) report that the amount and
severity of error decreases as payoffs increase. Interestingly, behavior
is not random, even when there is no monetary reward for a correct
decision. Using data from lottery choice experiments , Wilcox (1993)
finds that higher monetary payoffs affect behavior in complex
situations, but not in relatively simple decision making environments.
Harless and Camerer (1994) use econometric methods to compare error
rates in experiments with real losses to those with hypothetical losses.
They find that error rates are lower and variances are reduced in data
with real losses.
This article adds to the literature on the saliency of rewards by
analyzing behavior in a different experimental framework and by using
the logistic model to generate econometric estimates of error rates
under no payoff, payoff, and double payoff conditions. The underlying
behavioral model is an extension of the cascade model presented in
Bikhchandani, Hirshleifer, and Welch (1992). Experimental procedures are
discussed in section II. Section III discusses econometric details.
Section IV reports results and section V concludes.
II. PROCEDURES (2)
For each session of this experiment, seven subjects were recruited
from undergraduate economics courses at the University of Virginia. One
subject was randomly chosen to be a monitor, and the remaining six
subjects were decision markers. At the beginning of each period, the
monitor threw a six-sided die to determine which of two urns was to be
used for that period. If the throw of the die was 1, 2, or 3, urn A,
which contained two a marbles and one b marble, was used. Otherwise urn
B, which contained one a marble and two b marbles, was used. (3) After
the die throw, the monitor placed the contents of the appropriate urn in
an unmarked container. Subjects were chosen in a random order to see one
private draw from the container, with replacement. After seeing a
private draw, the subject would record it and make a decision, which was
a prediction about what urn was being used for the period. This
prediction, but not the signal, was announced out loud once it was made.
Hence, each subject knew his or her own priv ate draw and all previous
decisions, if any, before making a decision. Once all subjects made
decisions, the monitor announced which urn had been used and the period
ended. This process was repeated 15 times with each group of six
subjects.
Nine sessions of the experiment were conducted, involving a total
of 54 decision makers. Three sessions were conducted for each of the
three payoff treatments summarized in Table 1. Notice from table 1 that
in each treatment subjects were paid $5 for showing up for the
experiment. In the no payoff treatment, subjects were told that they
would all be paid $20 at the end of the experiment. In the payoff and
double payoff treatments, earnings varied depending on the accuracy of
predictions. Earnings for the $2 treatment (including the $5 for showing
up) averaged $24.54. (4) In the double payoff treatment, subjects were
paid $4 for a correct prediction, in addition to the $5 show-up fee, and
earnings averaged $45.39.
III. ECONOMETRIC DETAILS
Information cascades are defined as patterns of decisions that are
both consistent with Bayes' rule and inconsistent with private
information. To identify cascades in the experimental data, posterior probabilities must be calculated for each decision made. Further, since
decisions are made in sequence and the underlying model assumes that
people can make errors, the calculation of posteriors requires a
consideration of the error distribution for all previous rounds. (5)
Hence, the econometric model specifies that decisions made in any given
round depend on the error distributions for all previous rounds. (6)
Additionally, the econometric analysis is structured in such a way that
the error distribution that determines beliefs is used to calculate
expected payoffs, and errors are more likely when expected payoffs for
the two decisions are not too different. This feature of the model is
consistent with the decision cost explanation for errors proposed by
Smith and Walker (1993a).
Since errors are assumed to be logistically distributed, the
probability that a subject's decision in round i is urn A, denoted
[D.sub.i] = A, can be expressed in terms of the logistic error function:
(1) Pr([D.sub.i] = A)
=({exp[[lambda]([[pi].sup.A.sub.i] - [[pi].sup.B.sub.i])]}
/{1 + exp[[lambda]([[pi].sup.A.sub.i] - [[pi].sup.B.sub.i]]})
where [[pi].sup.A.sub.i] is the expected payoff for choosing urn A,
[[pi].sup.B.sub.i] is the expected payoff for choosing urn B and
[lambda] is a precision parameter. Notice that [lambda] 0 implies that
the Pr([D.sub.i] = A = 1/2. This complete randomization is the most
severe form of decision error. At the other extreme, with [lambda] =
[infinity] the Pr([D.sub.i] = A) = 0 if [[pi].sup.A.sub.i] <
[[pi].sup.B.sub.i], and the Pr([D.sub.i] = A) = if [[pi].sup.A.sub.i]
> [[pi].sup.B.sub.i]. Hence, [lambda] = [infinity] implies that there
is no decision error.
=(1/{1 + exp[-[lambda]([[pi].sup.A.sub.i] - [[pi].sup.B.sub.i])]})
Also notice from equation (1) that a subject's decision
depends on the difference in the expected payoffs for the two decisions:
(2) [[pi].sup.A.sub.i] - [[pi].sup.B.sub.i] = [R.sup.*] [P.sub.i] -
[R.sup.*](1 - [P.sub.i]) = [R.sup.*](2[P.sub.i] - 1)
where R is the payoff for a correct decision and [P.sub.i] is the
posterior probability of urn A. Error rates are estimated for each of
the three payoff conditions (R = 0, 2, 4), using the difference in
probabilities (2[P.sub.i] - 1) as the explanatory variable. Bayes'
rule is used to calculate the [P.sub.i]'s for every possible
combination of private signal and previous decisions. For example, there
are two possible values of private signal (a or b) that round one
decision makers use to calculate [P.sub.i], there are four possible
combinations of first rounds decisions and private signals that round
two decision makers use to calculate [P.sub.i], there are eight possible
combinations of first round decisions, second round decisions, and
private signals that round three decision makers use to calculate
[P.sub.i], etc.
The [lambda]'s are estimated using a maximum likelihood
routine in GAUSS. (7) The estimation is complicated by the fact that
[P.sub.i] depends on the [lambda]'s for all previous rounds.
Therefore, the independent variable, which is a function of [P.sub.i],
changes with different estimates of [lambda]. The estimation algorithm takes these interdependencies into account by defining [P.sub.i] as a
variable that depends on the individual's signal, previous
decisions, and [lambda]'s from previous rounds.
IV. RESULTS
Summary statistics from the estimation are presented in Table 2. In
one specification, [lambda] is constrained to be the same over all six
rounds of the experiment. These results are presented in the second
column of Table 2. In another specification, [lambda] is allowed to vary
over rounds. These results are listed in the remaining six columns of
Table 2. Likelihood ratio tests indicate that the restriction that
[lambda] is the same for all rounds cannot be rejected under any of the
three payoff conditions. Hence, the discussion that follows pertains to
the constrained [lambda]'s from Table 2.
All of the [lambda]'s are statistically significant,
indicating that the difference in probabilities alone is a significant
variable in determining a person's prediction. This suggests that
subjects attach some non-monetary value to making a correct prediction,
which is consistent with the finding of Smith and Walker (1993b).
Notice from the second column of Table 2 that [lambda] increases as
the payoff for a correct decision increases from $0 to $2, indicating
that the effect of a positive payoff is a reduction in decision error.
Also note that increasing the payoff from $2 to $4 has no significant
effect on the amount of decision error. This result is consistent with
Wilcox's (1993) finding that higher payoffs matter when decision
tasks are complex. The cascade setup is a relatively complex decision
making environment in the sense that inferences drawn from the decisions
of other people rely on assumptions about how those people processed
public and private information. Hence, adding some monetary incentive
increases interest in the problem and reduces error. However, the
problem is sufficiently complicated that doubling payoffs is not enough
to further reduce error rates.
The magnitude of the [lambda]'s from Table 2 translates into
decision probabilities in the following manner: there is an 81 percent
chance that a first round decision maker who sees a will predict urn A
in the no payoff treatment. This probability increases to 90 percent in
the payoff and double payoff treatments. These probabilities are listed
as information set 1 in Table 3 below.
Table 3 presents estimated values of the probability that a subject
will predict urn A using the [lambda]'s from Table 2. This table
demonstrates how these error rates affect decision probabilities for a
variety of information sets (private signal, [s.sub.i], and observed
decisions, ([D.sub.i]'S) As noted above, information set 1
characterizes a first round decision maker who sees an a signal. Some
information sets in the table show sequences where the current decision
maker's signal matches previous decisions (e.g., A, A, a), and
other examples show sequences where the current decision maker's
signal differs from the previous pattern of decisions (e.g., A, A, b).
Also, some sequences show all conforming decisions (e.g., A, A, A) and
others include deviations from the established pattern (e.g., A, A, B).
Notice that differences in decision probabilities across the three
payoff conditions are relatively small when the private signal matches a
series of observed decisions. With information set 6, the first three
decision makers predict urn A and the fourth decision maker sees an a
signal. In this case, the private signal confirms previous predictions,
suggesting that errors are less likely to have occurred. With this
combination of information, subjects in the no payoff condition predict
urn A 95 percent of the time and subjects in the payoff conditions
predict urn A 99 percent of the time.
Alternatively, when private information differs from a relatively
long sequence of conforming decisions, error rates have a more
pronounced effect on decisions. When the first three decision makers
predict A and the fourth decision maker sees a b signal (information set
7), subjects in one of the payoff treatments are 10 percentage points
more likely to predict urn A than subjects in the no payoff treatment
(72% vs. 62%). Since errors are more likely to occur in the no payoff
treatment, the previous A decisions contribute less to the posterior.
Therefore, a person observing a b signal under the no payoff treatment
has a lower posterior for A than a similar person in one of the payoff
treatments.
Table 4 shows some actual patterns of signals and decisions from
session 6 of the experiment, in which subjects were paid $2 for a
correct prediction and $0 otherwise. The estimated probabilities that
are reported in this table were calculated with the constrained [lambda]
for the $2 treatment in Table 2. In the first period of session 6 the
first round decision maker, subject S31, saw an a signal and predicted
urn A. The second round decision maker, subject S32, saw a b signal and
predicted urn B. Without decision error, the posterior probability for
urn A, with an inferred a signal and an observed b signal, is .50 for
subject S32. However, the possibility for error discounts the inferred
information, resulting in an estimated probability of .46 < .50 for
the second round decision maker. The third round decision maker saw an a
signal and predicted A. The fourth decision maker saw a private b
signal, and the combination of information resulted in an estimated
Bayesian posterior of .45 for A. However, this per son predicted urn A,
which was inconsistent with private information and with Bayes'
rule. These decisions are labeled ** mistakes. The sixth decision maker
in period 1 had a posterior of .57 for urn A but predicted that urn B
was being used. However, this was consistent with private information.
Decisions that are consistent with private information but inconsistent
with Bayes' rule are labeled * mistakes.
The first three decision makers in period 2 saw b signals and
predicted urn B. These decisions were consistent with Bayes' rule
and with private information. The last three decision makers in this
round saw a signals but predicted urn B. Each of these predictions was
consistent with Bayes' rule but inconsistent with private
information. These shaded decisions were part of an information cascade
started by the early conforming decisions. An incorrect cascade formed
in period 3 as the first two decision makers were unlucky to see b
signals when urn A was actually being used for the draws.
Results from all nine sessions are summarized in Table 5. The
second column of Table 5 lists the number of decisions that are
inconsistent with both Bayes; rule and private information (**
mistakes). There are 14 ** mistakes in both the $2 and the $4 payoff
treatments and exactly twice as many in the no payoff treatment. The
third column shows the number of decisions that are consistent with
private information but inconsistent with Bayes' rule (* mistakes).
There are 13 and 11 of these mistakes in the $2 and $4 treatments,
respectively, and 23 of these mistakes in the no payoff treatment.
Finally, the fourth column of Table 5 reports the number of cascade
decisions make under each payoff treatment and the percentage of cascade
decisions made when the combination of observed predictions and private
draw made a cascade decision possible. For example, under the no payoff
treatment, there were 41 cases where the optimal (Bayesian) decision
differed from a decision based solely on private information. In 18 of
th ose 41 cases (44%), the person made a decision that was consistent
with Bayes' rule.
Since a decision in the cascade experiment is constrained to be an
A or B prediction, the variance of errors is not directly comparable to
variances in experiments in which subjects choose from a range of
numbers (e.g., choosing a bid in an auction experiment). However, since
large deviations from optimal behavior are generally more costly than
small deviations, variations from optimal behavior can be analyzed in
terms of how costly they are in expected payoffs. As discussed above,
with posteriors close to 50 percent, errors are less costly than when
there are big differences in the posteriors for urn A and urn B. Table 6
reports the number of errors by payoff rate for five ranges of Bayesian
posteriors. In all three payoff conditions, over half of the mistakes
were made when the posterior for the more likely event (urn A or urn B)
was between 51 and 60 percent. At the other extreme, no subject failed
to predict an urn when its Bayesian posterior was higher than 90
percent. In the intermediate ranges, there i s no consistent pattern of
results. In the 71-90 percent range more errors were made in the no
payoff treatment than in the payoff treatments. However, the percent of
total errors made in the intermediate ranges was highest for the $4
payoff treatment. This suggests that increasing payoffs in this context
does not have the strong effect on the variance of errors that has been
documented in other experiments.
V. SUMMARY
In this article error rates are estimated econometrically using a
logistic error structure that highlights the impact of decision error in
early rounds on subsequent decisions. Further, error rates are compared
under three different payoff conditions. Results are consistent with
early theoretical and experimental studies of decision costs and payoff
effects. The data reveal that a no (variable) payoff condition results
in more decision error than two payoff conditions. Under the assumption
that people use Bayes' rule to form posterior probabilities,
previous public decisions are less informative when the possibility of
decision error is higher. Once a cascade starts, deviant decisions are
informative in the sense that they are more likely to reveal a
person's private information. However, deviant decisions are also
less informative in the no payoff condition since decision error is
higher.
Anderson: Assistant Professor, Department of Economics, The College
of William and Mary, Williamsburg, VA 23187-8795. Phone 1-757-221-2359,
Fax 1-757-221-2390, E-mail lrande@wm.edu
(*.) This research was supported in part by grants from the
National Science Foundation (SES 9320617 and SES 9709530). I wish to
thank (without implicating) Charles Holt, Roger Sherman, Sarah Stafford,
Steven Stern, Chris Swann, and two anonymous referees for helpful
suggestions.
(1.) Information cascades are discussed extensively in
Bikhchandani, Hirshleifer, and Welch (1992) and Anderson and Holt
(1997).
(2.) A more detailed description of procedures and a copy of the
instructions can be found in Anderson and Holt (1997). The notable
differences between the two experiments are that there are no public
draws and payoff conditions vary in the experiment discussed here.
(3.) The marbles were actually called light and dark in the
experiment, but they will be referred to as a and b signals in this
article to facilitate discussion. The urns were actually cups marked
"Urn A" or "Urn B."
(4.) The fixed payment in the no payoff treatment was set at $20 so
that average earnings were approximately the same for the no payoff and
payoff treatments.
(5.) This calculation is described in Anderson (1994).
(6.) The estimation described in this section is an extension of
the analysis in Chapter 7 of Anderson (1994), which is reported in
Anderson and Holt (1997).
(7.) The estimation program is available from the author upon
request.
REFERENCES
Anderson, L. R. "Information Cascades." Ph.D. diss.,
University of Virginia, 1994.
Anderson, L. R., and C. A. Holt. "Information Cascades in the
Laboratory." American Economic Review, 87(5), 1997, 847-62.
Bikhchandani, S., D. Hirshleifer, and I. Welch. "A Theory of
Fads, Fashion, Custom, and Cultural Change as Informational
Cascades." Journal of Political Economy, 100(5), 1992, 992-1026.
Harless, D. W., and C. F. Camerer. "The Predictive Utility of
Generalized Expected Utility Theories." Econometrica, 62(6), 1994,
1251-89.
McKelvey, R. D., and T. R. Palfrey. "Quantal Response
Equilibria for Extensive Form Games." Experimental Economics, 1(1),
1998, 1-41.
-----. "Quantal Response Equilibria for Normal Form
Games." Games and Economic Behavior, 10(1), 1995, 6-38.
Palfrey, T. R., and J. E. Prisbrey. "Anomalous Behavior in
Linear Public Goods Experiments: How Much and Why?" American
Economic Review, 87(5), 1997, 829-46.
Smith, V. L., and J. M. Walker. "Monetary Rewards and Decision
Cost in Experimental Economics." Economic Inquiry, 31(2), 1993a,
245-61.
-----. "Rewards, Experience, and Decision Costs in First Price
Auctions." Economic Inquiry, 31(2), 1993b, 237-45.
Wilcox, N. T. "Lottery Choice: Incentives, Complexity and
Decision Time." Economic Journal, 103(421), 1993, 1397-1417.
TABLE 1
Payoff Treatments
Payment for
Payoff Number of Payment for a Correct Fixed Average
Treatment Sessions Showing Up Decision Payment Earnings
No payoff 3 $5 $0 $20 $25.00
Payoff 3 $5 $2 $0 $24.54
Double payoff 3 $5 $4 $0 $45.39
TABLE 2
Econometric Results
[lambda] by Round
Payoff for (Standard Errors)
a Correct Constrained [lambda]
Decision (Standard Errors) 1 2
$0 4.47 5.59 5.50
(.44) (1.36) (1.59)
$2 6.59 4.73 10.60
(.71) (1.01) (2.83)
$4 6.25 4.88 5.38
(.61) (1.10) (1.15)
[lambda] by Round
Payoff for (Standard Errors)
a Correct
Decision 3 4 5 6
$0 6.09 3.61 3.52 3.88
(1.86) (.96) (.97) (1.02)
$2 11.83 4.01 5.90 8.45
(3.86) (1.13) (1.80) (2.96)
$4 11.08 16.13 4.95 6.99
(4.62) (7.72) (1.25) (2.09)
TABLE 3
Probability Decision Is A for Selected Combinations of Information
Available Information
Information
Set [D.sub.1] [D.sub.2] [D.sub.3] [s.sub.1]
1 a
2 A
3 A
4 A A
5 A A
6 A A A
7 A A A
8 A A B
9 A A B
Available Information
Information
Set [s.sub.2] [s.sub.3] [s.sub.4]
1
2 a
3 b
4 a
5 b
6 a
7 b
8 a
9 b
Probability Decision Is A
Information $2 Payoff &
Set $0 Payoff $4 Payoff
1 .81 .90
2 .92 .97
3 .36 .38
4 .94 .98
5 .56 .61
6 .95 .99
7 .62 .72
8 .87 .94
9 .25 .17
TABLE 4
Data for Selected Periods of Session 6
Subject Number: Urn Decision
(Private Draw, Estimated
Probability of Ura A)
Urn 1st 2nd 3rd
Pd Used Round Round Round
1 B S31:A S32:B S33:A
(a, .67) (b, .46) (a, .65)
2 B S35:B S36:B S34:B
(b, .33) (b, .22) (b, .18)
3 A S32:B S33:B S3:B
(b, .33) (b, .22) (a, .46)
Subject Number: Urn Decision
(Private Draw, Estimated
Probability of Ura A)
4th 5th 6th Cascade
Pd Round Round Round Outcome
1 S34:A (**) S35:A S36:B (*)
(b, .45) (a, .82) (b, .57)
2 S32:B S33:B S31:B cascade
(a, .43) (a, .40) (a, .38)
3 S34:B S35:B S31:B incorrect
(b, .16) (b, .14) (b, .13) cascade
Note: Shading: Bayesian decision, inconsistent with private information.
(*)Decision based on private information, inconsistent with Bayesian
updating.
(**)Decision inconsistent with Bayes' rule and private information.
TABLE 5
Errors and Casade Decisions
Payoff for a
Correct (**) (*) Cascade
Decision Mistake Mistake Decisions
$0 28 23 18 (44%)
$2 14 13 30 (70%)
$4 14 11 40 (78%)
Notes: (*)mistake: Decision based on private information inconsistent
with Bayesian updating.
(**)mistake: Decision inconsistent with Bayes' rule and private
information.
Cascade decision: Decision consistent with Bayes' rule but inconsistent
with private information.
TABLE 6
Severity of Errors
Bayesian Posterior Number of Errors
of More Likely by Payoff Rate
Event (Urn A (Percent of Total)
or Urn B) $0 $2 $4
51-60% 32 18 14
(63%) (67%) (56%)
61-70% 9 7 6
(17%) (26%) (24%)
71-80% 6 2 4
(12%) (7%) (16%)
81-90% 4 0 1
(8%) (0%) (4%)
91-100% 0 0 0
(0%) (0%) (0%)