Payoff dominance vs. cognitive transparency in decision making.
Irwin, Julie R. ; McClelland, Gary H. ; McKee, Michael 等
I. INTRODUCTION
There is a general question about how well laboratory markets work in
eliciting true preferences given the low opportunity costs of making
errors as in Harrison [1989]. Vernon Smith [1982] set out a series of
conditions that must be adhered to if a laboratory market investigation
is to provide insight into economic behavior in naturally occurring
markets. The opportunity cost question, posed above, is covered under
Smith's "payoff dominance" and "reward
saliency" precepts for laboratory market experiments. If the
experimental setting is to elicit true preferences from the subjects the
monetary payoffs in the experiment must be salient and dominate
potential extraneous influences on subject behavior. This paper reports
on three series of experiments which employ the Becker-DeGroot-Marshak
(BDM) mechanism to investigate the interaction between payoff
dominance/reward saliency and cognitive effort in the decision task. The
BDM mechanism is well suited to this task because it involves only
individual choice, is theoretically incentive compatible, and offers a
high degree of experimenter control over payoffs, initial information,
and feedback on the results of decisions.
Becker, DeGroot, and Marschak [1964] introduced the following
preference-elicitation mechanism: individuals state the most they would
be willing to pay (WTP)(1) for a good. Then, a random price is drawn
from a distribution known to the individuals. If the stated value is
greater than or equal to the random price, the individual buys the good
at the randomly-determined price. Otherwise the individual does not buy
the good.
The BDM bidding mechanism can be shown to be incentive-compatible.
The intuition is straightforward. It is not in the individual's
interest to understate true WTP; if the random buying price falls
between the stated WTP and the true WTP, the individual has foregone a
beneficial trade. It is also not in an individual's interest to
overstate true WTP; if the random buying price is greater than the true
value but less than the stated value, the individual will be required to
buy the good at a price greater than true WTP.
A more formal proof is easy to construct:(2) Let
V = the true value of one unit of the auction good;
B = the bid submitted to purchase one unit of the good;
R = the price, randomly determined, to be paid if the good is
purchased;
p(R) = probability that price R is randomly selected;
[Y.sup.o] = initial income;
U(Y) = utility, a function of money income and the value of the good;
and
E = initial monetary balance provided in an experiment.
In the WTP-version of the BDM auction, the good is purchased if B
[greater than or equal to] R (with the subject paying only R) and not
purchased if B [less than] R. In experiments using the BDM the subject
cannot bid more than the experimental balance E so it must be that V
[less than] E if the experiment is to be demand revealing. Assuming that
subjects maximize expected utility, they will submit bid B that
maximizes
EU = [integral of] p (R)U([Y.sup.o] + E + V - R)dR between limits B
and 0 + [integral of] p(R)U([Y.sup.o] + E)dR between limits E and B.
The first integral describes the expected payoff for random prices R
below the bid B and the second integral describes the expected payoff
for random prices between the bid B and the maximum possible bid as
limited by the balance E. The maximum over B occurs when the derivative
of EU with respect to B is zero; in other words, when
dEU/dB = p(B)[U(Y + E + V - B) - u(Y + E)] = 0
So long as p(B) [greater than] 0 (i.e., there is some probability the
offered bid will be the price), the above implies that the maximum
occurs when B = V. In other words, it is individually optimal to submit
a bid B equal to one's true value V for the commodity. Although the
BDM is incentive-compatible in theory, it is an empirical question
whether it has this property in practice.
The first experiment reported tests the incentive-compatibility
properties of the BDM in a pure induced-value setting. The results from
this experiment demonstrate that the BDM is, in fact,
incentive-compatible. The second experiment tests the performance of the
BDM under different information regimes and payoff schedules. The
results suggest that steep payoff schedules are unnecessary to induce
optimizing behavior when the subject is able to deduce the optimal
strategy from the initial information provided. The BDM would appear to
be a transparent decision task and steep payoff schedules have no effect
on behavior here. The third experiment tests whether subjects require
steep payoff schedules when they must search for, rather than compute,
an optimal strategy. The results suggest that steepness of the payoff
schedule can make a difference when search is required. We note that, to
be useful, feedback must provide the subject with the link between the
decision and the payoff and must be provided before the next decision is
made.
The following general methods apply to all three experiments reported
below. All experiments were conducted in the Laboratory for Economics
and Psychology (LEAP) at the University of Colorado, Boulder. The
subjects were volunteers from undergraduate economics classes. Subjects
sat at individual cubicles containing a display screen and a computer
keyboard, and they received both written and verbal instructions.(3)
Subjects were permitted to ask questions of the experimenter but they
were not allowed to communicate with each other. When recruited,
subjects were assured they should expect to earn a minimum of $5 for
their participation. In practice, earnings averaged more than $15.00 for
sessions lasting less than one hour and the minimum earnings level was
non-binding for all subjects.
II. A TEST OF THE BDM MECHANISM: THE INDUCED-VALUE SETTING
The first experiment, Experiment I, is designed to provide a test of
the reliability of the BDM mechanism in the form in which it is
typically applied. In Experiment I subjects in the WTP setting submit
bids for the purchase of a ticket with a known and certain redemption
value. In the WTA setting subjects are given a ticket with a known and
certain redemption value and they are invited to submit offers to sell
the ticket.(4) The random buying price is drawn from a uniform
distribution and the subjects are told the shape of this distribution.
The empirical question to be addressed is whether the subjects state
their true WTP (WTA) values in this setting.
Forty-six subjects participated in Experiment I. There were two
between-subject treatments: WTP and WTA. Subjects in the WTP treatment
received an initial balance of $10 and were asked to state their bid for
the ticket. Subjects in the WTA treatment were given a ticket and asked
to state their selling price. There were five practice rounds. After the
practice rounds, balances were restored to the initial $10 or $0. The
actual experiment consisted of 15 real rounds, although this number was
not announced to the subjects to avoid possible end-period effects.
In each round, the computer displayed on each subject's screen a
"ticket" value, randomly selected by the computer from the
range $0.25 to $5.50 in $0.25 increments. Subjects in the WTP treatment
then entered on their keyboards the most they would be willing to pay
for their tickets. After all subjects had entered bids, a price was
chosen randomly from a cage of 24 bingo balls. Prices ranged from $0 to
$6.00, in a uniform distribution with $0.25 increments.(5) The uniform
distribution induces a quadratic expected payoff function. All subjects
who bid above or equal to the chosen price bought the ticket and the
random price was deducted from their balances. The ticket was then
redeemed for its displayed value, and this value was added to individual
balances. Subjects who bid below the chosen price did not buy the ticket
and their balances remained unchanged. All these transactions appeared
on the subjects' screens. After viewing the transaction
information, subjects pressed a key to move on to the next round.
Subjects in the WTA treatment entered on their keyboards the least
they would be willing to accept to relinquish the ticket. After all
subjects had entered offers, the price was randomly chosen from the same
distribution of bingo balls as that used in the WTP treatment. Those
subjects who offered to sell their tickets for a price above the random
price kept their tickets. Tickets were then redeemed for their displayed
values, and these values were added to balances of those subjects who
kept their tickets. For those subjects whose offers to sell were equal
to or below the random price, the random BDM price of the ticket was
added to their balances in exchange for their tickets.
Results
The analyses reported throughout this paper include only the real
rounds of the experiment. Figures 1 and 2 show the distribution of
bid-ticket price differences for the WTP and WTA treatments,
respectively. Prices were distributed in 25[cents] increments, so a
bid-ticket difference between -25[cents] and $0 is individually optimal
for the WTP treatment and a bid-ticket difference between $0 and
+25[cents] is individually optimal for the WTA treatment. For both
treatments, the majority of bid-ticket differences are in the optimal
range. In the WTP treatment, 62% of the bids are optimal; in the WTA
treatment 67% of the bids are optimal. The mean differences between bid
and ticket value for each subject across all fifteen real rounds(6) did
not differ significantly from zero (t(27) = 1.21, not significant
(n.s.), for WTP and t(19) = .46, n.s., for WTA) There was no difference
in mean bid-ticket difference due to WTA versus WTP treatments (t(44) =
-0.22, n.s.). Finally, there also was no difference in percentage of
optimal bids between the two treatments (t(45) = .47, n.s.).
If subjects were attempting to be strategic, one would expect
underbidding for WTP and overbidding for WTA. However, non-optimal bids
tended to be overbids in both treatments (66% for WTP and 60% for WTA).
The mean difference between actual and optimal bids (or offers)
provides a measure of aggregate bias within an experimental treatment,
but it does not assess individual accuracy because it allows overbids
and underbids to cancel. The mean absolute difference, plotted in Figure
3 across rounds, does provide a measure of bidding accuracy by comparing
the theoretically predicted bidding behavior with the actual behavior.
There was no difference between the mean absolute differences for WTP
and WTA (t(45) = -0.18, n.s.). However, WTP accuracy improved over time
(an average $0.033 accuracy improvement per round) whereas WTA accuracy
remained unchanged on average across the rounds (the test of this
interaction is t(44) = 3.34, p [less than] .002).
It is interesting to compare our results with the body of literature
reporting large differences between stated WTA and WTP values. In
contrast to the many studies that have reported large disparities
between responses in WTA and WTP conditions (e.g., Gregory [1986];
Kahneman, Knetsch, and Thaler [1990]; Knetsch [1989]; and McClelland and
Schulze [1991]), there were essentially no differences between the WTA
and WTP conditions in this experiment. Shogren et al. [1994], examined
the effect of substitutability between goods as an explanation of the
disparity and also finds no difference between WTA and WTP when
substitution possibilities exist.
The mean differences between actual and optimal bids in our
experiments did not differ between the two conditions and the proportion
of optimal bids was about the same in both conditions. The only
difference was a tendency for WTP bids to start higher and then improve
with experience while WTA offers started closer to optimal and then did
not improve. If studies using a BDM mechanism find a large disparity
between WTA and WTP responses, then it is not reasonable to suspect that
the BDM mechanism itself caused the disparity.
In summary, the results of Experiment I demonstrate that in this
simple setting, the BDM mechanism is indeed incentive-compatible. Even
for the modest amounts of money offered in this experiment and for the
modest expected penalties for deviating from the theoretically predicted
individually optimal behavior, most subjects submitted bids that were at
or near the optimal bid. The question, addressed in the next experiment,
is whether subjects are sensitive to changes in the magnitude of the
expected penalties for deviating from optimal behavior.
III. DECISION COSTS, DECISION REWARDS, AND DECISION ERRORS
As a result of Harrison's [1989] critique of experimental
findings in sealed bid auctions, a number of researchers have addressed
the role of monetary payoffs in economic decision making. Smith and
Walker [1993] explicitly introduce decision costs and rewards into the
decision task. They draw a distinction between tasks in which the
subject is able to identify the optimal decision ex ante the decision
and tasks in which the subject must search for an optimum and is
informed of success or failure ex post. In the latter, the payoff
function must be steep and the feedback timely if the subject is to
reach an optimum decision quickly. In the former, the payoff function
need not be steep since the subject is able to analytically derive the
optimum decision from the information provided by the experimental
setting.
As shown above, the BDM mechanism is theoretically and empirically
incentive-compatible. In the complete information setting it also
appears to confront the subject with a simple task. For example, in the
WTP setting the subject merely chooses a bid against a random buying
price. This is a simple game against nature and the subject knows the
entire distribution of the moves available to nature. The BDM mechanism,
as generally applied, is a simple task in which the subject's
optimal decision is readily apparent: bid true WTP or ask true WTA.
However, the mechanism may be easily confounded by the experimenter so
that the subject is faced with decision settings in which the task is
made more opaque than in the basic BDM setting. Further, it is possible
to manipulate the payoff schedule to make it steeper or flatter and in
this way control the costs arising from failing to make optimal
decisions. Thus, the BDM mechanism provides a useful means of
investigating the role of payoff structure and task transparency in the
decision-making behavior of economic agents.
The cost of failing to bid exactly one's true value in typical
laboratory settings may be very small and it is possible that bidding
behavior may become sloppy. If this occurs, the experimenter has lost
control of the experimental setting due to the failure to maintain
payoff dominance (Smith [1982, 1991]). Payoff dominance requires that
the payoffs to decision-making dominate the cognitive costs of
decision-making. Without accurate estimates of decision-making costs, it
is necessary to test whether mechanisms such as the BDM are incentive
compatible under different payoff conditions. The experiment reported in
the next section addresses the effect of payoff steepness.
IV. PAYOFF DOMINANCE AND BIDDING BEHAVIOR IN THE BDM
Experiment II directly investigates the issue of payoff dominance by
comparing the behavioral effects of two different distributions of the
random buying prices in the BDM mechanism. These distributions produce
either a strong or weak penalty, relative to expected value, for
non-individually optimal bidding. Formally, note that the slope of the
payoff function in utility terms is
p(B)[U(Y + E + V - B) - U(Y + E)];
this reduces, in dollar terms, to
p(R)[V - B]
for risk neutral subjects. Thus, by altering p(R), the probability
density function of randomly chosen prices, we can alter the shape of
the payoff function and test Harrison's [1989] hypothesis that
subjects should perform worse for treatments with relatively fiat payoff
functions than for treatments with relatively peaked payoff functions.
A decision task is cognitively transparent when subjects readily
understand their optimal strategy from the instructions alone. In such a
setting, the non-satiation axiom states that the subjects will make
optimal decisions even when the costs of deviating from that strategy
are extremely small. Our maintained hypothesis is that the BDM is so
transparent and involves so little cognitive effort that subjects will
bid optimally, even when the rewards for doing so are small. In
contrast, bids ought to be less optimal and payoff structure ought to be
more influential if the bidding mechanism were more opaque. In opaque
situations subjects must rely on feedback information to search, across
repeated decisions, for the optimal bid. In the current experiment, we
introduce an opaque version of the BDM which is structurally identical
to the basic BDM setting, but about which the subject has little
information. The transparency vs. opaqueness treatment is
operationalized by giving subjects either full or minimal information
about the bidding mechanism. Following Smith and Walker [1993] we
predict that payoff structure will be important in the
minimal-information, or opaque, condition but not in the regular
full-information, or transparent, version of the BDM.
Method
Eighty-seven subjects participated in this experiment. A 2 x 2
factorial design was employed, with two between subjects treatments;
type of payoff structure (flat vs. peaked) and amount of information
concerning the mechanism (full vs. minimal). All conditions employed the
WTP context. Subjects were randomly assigned to each of the four
conditions and were each given an initial balance of $10. In each round
of the experiment, subjects submitted a bid on the computer terminal to
buy a ticket that was redeemable at the end of the round for $3. After
all the subjects had submitted a bid for the round, the price of the
ticket for that round was determined using the BDM mechanism.
Subjects in the full information conditions were told the value of
the ticket ($3), the probability distribution of prices, the actual
price of the ticket (as determined by the BDM mechanism), and whether
they bought the ticket or not. Subjects in the minimal information
conditions were only told that there was an optimal bid between $0.00
and $6.00 and that their task was to find that bid. They were not told
that they were bidding on a ticket nor were they told the value of the
ticket on which they were bidding. They were not told about the price
determination process or the price. They were told only their initial
balances, their payoffs and their ending balances for every round. Thus,
the outcome feedback about payoff and changes in balances received by
the subjects in both the full and minimal information conditions was
identical. But all other information was suppressed in the minimal
information setting.
Figure 4 shows the distribution of random prices used to generate the
two expected payoff functions shown in Figure 5. With the flat payoff
structure, which has the majority of prices either much below or much
above the optimal, subjects can be sloppy or careless in their bidding
behavior and expect to incur only a small penalty so long as their bids
are not at the very extremes. That is, as long as their bids are in the
general neighborhood of the optimal bid, it will be unlikely that the
random BDM price will be between the actual and the optimal bid. In
contrast, with the peaked payoff structure, which has a majority of its
prices near the optimal, the expected penalty for sloppy bidding,
especially in the neighborhood of the true value, is much larger. That
is, it is much more likely than the random BDM price will be between the
actual bid and the optimal.
As in the baseline Experiment I, each session began with five
practice rounds. After the practice rounds, the subjects' balances
were reset to the initial amount and all subjects participated in 13
real rounds, but this number was not announced.
Results
Figure 6 displays the mean absolute difference of subjects' bids
from the optimal (i.e., [absolute value of B - 3]). The mean absolute
difference was larger in the minimal information condition than in the
full information condition (t(86) = 5.36, p [less than] .0001). Further,
those subjects in the full information condition became more accurate by
about $0.025 per round, while those in the minimal information condition
became less accurate by about $0.02 per round (t(86) = 3.09, p [less
than] .003).
On average, across both information treatments there was no effect
due to the payoff structure (t(86) = 0.21, n.s.). However, of more
interest is whether there is an interaction between the payoff and the
information treatments. Specifically, do payoff structures make a
difference when subjects have minimal information, but not when they
have full information? As is clear in Figure 7, there is no evidence
that payoff structures were differentially effective within the two
information conditions (t(86) = 0.40, n.s.).
In summary, the results of this experiment are quite clear: payoff
structure had no effect on bidding behavior in the BDM. When the task
was transparent, as in the typical application of the BDM mechanism,
subjects performed well, relative to the theoretically predicted
optimal, and improved over time. However, it made no difference which
payoff structure they received; the flat payoff structure (flat relative
to the quadratic induced by the uniform distribution) and the peaked
payoff structure (peaked relative to the quadratic) produced virtually
identical performance to each other and to the performance with the
quadratic payoff structure of Experiment I. Hence, when the task is
transparent, payoff structure is irrelevant. Even when the penalties for
sloppiness are trivial, subjects are not more likely to be sloppy in
their bidding.
In sharp contrast to the full information treatment, subjects in the
minimal information or opaque treatment, with only the payoff feedback,
were unable to find the optimal bid, and, over time, their bids actually
became less efficient. This suggests that subjects in the full
information treatment were not using the outcome feedback on each round
as a clue to optimal behavior because the outcome feedback alone was
clearly inadequate. Apparently, the randomness in the feedback provided
by BDM payoffs defeats any attempt to search systematically for the
optimal bid. For example, the same bid of, say, $4 on two different
rounds may receive very different outcomes if the BDM prices are, say,
$3.50 (for a net loss of $0.50) and $2.50 (for a net gain of $0.50).
With such uncertain feedback, systematic search is difficult without
good record-keeping over a large number of rounds. In the next
experiment, we address whether systematic search might be feasible and
whether payoff structure might have an effect if the outcome feedback
were less uncertain.
V. SEARCHING FOR THE OPTIMAL BID: SEARCH UNDER CERTAINTY
The failure to find an effect due to the payoff structure for either
the full or minimal information treatments might suggest that the payoff
structures, although apparently different, were actually functionally
equivalent. That is, the differences in expected payoffs may have been
too trivial to produce differential performance. We will have more
confidence in our arguments concerning payoff dominance and decision
costs if we can show that the payoff structures used in Experiment II
are functionally different for at least one task. We attempt to do so in
this experiment, Experiment III, by using a minimal information
condition that has certain feedback. This is accomplished by changing a
subject's balance on each round according to the expected value of
his or her bid. That is, the amounts in Figure 5 are the actual payoffs
in this experiment. This design eliminates the uncertainty in the
feedback and makes it easier for subjects to search systematically for
the optimal bid. Thus, in the experiment we hold the feedback mechanism
fixed and vary the payoff structure as a treatment.
Even though subjects will have no direct information on the shape of
the payoff functions, we expect that subjects in the peaked payoff
structure condition will find the optimal bid rather quickly, because as
one moves away from the optimal bid of $3.00 in either direction the
payoff drops rapidly. For those subjects in the flat payoff condition,
we expect the feedback to be much less informative because of the very
small differences in payoffs for bids within one dollar of the optimal.
Finding a difference due to these payoff structures will demonstrate
that the payoff structures used in Experiment II are functionally
different and that the differences in expected values could have
produced differences in the earlier experiments had subjects chosen to
use this feedback information.
Method
Twenty-one subjects participated in this experiment. The procedures
used in this condition were the same as those used in the second
experiment except for the following changes: At the beginning of the
experiment, subjects were each given an initial balance of $6. These
subjects were given a smaller initial balance than those in Experiment
II to equalize the expected earnings of all subjects across all
conditions in both Experiments II and III. The instructions were
identical to those for the minimal information condition in Experiment
II. In particular, subjects were told that there was an optimal bid
between $0.00 and $6.00 and that their task was to find that bid. The
only change in procedure was that subjects received in each round an
amount exactly equal to the expected value of their payoffs given their
stated bids.
Results
The results of this experiment do show an effect of payoff structure
on accuracy. The mean absolute difference of bids from optimal was
higher for the flat payoffs than for the peaked payoffs (t(19) = 5.87, p
[less than] .0001). Figure 8 shows that subjects in the peaked payoff
structure condition were able to find the optimum rather quickly whereas
those in the flat payoff condition had more difficulty with this task.
However, there was improvement across rounds even for those in the flat
condition which indicates that subjects are sensitive to even small
differences of a penny or two when the feedback information is timely
and informative.
Experiment III clearly demonstrates that the two payoff structures
are functionally different. That these structures did not produce
different behavior in Experiment II suggests that subjects in the
transparent setting were able to choose the individually optimal bid on
the basis of the information provided and did not rely on the shape of
the payoff function to guide their decisions. Sufficient motivation was
provided even with a very flat payoff schedule; payoff dominance was
achieved.
VI. CONCLUSION
Experiment I demonstrates that the BDM mechanism is incentive
compatible within the domain of the payments typically offered to
laboratory subjects. Average bids (or offers) were not significantly
different from optimal, most bids were near the optimal bid, and
accuracy improved with experience.
In its basic form the BDM mechanism provides a task which is
cognitively simple but the experimenter may make this task more complex
and can also manipulate the payoff schedule easily. The results from
Experiment II suggest that subjects make optimal decisions even when
payoffs are flat if all of the information necessary for the decision
has been presented and the task is transparent. Further, when the task
is made opaque a steep payoff schedule is not sufficient to induce
optimal decision-making behavior. The failure to find a behavioral
effect attributable to payoff structure for the minimal information or
opaque condition in Experiment II is instructive. With only outcome
feedback equivalent to that received in the full information or
transparent conditions, subjects were unable to find the optimal bid and
were unable to improve with experience.
The two failures to detect effects of payoff structure in Experiment
II might be attributable either to lack of statistical power due to
small sample sizes or to the difference between the two payoff
structures being too small. However, Experiment III eliminates both
these alternative explanations by showing a reliable effect of payoff
structures when uncertainty was removed from the BDM feedback. That is,
in Experiment III when the feedback was made timely and informative, the
two payoff structures were sufficiently different to produce behavioral
differences. This result not only increases confidence in the results of
Experiment II but also suggests that Harrison's concerns about
payoff dominance may be important in experimental settings in which the
only feasible player strategy is to search for an optimal bid (e.g.,
Coursey & Mason [1987]) rather than compute an optimal bid from the
information provided in the experimental instructions.
Finally, the experiments undertaken here demonstrate that the BDM
mechanism is a reliable preference elicitation mechanism and may be
useful in other applications. Incentive compatibility is a desirable
property for bidding mechanisms used both in real-word market
institutions and in decision-making experiments in economics and
psychology. However, theoretical proofs notwithstanding, incentive
compatibility must always remain an empirical issue. The cognitive
complexity of understanding the bidding mechanism may be an important
determinant of whether it is incentive compatible in practice. Also,
cognitive complexity may be important in determining whether payoff
dominance is a key issue. For the very transparent BDM, payoff dominance
does not appear to be an issue; however, Smith and Walker [1993] and
Irwin, McClelland, and Schulze [1992] have shown that bidding
performance improves with increased experimental incentives for a
variety of market-like auction methods, all of which are likely more
opaque to subjects than the BDM.
An ideal bidding mechanism should be incentive compatible but also
cognitively transparent; further, it should be neutral in the sense of
not providing unintentional feedback about what the subject ought to be
doing. The results of these experiments suggest that the BDM bidding
mechanism satisfies both these criteria.
We would like to thank the Sloan Foundation and the Russell Sage Foundation for financial support for this research. We received helpful
comments on this paper from William Neilson and an anonymous referee.
All opinions expressed herein and any errors are, of course, the sole
responsibility of the authors. Address correspondence to Michael McKee,
Department of Economics, University of New Mexico, Albuquerque, NM
87131.
1. The version of the BDM for willingness to accept (WTA)
compensation to give up or forego a good is easily obtained by
substituting "sell" for "buy" and "less
than" for "greater than" in the description in the text.
2. The proof for the WTA case is analogous.
3. The instructions are available on request.
4. The BDM mechanism has been criticized for its reliance on the
Independence Axiom of Expected Utility Theory (see Holt [1986] and
Keller et al. [1993]). Most applications of the BDM mechanism place
subjects in the position of purchasing lottery tickets with obviously
uncertain payoffs. That application of the BDM mechanism represents a
compound lottery and is inappropriate for testing expected utility
theory. In the current application, it is only the preference revelation
facet of the BDM mechanism that is being evaluated. There is no risk
associated with the good being purchased thus subjects do not face a
compound lottery.
5. Bohm et al. [1997], demonstrate the importance of selecting the
range of permissible bid values in relation to the range of valuations
held by the subjects. They note that allowing bids significantly outside
the range of individual values may compromise the mechanism. In our
design that is not a problem since the ranges overlap almost completely.
6. To avoid non-independence problems due to repeated bids, a mean
was computed for each subject across the 15 rounds so that in the
analysis there was only one data value for each subject.
REFERENCES
Becker, G. M., M. H. DeGroot, and J. Marschak. "Measuring
Utility By a Single-response Sequential Method." Behavioral
Science, July 1964, 226-32.
Bohm, P., J. Linden, and J. Sonnegard. "Eliciting Reservation
Prices: Becker-DeGroot-Marschak Mechanisms vs Markets." Economic
Journal, forthcoming 1997.
Coursey, D. L., and C. Mason. "Investigations Concerning the
Dynamics of Consumer Behavior in Uncertain Environments." Economic
Inquiry, October 1987, 549-54.
Gregory, R. "Interpreting Measures of Economic Loss: Evidence
from Contingent Valuation and Experimental Studies." Journal of
Environmental Economics and Management, December 1986, 325-37.
Grether, D. M., and C. R. Plott. "Economic Theory of Choice and
the Preference Reversal Phenomenon." American Economic Review, June
1979, 623-38.
Harrison, G. W. "Theory and Misbehavior of First-price
Auctions." American Economic Review, September 1989, 749-62.
-----. "Theory and Misbehavior of First-price Auctions:
Reply." American Economic Review, December 1992, 1,426-43.
-----. "Expected Utility Theory and the Experimentalists."
Empirical Economics, 19(2) 1994, 223-53.
Holt, C. "Preference Reversals and the Independence Axiom."
American Economic Review, June 1986, 508-15.
Irwin, J. R., G. H. McClelland, and W. D. Schulze. "Hypothetical
and Real Consequences in Experimental Auctions for Insurance Against Low
Probability Risks." Journal of Behavioral Decision Making, 2(1),
1992, 107-16.
Kahneman, D., J. L. Knetsch, and R. H. Thaler. "Experimental
Tests of the Endowment Effect and the Coase Theorem." Journal of
Political Economy, December 1990, 1,325-48.
Karni, E., and Z. Safra. "Preference Reversals and the
Observability of Preferences by Experimental Methods."
Econometrica, May 1987, 675-85.
Keller, L. R., U. Segal, and T. Wang. "The
Becker-DeGroot-Marschak Mechanism and Generalized Utility Theories:
Theoretical Predictions and Empirical Observations." Theory and
Decision, March 1993, 83-97.
Knetsch, J. L. "The Endowment Effect and Evidence of
Nonreversible Indifference Curves." American Economic Review,
December 1989, 1277-84.
Lichtenstein, S, and P. Slovic. "Reversals of Preference Between
Bids and Choices in Gambling Decisions." Journal of Experimental
Psychology, July-August 1971, 46-55.
McClelland, G. H., and W. D. Schulze. "The Disparity Between
Willingness-to-Pay Versus Willingness-To-Accept as a Framing
Effect," in Frontiers of Mathematical Psychology: Essays in Honor
of Clyde Coombs, edited by D. R. Brown & J. E. K. Smith. New York:
Springer-Verlag, 1991, 166-92.
Shogren, J. et al. "Resolving Differences in Willingness to Pay and Willingness to Accept." American Economic Review, March 1994,
255-70.
Smith, V. L. "Microeconomic Systems as an Experimental
Science." American Economic Review, December 1982, 923-55.
-----. "Rational Choice: The Contrast Between Economics and
Psychology." Journal of Political Economy, August 1991, 877-97.
Smith, V. L., and J. M. Walker. "Monetary Rewards and Decision
Cost in Experimental Economics." Economic Inquiry, April 1993,
245-61.
Irwin: Assistant Professor, Stem School of Business, New York
University, New York, Phone 1-212-998-0511 Fax 1-212-995-4006 E-mail
irwin@fourps.wharton.upenn.edu
McClelland: Professor, Department of Psychology, University of
Colorado, Boulder, Phone 1-303-492-8122 Fax 1-303-492-5580 E-mail
gary.mcclelland@colorado.edu
McKee: Associate Professor, Department of Economics University of New
Mexico, Albuquerque Phone 1-505-277-1960, Fax 1-505-277-9445 E-mail
mckee@unm.edu
Schulze: Professor, Department of Agricultural Economics, Cornell
University, Ithaca, Phone 1-607-255-9611 Fax 1-607-255-9984, E-mail
wds3@cornell.edu
Norden: Consultant, Lodestone Research, Loveland Phone
1-970-663-1055, Fax 1-970-663-2595 E-mail elizabeth._norden@hp.com