Strategic groups and rent dissipation.
Baik, Kyung Hwan ; Lee, Sanghack
SANGHACK LEE (*)
I. INTRODUCTION
A rent-seeking contest is a situation in which players compete with
one another by expending outlays to win a rent. Examples abound. When a
positive monopoly rent is secured under government protection, firms
lobby to win the monopoly. When governmental decisions to establish
tariffs or other trade barriers create rents, firms compete to capture
these rents. Firms compete to acquire a rent generated by rights of
ownership to an import quota. Firms compete to obtain a rent generated
by a government procurement contract.
Beginning with the seminal work of Tullock (1967), the early
literature on rent seeking has concentrated on individual rent
seeking--that is, contests in which players compete individually to win
the rent. This includes, for example, Krueger (1974), Posner (1975),
Tullock (1980), Hillman and Katz (1984), Appelbaum and Katz (1987),
Hillman and Riley (1989), Hirshleifer (1989), Leininger (1993), and
Hurley and Shogren (1998). (1)
Recently, several economists have studied collective rent
seeking--that is, contests in which competition for the rent arises
among groups of players and the rent is awarded to a group. For example,
Nitzan (1991a, 1991b), Baik and Shogren (1995), Lee (1995), Hausken
(1995), and Baik and Lee (1997) study collective rent seeking with a
privategood rent. Katz et al. (1990), Ursprung (1990), Baik (1993), Riaz et al. (1995), Katz and Tokatlidu (1996), and Baik et al. (2001) study
collective rent seeking with a group-specific public-good rent. A
salient feature of the rent-seeking contests in these articles is that
the players expend their outlays noncooperatively.
This article studies individual rent seeking with a private-good
rent. But unlike the previous work, we consider a rent-seeking contest
with endogenous group formation in which players can form groups before
they expend their outlays. (2) What type of groups do we consider? As we
will explain it in section II, if a group is formed and then a player in
that group wins the rent, the winner "shares" it with the
other players in that group. Examples of such groups may include
coalitions among firms, political parties, or interest groups, and
R&D joint ventures among firms. This article focuses on the
profitability of endogenous group formation and the effect of such group
formation on rent dissipation. Specifically, we consider a three-stage
game in which the players first decide whether to form groups, then the
players in each group decide how to share the rent if "they"
win it, and finally all the players in the contest expend their outlays
independently to win the rent. The rent is awarded to a single player.
Why do players form such groups? An intuitive explanation is that
each player wants to ensure against his failure in winning the rent--in
other words, he wants to share the risk of his failure with the other
players in his group. Or, as it will be clear in section II, each player
wants to make his prize bigger in case he becomes the winner. Another
explanation is that they can benefit by achieving strategic commitments
through such group formation: They can change their opponents'
behavior in their favor by using their sharing rule and treating members
differently from nonmembers. To highlight the idea of strategic group
formation, we call groups formed herein strategic groups. (3) We define
a strategic group as follows: (a) the players in each group first choose
their sharing rule--winner's fractional share--and then expend
their outlays noncooperatively; and (b) if a player in a group wins the
rent, the winner "shares" the rent with the other players in
that group according to the predetermined sharing rule . The players in
a strategic group do not need to know how much outlays their group
members expended, when they share the rent.
This article endogenizes the number of strategic groups, their
sizes, and their sharing rules. Defining an equilibrium as a situation
in which no payoff-increasing individual move-in or move-out is
possible, we obtain the number of strategic groups and their sizes in
equilibrium. Given the number of players, the equilibrium number of
strategic groups is not unique. When just one strategic group is formed
in equilibrium, there may be players who do not belong to the single
strategic group and, for more than five players, the equilibrium group
size equals the smallest of integers greater than half the number of
players. When more than one strategic group is formed in equilibrium,
every player belongs to one of the groups and the difference in
equilibrium group size between any two groups is at most one.
Equilibrium winner's fractional share is less than one when just
one strategic group is formed, and is greater than one--the winner takes
all the rent and further receives "bounties" from the other
players in hi s group--for all the strategic groups when more than two
strategic groups are formed.
Examining the extent of rent dissipation is one of the main issues
in the literature on rent seeking. It is important because the
opportunity costs of resources expended on rent-seeking activities are
social costs and thus create economic inefficiency. Examining the
profitability of endogenous group formation and the effect of such group
formation on rent dissipation, we show the following. When just one
strategic group is formed in equilibrium, group formation is beneficial
both to the group members and to the nonmembers, and rent dissipation
(or total outlay) is smaller than with usual individual rent
seeking--that is, the social cost associated with rent seeking decreases
by such group formation. However, when more than two strategic groups
are formed in equilibrium, group formation is never profitable to any
players and rent dissipation is greater than with individual rent
seeking. We also show that total rent-seeking outlay is less than the
rent, regardless of the number of strategic groups formed.
This article is related to the literature on the noncooperative
theory of endogenous formation of coalitions--the literature that deals
with situations in which players first form coalitions and then, given
the coalition structure determined, engage in noncooperative
competition. Papers in this literature include Bloch (1995, 1996), Yi
(1996, 1997, 1998), Konishi et al. (1997), Belleflamme (2000), Yi and
Shin (2000), and Morasch (2000). They concentrate on examining the
equilibrium (or stable) structures of coalitions--the equilibrium
numbers and the sizes of coalitions--in models with various
applications. Bloch (1995), Yi (1998), Belleflamme (2000), and Yi and
Shin (2000) examine the equilibrium structures of associations (such as
R&D joint ventures) in oligopolies. Yi (1996) examines the
equilibrium structure of customs unions in a situation in which
countries can form customs unions freely. Morasch (2000) obtains the
equilibrium structures of strategic alliances of firms and, using them,
examines the loos e competition policy toward strategic alliances as an
alternative to the strategic trade policy. One main finding of these
articles is that the grand coalition is typically not an equilibrium
coalition structure, with the exception that, in the case where
coalition formation among symmetric players creates negative
externalities for nonmembers, the grand coalition is an equilibrium
coalition structure under the open membership rule--the rule that
stipulates that a coalition admit new members on a nondiscriminatory
basis. We obtain a similar result in this article: The grand coalition
never occurs if the number of players exceeds five.
The remainder of the article is organized as follows. In section
II, we develop the model and set up the three-stage game. In section
III, we solve a subgame that starts at the second stage of the
three-stage game. In this subgame, given the number of groups and their
sizes, the players in groups choose their winner's fractional
shares and then all the players in the contest expend their outlays. In
section IV, we analyze the first stage of our three-stage game and
thereby obtain the equilibrium numbers of strategic groups and
equilibrium group sizes. In section V, we compute the equilibrium
winner's fractional shares of the groups and examine the
profitability of endogenous group formation and the effect of such group
formation on rent dissipation. Finally, section VI offers our
conclusions.
II. THE MODEL
There are n risk-neutral players who want to win a fixed rent,
where n > 1. The rent is worth V and will be awarded to one of the
players. The probability that a player wins the rent is equal to his
outlay divided by the players' total outlay if the total outlay is
positive, and it is equal to 1/n if all the players expend zero. (4)
The players can form groups before they compete by expending
outlays. Groups formed are called strategic groups. We define a
strategic group as follows. Suppose that a group consists of m players,
where m is an integer and 1 < m [less than or equal to] n. The m
players write an agreement. The agreement specifies how much of the rent
the winner and the losers each will take, when a player in the group
wins the rent. Then all the players in the contest expend their outlays
noncooperatively. If a player in that group wins the rent, the winner
"shares" it with the other players in that group according to
the previously written agreement. We assume that the winning player
takes [sigma]V and each losing player "takes" (1 -
[sigma])V/(m - 1). The winner's fractional share, [sigma], is
assumed to be greater than or equal to 1/m. If [sigma] = 1/m holds, the
players in that group share the rent equally when a player in that group
wins it. In the case where 1/m [less than or equal to] [sigma] < 1,
the winner helps the o ther players in that group, and thus the prize to
the winner is less than the rent. When the winner's fractional
share is equal to unity, the winner takes all the rent. In the case
where [sigma] > 1, the winner takes all the rent and further receives
"bounties" from the other players in that group. Thus, in this
case, the prize to the winner is greater than the rent. We assume that
there is no transaction cost associated with organizing a strategic
group, negotiating an agreement, and enforcing compliance.
We formally consider the following three-stage game. In the first
stage, the players decide simultaneously and independently whether to
form strategic groups. (5) In the second stage, after knowing the number
of groups and their sizes, the players in each group make a binding
agreement that specifies how much of the rent the winner and the losers
each will take when a player in the group wins the rent. In doing so,
the players in each group set their winner's fractional share. Then
all the groups announce their choices simultaneously. Note that, because
the players in each group are identical, their decision on their
winner's fractional share is unanimous. In the third stage, after
knowing the number of groups, their sizes, and their winner's
fractional shares, all the players in the contest choose their outlays
simultaneously and independently. At the end of the third stage, the
winning player is chosen, and the winner "shares" the rent
with the other players in his group according to the agreement written i
n the second stage. We assume that all of this is common knowledge. We
employ subgame-perfect equilibrium as the solution concept.
III. EXPECTED PAYOFFS FOR THE PLAYERS GIVEN N STRATEGIC GROUPS
This section considers subgames which start at the second stage of
our three-stage game. Suppose that N strategic groups (1 through N) are
formed in the first stage, where N [greater than or equal to] 1. The
players who do not belong to any of these N groups are treated as those
in an imaginary strategic group (called group N + 1) whose winner's
fractional share is unity. Let [m.sub.i] denote the number of players in
group i. We have then n = [summation over (N+1/k=1)] [m.sub.k]. Without
loss of generality, assume that 1 < [m.sub.N] [less than or equal
to]...[less than or equal to] [m.sub.2] [less than or equal to]
[m.sub.1] and [m.sub.N+l] [greater than or equal to] 0.
Specifically, we consider the following subgame of our three-stage
game. In the second stage, given the number of groups, N + 1, and their
sizes, ([m.sub.1],..., [m.sub.N+1]), the players in groups 1 through N
choose their winner's fractional shares simultaneously and
independently. In the third stage, after learning the winner's
fractional shares of the N + 1 groups (including group N + 1) and the
size of each group, all the players in the contest choose their outlays
simultaneously and independently. At the end of the third stage, the
winner is chosen, and the winner "shares" the rent with the
other players in his group according to the agreement written in the
second stage. Note that we can view this subgame as a full game
resulting when the number of groups and their sizes are exogenously
given.
Lemma 1 describes the subgame-perfect equilibrium outcomes of the
subgame in the case where [m.sub.1] = n or, equivalently, N = 1 and
[m.sub.N+1] = 0.
LEMMA 1. In the case where [m.sub.1] = n, the equilibrium
winner's fractional share of group 1 is 1/n and each player's
equilibrium outlay is zero.
Proof. The brief proof of Lemma 1 follows. First recall that the
winner's fractional share of a group is assumed to be greater than
or equal to one divided by the number of players in the group. Hence, in
the case where [m.sub.1] = n, the winner's fractional share is
greater than or equal to 1/n. One can easily check the following. If
[sigma] = 1/n, then each player expends zero outlays and his payoff is
V/n. If [sigma] > 1/n, then each player's outlay is positive and
his expected payoff is less than V/n. Comparing these findings, we
obtain Lemma 1.
Lemma 1 shows that, if all the players in the contest belong to the
same group, they expend zero outlays and share the rent equally, whoever
wins it. Thus Lemma 1 implies that, if the grand coalition occurs, the
inefficiency problem associated with rent seeking disappears.
To solve for the subgame-perfect equilibrium of the subgame in the
case where [m.sub.1] < n, we work backward. (6) Let [[sigma].sub.i]
represent the winner's fractional share of group i. Let [x.sub.ij]
represent the irreversible rent-seeking outlay of player j in group i
and let [X.sub.i] represent group i's outlay. In the third stage,
Given ([m.sub.1],..., [m.sub.N+1] and an (N + 1)-tuple vector of
winner's fractional shares, player j in group I seeks to maximize
his expected payoff:
(1) [[pi].sub.ij] = ([[sigma].sub.i]V - [x.sub.ij])([x.sub.ij]/S) +
[(1 - [[sigma].sub.i])V/[m.sub.i] - 1) - [x.sub.ij]] X [([X.sub.i] -
[x.sub.ij])/S] + ([-x.sub.ij]) X [(S - [X.sub.i])/S] =
[[sigma].sub.i]V([x.sub.ij]/S) + [(1 - [[sigma].sub.i])V/([m.sub.i] -
1)] X [([X.sub.i] - [x.sub.ij])/S] - [x.sub.ij]
for j = 1,..., N,
and
[[pi].sub.ij] = V([x.sub.ij]/S) - [x.sub.ij] for i = N+1,
where S = [summation over (N+1/k=1)] [X.sub.k]. (7) In the payoff
functions, [x.sub.ij]/S is the probability that player j in group wins
the rent, ([X.sub.i] - [x.sub.ij])/S is the probability that any one of
the other players in group i wins the rent, and (S-[X.sub.i])/S is the
probability that any one of the other groups' players wins the
rent. Note that given S > 0, the probability that a player wins the
rent depends only on his own outlay, not on the group's outlay.
Given a positive outlay of the other players, the first-order condition for maximizing [[pi].sub.ij] yields
(2) [[sigma].sub.i]V(S - [x.sub.ij]) + (1 - [[sigma].sub.i]) x
V([x.sub.ij] - [X.sub.i])/([m.sub.i] - 1) = [S.sup.2]
for i = 1,..., N,
and
V(S - [x.sub.ij]) = [S.sup.2] for i N+1.
The second-order condition is satisfied. At the Nash equilibrium of
the third-stage subgame, the players in the same group expend the same
outlay. Denote the third-stage equilibrium outlay of each player in
group i by [x.sub.i], ([sigma], m), where [sigma] =
([[sigma].sub.1],...,[[sigma].sub.N+1]) and m = ([m.sub.1],...,
[m.sub.N+1]). Then, at the third-stage Nash equilibrium, equation (2)
reduces to (3):
(3) [[sigma].sub.i]VH - [V[x.sub.i]([sigma], m) = [H.sup.2]
for i = 1,..., N+1,
where H = [summation over (N+1/k=1)] [m.sub.k][x.sub.k]([sigma],
m). Note that equation (3) holds for i = N + 1 because [[sigma].sub.N+1]
= 1. Multiplying (3) through by [m.sub.i], we have
[[sigma].sub.i][m.sub.i]VH - [m.sub.i] V[x.sub.i]([sigma], m) =
[m.sub.i][H.sup.2]. Summing over all groups, we obtain [summation over
(N+1/k=1)] [[sigma].sub.k][m.sub.k]VH - [summation over (N+1/k=1)]
[m.sub.k]V[x.sub.k] ([sigma], m) = [summation over (N+1/k=1)]
[m.sub.k][H.sup.2]. This is simplified to VM - V = nH, where M =
[summation over (N+1/k=1)] [[sigma].sub.k][m.sub.k]. We have then
(4) H = V(M - 1)/n.
Substituting equation (4) into (3), we obtain the outlay of each
player in group i at the third-stage Nash equilibrium:
(5) [x.sub.i]([sigma], m) = V(M -1)
([[sigma].sub.i]n-M+1)/[n.sup.2].
Let [[pi].sub.i]([sigma], m) represent the expected payoff for each
player in group i at the third-stage Nash equilibrium. Then, using (1),
we obtain
(6) [[pi].sub.i]([sigma], m) = (V - H)[x.sub.i]([sigma], m)/H.
Substituting (4) and (5) into equation (6), we obtain
(7) [[pi].sub.i]([sigma], m) = V(n - M+1) x ([[sigma].sub.i]n -
M+1)/[n.sup.2].
Consider now the second stage in which the players in group i (in
this paragraph, i = 1,..., N) choose their winner's fractional
share. The N groups choose their winner's fractional shares
simultaneously and independently. Because the players in group i are
identical, the winner's fractional share that is
"optimal" for a player is also optimal for the other players
in the group. This implies that group i's decision on its
winner's fractional share is unanimous. In this stage, the players
in group i know that [[sigma].sub.N+1] = 1 and have perfect foresight about the third-stage competition. Given winner's fractional shares
of the other groups, the best response of group i is the winner's
fractional share that maximizes [[pi].sub.i] ([sigma], m) subject to
[[sigma].sub.i] [greater than or equal to] 1/[m.sub.i]. From the
first-order condition for maximizing (7), we obtain
(8) -[m.sub.i]([[sigma].sub.i]n - M + 1) + (n - M + 1)(n -
[m.sub.i] = 0.
It is easy to see that [[pi].sub.i]([sigma], m) is strictly concave in [[sigma].sub.i] and thus the second-order condition for maximizing
[[pi].sub.i]([sigma], m) is satisfied. Let [[sigma].sub.i](m) represent
group i's winner's fractional share, which is specified in the
subgame-perfect equilibrium. From the above N equations and the fact
that [[sigma].sub.N+1] = 1, we obtain group i's equilibrium
winner's fractional share [[sigma].sub.i](m).
LEMMA 2. In the case where [m.sub.1] < n, group i's
equilibrium winner's fractional share is [[sigma].sub.i](m) = 1 +
(n - 2[m.sub.i])/[m.sub.i][n(N - 1) + 2[m.sub.N+1] for i = 1, ... , N.
The winner's fractional share of group N+1 is defined above as
equal to unity.
Using Lemma 2, we find the following. First, group i's
equilibrium winner's fractional share is greater than 1/[m.sub.i],
(in this paragraph, i = 1, ... ,N). This can be explained as follows.
Equal sharing brings a serious free-rider problem and fails to induce group i's players to expend "optimal" outlays. Therefore,
facing the rival groups, the players in group i adopt a
"sharing" rule, which allows the winner to take more than the
equal share. Second, group i's equilibrium winner's fractional
share is less (greater) than unity if [m.sub.i] is greater (less) than
n/2. It is equal to unity if [m.sub.i] = n/2 holds. Because group 1 is
the largest of the N groups, we have the following. If [m.sub.1] >
n/2 holds, then group l's equilibrium winner's fractional
share is less than unity and the equilibrium winner's fractional
shares of groups 2 through N are greater than unity. Otherwise, all the
equilibrium winner's fractional shares are greater than or equal to
unity. Finally, two groups with the same number of players have the same
equilibrium winner's fractional share, and a smaller group has a
greater equilibrium winner's fractional share than a larger one: In
terms of the symbols, [[sigma].sub.1](m) [less than or equal to] ...
[less than or equal to] [[sigma].sub.N](m) holds.
Let [x.sub.i](m) represent the outlay of each player in group i in
the subgame-perfect equilibrium, [X.sub.i](m) group i's equilibrium
outlay, and H(m) the equilibrium total outla1y: [X.sub.i](m) =
[m.sub.i][x.sub.i](m) and H(m) = [summation over (N+1/k=1)] [X.sub.k](m)
= [summation over (n+1/k=1)][m.sub.k][X.sub.k](m). Using equation (5)
and Lemma 2, we obtain Lemma 3.
LEMMA 3. In the case where [m.sub.1] < n, the equilibrium
outlays of the individual players, those of the groups, and the
equilibrium total outlay are
[x.sub.i](m) = V[n(N-1)+[2m.sub.N+1]-1]
x(n-[m.sub.i])/[m.sub.i][[n(N-1)+2[m.sub.N+1].sup.2]
for i = 1,... ,N;
[x.sub.N+1](m) =
V[n(N-1)+[2m.sub.N+1]-1]/[[n(N-1)+2[m.sub.N+1].sup.2];
[X.sub.i](m) = V[n(N-1)+2[m.sub.N+1]-1]
x(n-[m.sub.i]/[[n(N-1)+[2m.sub.N+1].sup.2]
for i=1,..., N;
[X.sub.N+1](m) =
V[n(N-1)+2[m.sub.N+1]-1][m.sub.N+1]/[[n(N-1)+[2m.sub.N+1].sup.2];
and
H(m) = V{1-1/[n(N-1)+2[m.sub.N+1]}.
Using Lemma 3, we obtain the following. First, [x.sub.1](m) [less
than or equal to] ... [less than or equal to] [x.sub.N](m) and
[X.sub.1](m) [less than or equal to] ... [less than or equal to]
[X.sub.N](m) hold. It means that the players in a smaller group expend
more than those in a larger one. This is because a smaller group has a
greater winner's fractional share than a larger one, and therefore
the prize to the winner is greater in a smaller group than in a larger
one-in other words, the players in a smaller group are motivated more
than those in a larger one. Second, group i's individual outlay
[x.sub.i](m), for I = 1,... ,N, is less (greater) than [x.sub.N+1](m) if
[m.sub.i] is greater (less) than n/2. It is equal to [x.sub.N+1] (m) if
[m.sub.i], = n/2 holds. Because group 1 is the largest of the N groups,
if [m.sub.1] > n/2 holds, then group l's individual outlay is
less than [x.sub.N+1](m) and the individual outlays of groups 2 through
N are greater than [x.sub.N+1](m). Otherwise, all the individual outlays
are greater than or equal to [x.sub.N+1](m). Third, group i's
outlay [X.sub.i](m), for i = 1, ... , N, is greater than [X.sub.N+1](m)
if [m.sub.i] is less than n-[m.sub.N+1]. it is equal to [X.sub.N+1](m)
if [m.sub.i] is equal to n-[m.sub.N+1]. In other words, group i's
outlay is greater than [X.sub.N+1](m) if there is more than one
strategic group excluding group N + 1 (i.e., N > 1). It is equal to
[X.sub.N+1](m) if there are just two groups, including group N + 1
Finally, the equilibrium total outlay is less than the rent. Other
things being equal, as the number of groups, the number of players in
the contest, or [m.sub.N+1] increases, the equilibrium total outlay
increases.
Next, using equation (7), Lemmas 1 and 2, and the fact that
[[sigma].sub.N+1] = 1, we obtain Lemma 4, which describes each
player's expected payoff in the subgame-perfect equilibrium.
LEMMA 4. In the case where [m.sub.1] = n, the equilibrium expected
payoff for each player is V/n. In the case where [m.sub.1] < n, the
equilibrium expected payoff for each player in group i is
[[pi].sub.i](m) = V (n - [m.sub.i]/[m.sub.i][[n(N - 1)+
[2m.sub.N+1].sup.2]
for i = 1,... ,N
and
[[pi].sub.N+1](m) = V/[[n(N - 1)+[2m.sub.N+1].sup.2].
Lemma 4 shows that [[pi].sub.1](m) [less than or equal to] ...
[less than or equal to] [[pi].sub.N](m) holds. It means that the players
in a smaller group have greater equilibrium expected payoffs than those
in a larger one. Lemma 4 also shows that the equilibrium expected payoff
for each player in group i, for i = 1,... , N, is less (greater) than
that for each player in group N + 1 if [m.sub.i] is greater (less) than
n/2. They are equal if [m.sub.i] = n/2 holds. Because group 1 is the
largest of the N groups, if [m.sub.1] > n/2 holds, then the
equilibrium expected payoff for each player in group 1 is less than
[[pi].sub.N+1](m) and the equilibrium expected payoff for each player in
groups 2 through N is greater than [[pi].sub.N+1](m). Otherwise, the
equilibrium expected payoff for each player in groups 1 through N is
greater than or equal to [[pi].sub.N+1](m).
IV. EQUILIBRIUM NUMBERS OF STRATEGIC GROUPS ND EQUILIBRIUM GROUP
SIZES
We analyzed the second and the third stages of our three-stage game
in section III. We now consider the first stage in which the players
decide simultaneously and independently whether to form strategic
groups. By doing so, we obtain the equilibrium number of strategic
groups and the equilibrium size of group i denoted by [N.sup.*] and
[m.sup.*.sub.i], respectively. Note that [N.sup.*] and [m.sup.*.sub.i]
are determined at the same time (see note 5). We obtain [N.sup.*] and
[m.sup.*.sub.i], using Lemma 4 and the fact that in equilibrium no
player has an incentive to deviate individually from his
"position"-that is, no payoff-increasing individual move-in or
move-out is possible. Given n, the equilibrium number of strategic
groups is not unique. We obtain first the equilibrium group sizes when
[N.sup.*] = 1, which are summarized in Lemma 5 and Table 1. (8)
LEMMA 5. When [N.sup.*] = 1, the equilibrium group sizes are: (i)
[m.sup.*.sub.i] = n for n = 2 or 3, (ii) [m.sup.*.sub.i] = 3 and 4 for n
= 4 or 5, (iii) [m.sup.*.sub.i] = (n+2)/2 when n is even and n [greater
than or equal to] 6, and (iv) [m.sup.*.sub.i] = (n + 1)/2 when n is odd
and n [greater than equal to] 7.
Lemma 5 and Table 1 imply that when [N.sup.*] = 1, there may be
players who do not belong to the single strategic group. This occurs
because, in the case where just one strategic group is formed, if the
size of the single group is greater (less) than half the number of
players, then the expected payoff for each member is less (greater) than
that for each nonmember (see Lemma 4). Note that, for n [greater than or
equal to] 6, the equilibrium group size equals the smallest of integers
greater than half the number of players. This means that, as the number
of players increases, the number of nonmembers weakly increases. Recall
from Lemma 1 that the grand coalition eliminates the inefficiency
problem associated with rent seeking. This and Lemma 5 tell us that,
when n [less than or equal to] 4, the inefficiency problem of rent
seeking can be eliminated by endogenous strategic-group formation.
Next, we consider the case where [N.sup.*] [greater than or equal
to] 2.
LEMMA 6. (a) When [N.sup.*] [greater than or equal to] 2, every
player is a strategic-group member: n = [m.sup.*.sub.1]
+...+[m.sup.*.sub.[N.sup.*]]. (b) when [N.sup.*] [greater than or equal
to] 2, the difference in equilibrium group size between group 1 and
group [N.sup.*] is either zero or one: In terms of the symbols,
[m.sup.*.sub.1] = [m.sup.*.sub.[N.sup.*]] or [m.sup.*.sub.1] =
[m.sup.*.sub.[N.sup.*]]+ 1. (c) Suppose that n = [m.sub.1] +...+
[m.sub.N], and that [m.sub.1] = [m.sub.N] or [m.sub.1] = [m.sub.N] + 1.
Then, when N [greater than or equal to] 5, no player in group i with
[m.sub.i] [greater than or equal to] 2 has an incentive to move out of
his strategic group. When N [greater than or equal to] 2, no player in
group i with [m.sub.i] [greater than or equal to] 3 has an incentive to
move out of his strategic group.
Due to the assumption that [m.sub.[N.sup.*]] [less than or equal
to] ... [less than or equal to] [m.sub.2] [less than or equal to]
[m.sub.1], part (b) is equivalent to stating that the difference in
equilibrium group size between any two groups is either zero or one. In
other words, the [N.sup.*] strategic groups are of the same size, or a
largest strategic group has at most one more player when compared with a
smallest group.
Lemma 6 and additional computation yield Lemma 7.
LEMMA 7. (a) When [N.sup.*] = 2, the equilibrium group sizes are:
([m.sup.*.sub.1], [m.sup.*.sub.2]) = (n/2, n/2) for n = 2k, and
([m.sup.*.sub.1], [m.sup.*.sub.2]) = ((n+1)/2, (n-1)/2) for n = 2k+1,
where k is an integer and n [greater than or equal to] 6.
(b) When [N.sup.*] = 3, the equilibrium group sizes are:
[m.sup.*.sub.1] = [m.sup.*.sub.2] = [m.sup.*.sub.3] = n/3 for n =
3k,
[m.sup.*.sub.1] = (n+2)/3 and [m.sup.*.sub.2] = [m.sup.*.sub.3] =
(n-1)/3 for n = 3k+1,
and
[m.sup.*.sub.1] = [m.sup.*.sub.2] = (n + 1)/3 and [m.sup.*.sub.3] =
(n - 2)/3 for n = 3k+2,
where k is an integer and n [greater than or equal to] 8.
(c) When [N.sup.*] = 4, the equilibrium group sizes are:
(i) [m.sup.*.sub.1] =...= [m.sup.*.sub.4] = 2 for n = 8, and
(ii) [m.sup.*.sub.1] =...= [m.sup.*.sub.4] = n/4 for n = 4k,
[m.sup.*.sub.1] = (n+3)/4 and [m.sup.*.sub.2] = [m.sup.*.sub.3] =
[m.sup.*.sub.4] = (n-1)/4 for n = 4k+1,
[m.sup.*.sub.1] = [m.sup.*.sub.2] = (n+2)/4 and [m.sup.*.sub.3] =
[m.sup.*.sub.4] = (n-2)/4 for n=4k+2,
and
[m.sup.*.sub.1] = [m.sup.*.sub.2] = [m.sup.*.sub.3] = (n+1)/4 and
[m.sup.*.sub.4] = (n-3)/4 for n = 4k+3,
where k is an integer and n [greater than or equal to] 11.
(d) When [N.sup.*] = 5, the equilibrium group sizes are:
[m.sup.*.sub.1] =...= [m.sup.*.sub.5] = n/5 for n = 5k,
[m.sup.*.sub.1] = (n+4)/5 and [m.sup.*.sub.2] =...= [m.sup.*.sub.5]
= (n-1)/5 for n = 5k+1,
[m.sup.*.sub.1] = [m.sup.*.sub.2] = (n+3)/5 and [m.sup.*.sub.3] =
[m.sup.*.sub.4] = [m.sup.*.sub.5] = (n-2)/5 for n = 5k+2,
[m.sup.*.sub.1] = [m.sup.*.sub.2] = [m.sup.*.sub.3] = (n+2)/5 and
[m.sup.*.sub.4] = [m.sup.*.sub.5] = (n-3)/5 for n = 5k+3,
and
[m.sup.*.sub.1] =...= [m.sup.*.sub.4] = (n+1)/5 and [m.sup.*.sub.5]
= (n-4)/5 for n = 5k+4,
where k is an integer and n [greater than or equal to] 10.
Using Lemma 6, one can easily obtain the equilibrium group sizes
when [N.sup.*] [greater than or equal to] 6. It is easy to see that,
given [N.sup.*] [greater than or equal to] 2, the equilibrium size of
group i is weakly increasing in the number of players. Table 2 shows the
equilibrium group sizes for n [less than or equal to] 15, when 2 [less
than or equal to] [N.sup.*] [less than or equal to] 5.
In the literature on endogenous coalition formation, it is common
to obtain the equilibrium coalition structures involving multiple
coalitions (see, for example, Bloch, 1995; Yi, 1997, 1998; and Yi and
Shin, 2000). Morasch (2000) considers a game of endogenous formation of
strategic alliances. Examining the equilibrium structures of strategic
alliances resulting when only national alliances are possible, he shows
the following: All firms in the national industry join a single alliance
if the industry consists of up to four firms, but alliance structures
with outsiders and those with two or more alliances are quite likely if
the number of firms in the industry exceeds four.
We end this section by highlighting the interesting results
obtained from Lemmas 5, 6, and 7.
PROPOSITION 1. (a) The equilibrium number of strategic groups is
one for n [less than or equal to] 5, but is not unique for n [greater
than or equal to] 6. (b) The grand coalition never occurs for n [greater
than or equal to] 5. (c) When more than one strategic group is formed,
every player belongs to one of the groups and the difference in
equilibrium group size between any two groups is at most one. (d) Given
[N.sup.*] [greater than or equal to] 2, the equilibrium size of group i
is weakly increasing in the number of players.
Parts (a) and (b) (and Lemmas 5, 6, and 7) say that, as the number
of players increases, more players become nonmembers (in the case where
just one strategic group is formed) or more strategic groups are formed.
This implies that, as the number of players increases, cooperation among
the players becomes weaker. Part (b) means that, for n [greater than or
equal to] 5, if a player deviates individually from the grand coalition,
his expected payoff increases. This happens because, as the number of
players increases, the equal share in the grand coalition becomes
smaller and the members in the group (formed without the deviating
player) become less motivated. Indeed, they become less motivated
because the winner's fractional share of the group--and thus the
prize to the winning member--decreases as the number of players
increases. Part (c) is explained by two facts derived from Lemma 4: (i)
the expected payoff for each player in groups 2 through N is always
greater than that for a player who does not belong to a strategic group,
and (ii) the players in a smaller group have greater equilibrium
expected payoffs than those in a larger one. The former tells us that a
nonmember can increase his expected payoff by joining one of those
groups. The latter fact tells us that, if the difference in group size
between any two groups is greater than one, then a player in a larger
group can increase his expected payoff by switching his membership to a
smaller group. Part (d) follows immediately from part (c) and the
assumption that [m.sub.[N.sup.*]] [less than or equal to] ... [less than
or equal to] [m.sub.2] [less than or equal to] [m.sub.1].
V. WINNER'S FRACTIONAL SHARES, EXPECTED PAYOFFS, AND RENT
DISSIPATION
We begin by computing the groups' equilibrium winner's
fractional shares of our three-stage game. Using Lemmas 1, 2, 5, 6, and
7, we obtain Proposition 2. (9)
PROPOSITION 2. (a) When lust one strategic group is formed in
equilibrium, the strategic group's equilibrium winner's
fractional share is less than one. (b) When two strategic groups are
formed in equilibrium, (i) each group's equilibrium winner's
fractional share equals one when n is even, and (ii) the equilibrium
winner's fractional share of the larger group is less than one and
that of the smaller group is greater than one, when n is odd. (c) When
more than two strategic groups are formed in equilibrium, the
groups' equilibrium winner's fractional shares are greater
than one.
In the case where just one strategic group is formed in
equilibrium, if a player in the group wins the rent, the winner helps
the losers in the group and thus the prize to the winner is less than
the rent. This confirms our explanation in section I that one motive of
group formation is that players want to ensure against their failure in
winning the rent. Part (b) says that when two strategic groups are
formed and n is even, the winner takes all the rent. Part (c) says that
when more than two strategic groups are formed in equilibrium, the
winner takes all the rent and further receives "bounties" from
the other players in his group. Thus, in this case, the prize to the
winner is greater than the rent.
Why do group members write an agreement that if a player in their
group wins the rent, the other members in the group pay
"bounties" to the winner? One reason is that they can achieve
strategic commitments: They can change their opponents' behavior in
their favor by using such a "sharing" rule. Another and more
convincing reason is that they each--as the potential beneficiary--can
be motivated to exert more effort and thus can be more aggressive in the
outlays-expending stage because the "sharing" rule makes the
winner's prize bigger. In short, each group member agrees to pay
"bounties" to increase his own expected payoff. Indeed, each
group member supports himself by promising to support the winning
member.
An explanation for part (c) is then: Competing against the members
in the other groups who are more aggressive than individual players, the
members in each group make themselves more aggressive by setting their
winner's fractional share greater than one.
Next, using Lemmas 4 through 7, we compute the equilibrium expected
payoffs for the players, and compare them with the players'
expected payoffs resulting from usual individual rent seeking. Note that
each player's expected payoff resulting from individual rent
seeking, denoted by [pi](IR), is V/[n.sup.2] (see note 4). We obtain
Proposition 3.
PROPOSITION 3. (a) When just one strategic group is formed in
equilibrium, each player's equilibrium expected payoff is greater
than [pi](IR). (b) When two strategic groups are formed in equilibrium,
(i) each player's equilibrium expected payoff equals [pi](IR) when
n is even, and (ii) the equilibrium expected payoff for each player in a
larger group is less than [pi](IR) and that for each player in a smaller
group is greater than [pi](IR), when n is odd. (c) When more than two
strategic groups are formed in equilibrium, each player's
equilibrium expected payoff is less than [pi](IR).
When just one strategic group is formed in equilibrium, group
formation is beneficial both to the group members and to the nonmembers.
This means that group formation creates a positive externality for the
nonmembers. (10) However, when more than two strategic groups are formed
in equilibrium, group formation is never profitable to any players. The
intuitive explanations for these follow. When one strategic group is
formed, only the group members move before the outlays-expending stage
by announcing their sharing rule. According to the sharing rule, if a
player in the group wins the rent, the winner must help the losers in
the group. The exclusive move and rent sharing mitigate the competition
among the players in the following outlays-expending stage, and thus
enables the group members to increase their expected payoffs, as
compared with those earned in the case of individual rent seeking.
Interestingly, the nonmembers also benefit by that exclusive move. (11)
By contrast, when more than two strategic groups are formed, the groups
announce their sharing rules simultaneously. And, according to each
sharing rule, a winner takes all the rent and further receives
"bounties" from the other players in his group. These
simultaneous moves and the prize bigger than the rent lead to an intense
competition, and thus the players' expected payoffs decrease as
compared with individual rent seeking.
Yi (1996) examines the welfare effects of endogenous formation of
customs unions On member and nonmember countries. He shows that
formation of customs unions improves the aggregate welfare of member
countries but reduces the welfare of nonmember countries. He also shows
that, in any customs-union structure, a member of a large union has a
higher level of welfare than a member of a small union. Morasch (2000)
shows in the linear Cournot model that, in the case where only national
alliances are possible, the members of a smaller alliance earn higher
profits because they are more aggressive in the output market. To
compare these results with ours, recall the result in Lemma 4 that the
players in a smaller group have greater equilibrium expected payoffs
than those in a larger one.
Finally, using Lemmas 1, 3, 5, 6, and 7, we compute the equilibrium
outlays of the individual players and the equilibrium total outlay, and
compare them with the individual outlays and total outlay resulting from
usual individual rent seeking. Note that each player's outlay and
the total outlay resulting from individual rent seeking, denoted by
x(IR) and H(IR), are V(n-1)/[n.sup.2] and V(n - 1)/n, respectively (see
note 4). We obtain Proposition 4.
PROPOSITION 4. (a) When just one strategic group is formed in
equilibrium, each group member's equilibrium outlay is less than
x(IR), each nonmember's equilibrium outlay is greater than x(IR),
and the equilibrium total outlay is less than H(IR). (b) When two
strategic groups are formed in equilibrium, (i) each player's
equilibrium outlay and the equilibrium total outlay equal x(IR) and
H(IR), respectively, when n is even; (ii) the equilibrium outlay of each
player in a larger group is less than x(IR) and that of each player in a
smaller group is greater than x(IR), when n is odd; and (iii) the
equilibrium total outlay equals H(IR). (c) When more than two strategic
groups are formed in equilibrium, (i) the equilibrium outlays of some
players may be less than x(IR), and (ii) the equilibrium total outlay is
greater than H(IR) but is less than the rent.
How much of the rent is dissipated by rent-seeking activities?
Examining the extent of rent dissipation is one of the main issues in
the literature on rent seeking. It is important because the opportunity
costs of resources expended on rent-seeking activities are social costs
and thus create economic inefficiency.
Proposition 4 says that, in the case where just one strategic group
is formed in equilibrium, rent dissipation (or total outlay) is smaller
than with individual rent seeking--that is, the social cost associated
with rent seeking decreases by such group formation. However, in the
case where more than two strategic groups are formed in equilibrium,
rent dissipation is greater than with individual rent seeking. This
result that group formation increases rent dissipation compared with
individual rent seeking, is new in the literature on rent seeking. Baik
(1994) shows in a model similar to ours that group formation always
decreases rent dissipation compared with individual rent seeking. The
main reason why we obtain the different result is that the winner's
fractional share can be greater than unity in this article but cannot be
so in Baik (1994). Proposition 4 also implies that the equilibrium total
outlay is less than the rent, V, regardless of the number of strategic
groups formed. This establishes that less t han complete dissipation of
the contested rent occurs when the players endogenously form strategic
groups. (12)
Using Lemmas 3 and 6, we obtain that, when [N.sup.*] [greater than
equal to] 2, the equilibrium total outlay is V[1 - 1/n ([N.sup.*] - 1].
It follows from this that, given the number of players, n, rent
dissipation increases as the equilibrium number of strategic groups,
[N.sup.*], increases. It also follows that, given [N.sup.*] [greater
than equal to] 2, rent dissipation increases as the number of players,
n, increases. Another interesting result is that, in contrast with
individual rent seeking, rent dissipation may decrease as the number of
players increases. (13) This occurs when an increase in the number of
players is accompanied by a decrease in the equilibrium number of
strategic groups.
VI. CONCLUSION
We have considered a rent-seeking contest in which players can form
strategic groups before they expend their outlays. After obtaining the
equilibrium numbers of strategic groups and equilibrium group sizes, we
have examined the profitability of endogenous group formation and the
effect of such group formation on rent dissipation. We have found the
following. When just one strategic group is formed in equilibrium, group
formation is beneficial both to the group members and to the nonmembers,
and rent dissipation is smaller than with usual individual rent seeking.
However, when more than two strategic groups are formed in equilibrium,
group formation is never profitable to any players and rent dissipation
is greater than with individual rent seeking. Finally, total
rent-seeking outlay is less than the rent, regardless of the number of
strategic groups formed.
We have shown in section IV that, when the number of players does
not exceed five, the grand coalition occurs and, therefore, the
inefficiency problem associated with rent seeking disappears.
In section IV, to obtain the equilibrium numbers of strategic
groups and equilibrium group sizes, we have checked only whether a
player has an incentive to deviate individually from his position. This
means that our notion of equilibrium does not rule out the possibility
of profitable coalitional-deviations from an equilibrium. That is, in an
equilibrium, no player has an incentive to deviate individually, but
coalitions of players may have incentives to deviate collectively.
Hence, if we use an equilibrium concept that takes into account
coalitional deviations also, we may obtain fewer equilibrium than we
have in section IV. Indeed, we can refine the "Nash equilibrium
set" obtained in section IV--we can obtain sharper predictions
about the equilibrium numbers of strategic groups and equilibrium group
sizes--by using the concept of coalition-proof Nash equilibrium
introduced by Bernheim et al. (1987). (14) However, our main results in
section V remain unchanged because the coalition-proof Nash equilibrium
set is merely a subset of the Nash equilibrium set.
Baik: Professor, Department of Economics, Sungkyunkwan University,
Seoul 110-745, South Korea. Phone 82-2-740-0432, Fax 82-2-744-5717
E-mail khbaik@skku.ac.kr
Lee: Professor, School of Economics, Kookmin University, Seoul
136-702, South Korea. Phone 82-2-910-4546, Fax 82-2-910-4519, E-mail
slee@kmu.kookmin.ac.kr
(*.) We are grateful to Yongsung Chang, Jacques Cremer, Terrance
Hurley, Inchul Kim, Jaehong Kim, Kenneth Koford, Richard Milam, William S. Neilson, Suk Jae Noh, Robert Oxoby, Tim Perri, Sang-Seung Yi, and two
anonymous referees for their helpful comments and suggestions. Earlier
versions of this paper were presented at the 1998 Annual Conference of
the Korean Econometric Society, Seoul, Korea, November 1998; the 74th
Annual Conference of the Western Economic Association International, San
Diego, CA, July 1999; and the 2001 Annual Meetings of the Allied Social
Science Associations, New Orleans, LA, January 2001. This work was
supported by Faculty Research Fund, Sungkyunkwan University, 1997.
(1.) Nitzan (1994) provides an excellent survey of the literature
on rent seeking.
(2.) Baik (1994) and Baik and Shogren (1995) formally study group
formation. But the number of groups formed is exogenously restricted to
unity. By contrast, we endogenize the number of groups formed.
(3.) To highlight the first motive to form such groups, one may
wish to call them something different, say, support groups.
(4.) This simplest logit-form probability-of-winning function (also
called contest success function) is extensively used in the literature
on rent seeking. Examples include Tullock (1980), Appelbaum and Katz
(1987), Hillman and Riley (1989), Hirshleifer (1989), Katz et al.
(1990), Ursprung (1990) Nitzan (1991a, 1991b), Leininger (1993), Baik
(1994), Baik (1994), Baik and Shogren (1995), Lee (1995), and Che and
Gale (1997). For other forms of probability of winning functions, See
Baik (1998) and Baik et al. (2001).
Consider the case in which the players compete individually to win
the rent. Assume that the players choose their outlays simultaneously.
Then, at the Nash equilibrium, each player's expected payoff is
V/[n.sup.2], each player's outlay is V(n - 1 )/[n.sup.2], and the
players' total outlay is V(n - 1)/n (see Baik, 1994). We will use
these values as the comparative benchmarks when we examine the effects
of endogenous group formation on each player's expected payoff,
each player's outlay, and the players' total outlay.
(5.) Imagine the following procedure. Each player throws his name
tag into one of n jars. The players who do not want to form a strategic
group should throw their names in one particular jar, say, the nth jar.
The players who throw their names in the same jar (other than the nth
one) will form a strategic group. If the jth jar contains only one name,
then the player forms a strategic group with, say, the kth jar players.
In order not to have a trivial equilibrium in which no strategic group
is formed, we assume that one player throws his name in a jar (other
than the nth one) before the other players choose their jars.
(6.) In the rest of this section, if you consider the case where
[m.sub.N+1] = 0, then ignore the discussions and analyses for the
players in group N + 1 and substitute [m.sub.N+1] with zero in all the
mathematical results for the players in groups 1 through N.
(7.) These payoff functions hold for S > 0. If all the players
expend zero, that is, S = 0, then [[pi].sub.ij] = V/n for i = 1,...,
N+1.
(8.) The proofs of Lemmas 5, 6, and 7 are straightforward and
therefore omitted.
(9.) The proofs of Propositions 2,3 and 4 are straightforward and
therefore omitted.
(10.) Yi (1997) states that research-coalition formation in
oligopolies and customs-union formation in international markets each
create negative externalities for nonmembers whereas formation of output
cartels in oligopolies and formation of coalitions to provide public
goods each create positive externalities.
(11.) It follows immediately from Lemmas 4 and 5 that each group
member's expected payoff is less than each nonmember's
(12.) Many economists obtain the underdissipation-of-rents result.
Examples include Tullock (1980), Hillman and Katz (1984), Hillman and
Riley (1989), Katz et al. (1990), Ursprung (1990), Guttman et al.
(1992), Baik (1994), and Baik and Shogren (1995).
(13.) Nitzan (1991b) also obtains this result.
(14.) The coalition-proof Nash equilibrium set may be empty. Yi and
Shin (2000) obtain stable structures of research joint ventures, using
the concept of coalition-proof Nash equilibrium.
REFERENCES
Appelbaum, E., and E. Katz. "Seeking Rents by Setting Rents:
The Political Economy of Rent Seeking." Economic Journal, 97(387),
1987, 685-99.
Baik, K. H. "Effort Levels in Contests: The Public-Good Prize
Case." Economics Letters, 41(4), 1993, 363-67.
-----. "Winner-Help-Loser Group Formation in Rent-Seeking
Contests." Economics and Politics, 6(2), 1994, 147-62.
-----. "Difference-Form Contest Success Functions and Effort
Levels in Contests." European Journal of Political Economy, 14(4),
1998, 685-701.
Baik, K. H., and S. Lee. "Collective Rent Seeking with
Endogenous Group Sizes." European Journal of Political Economy,
13(1), 1997, 121-30.
Baik, K. H., and J. F. Shogren. "Competitive-Share Group
Formation in Rent-Seeking Contests." Public Choice, 83(1-2), 1995,
113-26.
Baik, K. H., I.-G. Kim, and S. Na. "Bidding for a
Group-Specific Public-Good Prize." Journal of Public Economics,
2001 (forthcoming).
Belleflamme, P. "Stable Coalition Structures with Open
Membership and Asymmetric Firms." Games and Economic Behavior,
30(1), 2000, 1-21.
Bernheim, B. D., B. Peleg, and M. D. Whinston.
"Coalition-Proof Nash Equilibria: I. Concepts." Journal of
Economic Theory, 42(1), 1987, 1-12.
Bloch, F. "Endogenous Structures of Association in
Oligopolies." Rand Journal of Economics, 26(3), 1995, 537-56.
-----. "Sequential Formation of Coalitions in Games with
Externalities and Fixed Payoff Division." Gaines and Economic
Behavior, 14(1), 1996, 90-123.
Che, Y.-K., and I. Gale. "Rent Dissipation When Rent Seekers
Are Budget Constrained." Public Choice, 92(1-2), 1997, 109-26.
Guttman, J. M., S. Nitzan, and U. Spiegel. "Rent Seeking and
Social Investment in Taste Change." Economics and Politics, 4(l),
1992, 31-42.
Hausken, K. "The Dynamics of Within-Group and Between-Group
Interaction." Journal of Mathematical Economics, 24(7), 1995,
655-87.
Hillman, A. L, and E. Katz. "Risk-Averse Rent Seekers and the
Social Cost of Monopoly Power." Economic Journal, 94(373), 1984,
104-10.
Hillman, A. L., and J. G. Riley. "Politically Contestable
Rents and Transfers." Economics and Politics, 1(1), 1989, 17-39.
Hirshleifer, J. "Conflict and Rent-Seeking Success Functions:
Ratio vs. Difference Models of Relative Success." Public Choice,
63(2), 1989, 101-12.
Hurley, T. M., and J. F. Shogren. "Effort Levels in a Cournot
Nash Contest with Asymmetric Information." Journal of Public
Economics, 69(2), 1998, 195-210.
Katz, E., and J. Tokatlidu. "Group Competition for
Rents." European Journal of Political Economy, 12(4), 1996,
599-607.
Katz, E., S. Nitzan, and J. Rosenberg. "Rent-Seeking for Pure
Public Goods." Public Choice, 65(1), 1990, 49-60.
Konishi, H., M. Le Breton, and S. Weber. "Pure Strategy Nash
Equilibrium in a Group Formation Game with Positive Externalities."
Games and Economic Behavior, 21(1/2), 1997, 161-82.
Krueger, A. O. "The Political Economy of the Rent-Seeking
Society." American Economic Review, 64(3), 1974, 291-303.
Lee, S. "Endogenous Sharing Rules in Collective-Group
Rent-Seeking." Public Choice, 85(1-2), 1995, 31-44.
Leininger, W. "More Efficient Rent-Seeking--A Munchhausen
Solution." Public Choice, 75(1), 1993, 43-62.
Morasch, K. "Strategic Alliances: A Substitute for Strategic
Trade Policy?" Journal of International Economics, 52(1), 2000,
37-67.
Nitzan, S. "Rent-Seeking with Non-identical Sharing
Rules." Public Choice, 71(1-2), 1991a, 43-50.
-----. "Collective Rent Dissipation." Economic Journal,
101(409), 1991b, 1522-34.
-----. "Modelling Rent-Seeking Contests." European
Journal of Political Economy, 10(1), 1994, 41-60.
Posner, R. A. "The Social Costs of Monopoly and
Regulation." Journal of Political Economy, 83(4), 1975, 807-27.
Riaz, K., J. F. Shogren, and S. R. Johnson. "A General Model
of Rent Seeking for Public Goods." Public Choice, 82(3-4), 1995,
243-59.
Tullock, G. "The Welfare Costs of Tariffs, Monopolies, and
Theft." Western Economic Journal, 5, June 1967, 224-32.
-----. "Efficient Rent Seeking," in Toward a Theory of
the Rent-Seeking Society, edited by J. M. Buchanan, R. D. Tollison, and
G. Tullock College Station, TX: Texas A&M University Press, 1980,
97-112.
Ursprung, H. W. "Public Goods, Rent Dissipation, and Candidate
Competition." Economics and Politics, 2(2), 1990, 115-32.
Yi, S.-S. "Endogenous Formation of Customs Unions under
Imperfect Competition: Open Regionalism Is Good." Journal of
International Economics, 41(1-2-, 1996, 153-77.
-----. "Stable Coalition Structures with Externalities."
Games and Economic Behavior, 20(2), 1997, 201-37.
-----. "Endogenous Formation of Joint Ventures with Efficiency
Gains." Rand Journal of Economics, 29(3), 1998, 610-31.
Yi, S.-S., and H. Shin. "Endogenous Formation of Research
Coalitions with Spillovers." International Journal of Industrial
Organization, 18(2), 2000, 229-56.
TABLE 1
The Equilibrium Group Sizes When [N.sub.*] = 1
n [m.sup.*.sub.1]
2 2
3 3
4 3 and 4
5 3 and 4
6 4
7 4
8 5
9 5
. .
. .
. .
even (n + 2)/2
odd (n + 1)/2
TABLE 2
The Equilibrium Group Sizes When 2 [less than or equal to]
[N.sup.*] [less than or equal to] 5
([m.sup.*.sub.1],
([m.sup.*.sub.1], [m.sup.*.sub.2],
([m.sup.*.sub.1], [m.sup.*.sub.2], [m.sup.*.sub.3],
n [m.sup.*.sub.2]) [m.sup.*.sub.3]) [m.sup.*.sub.4])
6 (3,3)
7 (4,3)
8 (4,4) (3,3,2) (2,2,2,2)
9 (5,4) (3,3,3)
10 (5,5) (4,3,3)
11 (6,5) (4,4,3) (3,3,3,2)
12 (6,6) (4,4,4) (3,3,3,3)
13 (7,6) (5,4,4) (4,3,3,3)
14 (7,7) (5,5,4) (4,4,3,3)
15 (8,7) (5,5,5) (4,4,4,3)
*
*
*
([m.sup.*.sub.1],
[m.sup.*.sub.2],
[m.sup.*.sub.3],
[m.sup.*.sub.4],
n [m.sup.*.sub.5])
6
7
8
9
10 (2,2,2,2,2)
11 (3,2,2,2,2)
12 (3,3,2,2,2)
13 (3,3,3,2,2)
14 (3,3,3,3,2)
15 (3,3,3,3,3)
*
*
*