Leviathan at bay: constitutional versus political controls on government.
Sutter, Daniel
A dependence on the people is, no doubt, the primary control on
government; but experience has taught mankind the necessity of auxiliary
precautions.
- James Madison, Federalist No. 51
I. INTRODUCTION
Citizens possess two main methods of controlling politicians,
elections and constitutional constraints. The British system of
parliamentary supremacy and America's written constitution with
judicial review by the Supreme Court reflect the contrasting approaches.
Political theorists continue to debate the relative effectiveness of
constitutional and electoral controls on politicians. These controls
seemingly are substitutes: if elections effectively control politicians,
constitutional constraints become redundant and can only lower the
effectiveness of government.
Public choice theory separately examines elections and constitutions.
An extensive literature beginning with Barro [1973] analyzes electoral
controls, but has not considered constitutional controls. Constitutional
political economy examines various constraints on politicians (Buchanan
[1987], Brennan and Buchanan [1980]), yet assumes elections
insufficiently control politicians. Recent studies of term limits (i.e.,
Dick and Lott [1993]) represent one effort to analyze constitutional and
electoral controls together.
I integrate constitutional limits on government into a model of
electoral control of politicians. My model features two types of
politicians, knaves who abuse discretionary powers at their disposal,
and angels who never misuse power. Citizens delegate a variable amount
of discretionary power to government, which provides benefits if
properly employed but lowers welfare if abused. The interaction between
constitutional limits and elections is complicated; constraints
complement electoral controls based on politician payoffs (selection and
incentive effects) while the screening and sorting effects substitute
for constraints.
I proceed in this paper as follows. Section II describes the
citizen's constitutional delegation of authority to government and
incorporates electoral screening of candidates. Optimal delegation of
power increases with the effectiveness of screening, but unless
screening is perfect, constitutional limits help keep Leviathan at bay.
Section III endogenizes the candidate pool and examines the selection
effect constitutional controls. The composition of the candidate pool
depends on delegation to government, which has implications for the
propensity of politicians to pursue their personal self-interest. While
constitutional political economy relies heavily on the threat from
knavish politicians, many political observers contend that most
politicians sincerely pursue the public interest as they perceive it. I
show that politicians' observed honesty does not invalidate the
argument for chains.
Section IV considers the ability of repeated elections to sort knaves
out of office. The sorting effect increases optimal delegation of power
to government, but constraints can still play a useful role if knaves
try for office and electoral review is not continuous. Section V allows
knaves to act opportunistically and considers the incentive effect of
retrospective voting and post-political incentives. Constitutional
constraints complement electoral incentives by limiting opportunistic
knaves' gain from shirking. The final section concludes.
II. CONSTITUTIONAL CHOICE IN A MODEL OF ANGELS AND KNAVES
I adopt a principal-agent view of government. A representative
citizen selects an agent to exercise the powers of government on her
behalf. The representative citizen framework abstracts from differences
amongst the population about the actions the agent should undertake. The
control of politicians becomes difficult in the absence of a
"common interest," both positively and normatively.
Consequently, models of electoral control typically employ this
assumption.(1)
The agency model assumes a conflict of interest between the principal
and agent. The agent can take some action (shirking) which advances his
interest at the principal's expense. Political misbehavior in a
representative citizen model might involve seeking personal financial
gain, allocating public projects on the basis of bribes or friendship
instead of efficiency, or violating the rights of political opponents. I
assume two types of politicians exist so political institutions can have
screening, sorting, and selection effects. A politician's type is
private information. Politicians differ in their willingness to misuse
the powers of office (shirk): angels never misuse power, while knaves
will use the powers of government for their own purposes.(2) Angels are
internally constrained; guilt might result in a bribe lowering their
utility. Knaves lack the angels' internal constraint, so
misappropriated funds raise their utility. While none of us may be above
considerations of self-interest, casual empiricism suggests people
differ in their willingness to pursue their self-interest at the expense
of others. My angels are not totally selfless; their decision to pursue
office in section III depends on the expected payoff of public service.
Knaves always abuse power, except in section V where they behave
opportunistically.
The representative citizen's constitutional choice is the
delegation of authority to a single governmental agent.(3) Government
requires authority to provide benefits to citizens; but the misuse of
power by a knave harms the citizen. Both the benefit of proper use and
the cost of misuse of power increase with the authority government
possesses. A well-intentioned politician in my model faces no difficulty
in serving the representative citizen.(4)
Let x be the amount of authority delegated to government, normalized
so that x [element of] [0, 1]. If x = 0 government lacks authority,
while x = 1 is unlimited government. I do not consider potential
problems enforcing a constraint on government; that is, the choice of x
binds. The elements of a constitution captured in x include allowable
tax bases and rates, the conditions for taking private property, and
procedural rights for individuals in legal disputes with the government
(due process). The [TABULAR DATA FOR TABLE I OMITTED] citizen's net
benefit when authority is used properly to produce public goods is B(x),
with B(0) = O, B[prime] [greater than] 0, and B[double prime] [less
than] 0. Let T(x) be the citizen's cost if power is misused, with
T(0) = 0, T[prime] [greater than] 0, and T[double prime] [greater than]
0. Further, assume B[prime] (0) [greater than] T[prime] (0) = 0. Table I
summarizes notation.
I initially assume an exogenous candidate pool consisting of n angels
and m knaves. Let [Pi] be the equilibrium probability an angel holds
office. Elections initially select a candidate at random from the pool
to take office, so [Pi] = n/(m + n). The selection of several candidates
from the pool does not alter n/(n + m).
The representative citizen chooses x to maximize
[Pi] [multiplied by] B(x) - (1 - [Pi]) [multiplied by] T(x),
The first order condition for an interior solution is
(1) [Pi] [multiplied by] B[prime](x) - (1 - [Pi]) [multiplied by]
T[prime](x),
Let [x.sub.0] be the optimal amount of discretion. Figure 1
illustrates the constitutional choice. Optimal delegation equates the
marginal benefit of proper use of authority with the marginal cost of
misuse. B[double prime] [less than] 0 and T[double prime] [greater than]
0 ensure satisfaction of the second order condition. The candidate pool
must contain some angels to rule out a no authority corner solution;
B[prime](0) [greater than] T[prime](0) = 0 and [Pi] [greater than] 0
together imply [x.sub.0] [greater than] 0. A no constraint corner
solution ([x.sub.0] = 1) occurs if B[prime](1) [greater than or equal
to] (1 - [Pi]) [multiplied by] T[prime](1)/[Pi]. A vanishing marginal
benefit of delegation or unbounded marginal cost of abuse, B[prime](1) =
0 or T[prime](1) = [infinity], rules [x.sub.0] = 1 out. I wish to ensure
a nontrivial constitutional choice problem. Discretion becomes worthless
so limiting government is costless if B[prime](1) = 0. But [x.sub.0] = 1
when elections perform no meaningful control function means
constitutional constraints can never be optimal. So I impose B[prime](1)
[less than] (1 - [Pi]) [multiplied by] T[prime](1) to initially rule out
unlimited government.
Electoral campaigns might reveal a candidate's knavishness.
Suppose a candidate chosen at random out of the pool is screened and if
identified as an angel, assumes office. Selection continues until a
candidate passes screening. Assume the campaign produces a noisy
information signal regarding a candidate's type. Let [s.sub.k]
([s.sub.a]) be the probability of incorrectly identifying a knave
(angel). An angel takes office unless mistyped while a knave passes
screening only if mistyped. The probability an angel holds office with
screening is
(2) [[Pi].sub.s] = n [center dot] (1 - [s.sub.a])/[n [center dot] (1
- [s.sub.a]) + m [center dot] [s.sub.k]].
Figure 1 illustrates the effect of screening; the marginal benefit
curve shifts up and the marginal cost curve shifts down. Let [x.sub.s]
be optimal delegation with screening. Screening increases the
probability an angel holds office as long as 1 - [s.sub.a] [greater
than] [s.sub.k], and hence [x.sub.s] [greater than] [x.sub.0]. The
screening function of elections substitutes for constitutional
constraint. Since [[Pi].sub.s] [greater than] [Pi], for some values of
B[prime](1) and T[prime](1) a corner solution may be optimal with
screening. But even the most ardent democrats stress that elections do
more than randomly select among candidates. Consequently an interior
solution without screening must be robust to a wide range of parameter
values. A high marginal cost of abuse for close to unlimited government,
T[prime](1) [approximately equal to] [infinity], accomplishes this. But
T[prime](1) [approximately equal to] implies that [[Pi].sub.s] must
equal 1 for x [x.sub.s] = 1. And [[Pi].sub.s] = 1 requires [s.sub.k] =
0, so as long as knaves slip through electoral screening, some
constitutional constraint on government remains optimal.
III. DELEGATION AND ELECTIONS WITH AN ENDOGENOUS CANDIDATE POOL
Electoral screening and constitutional delegation affect the
incentives for politicians to pursue office, undermining the assumption
of an exogenous candidate pool. I now endogenously determine the
candidate pool, which requires specification of the payoffs from
political and private sector employment for knaves and angels. Limiting
delegation helps induce knaves to select out of politics.
Candidates forego private sector earnings when running for office.
Let E be the opportunity cost of candidacy, which I set equal for each
type politician. Angels and knaves receive payoffs in office
proportional to the benefit of public goods production or the social
cost of abuse, u [center dot]B(x) and v [center dot] T(x)
respectively.(5) A mixed candidate pool requires payoff heterogeneity
amongst at least one type of politicians. I assume that all angels have
the same coefficient u while v is distributed over [0, V] with K(v)
knaves having a coefficient greater than or equal to v.
Candidate selection is as in section II. Potential politicians decide
to enter the pool. A politician not selected out of the pool or
identified by screening as a knave receives a payoff of zero. Let q be
the probability of selection for screening for a member of the pool
(more than one candidate may be screened). The expected payoffs from
candidacy for each type of politician are
Angels: q [center dot] (1 - [s.sub.a]) [center dot] u [center dot]
B(x)
Knaves: q [center dot] [s.sub.k] [center dot] v [center dot] T(x).
The politicians with the highest expected payoffs join the pool. Of
importance is the value of v which equates knaves' expected payoff
of candidacy with angels', [v.sup.*], which is
(3) [v.sup.*] = (1 - [s.sub.a]) [center dot] u [center dot]
(B(x)/[[s.sub.k] [center dot] T(x)]
Only knaves with v [greater than or equal to] [v.sup.*] might become
candidates. Three cases are possible. If [v.sup.*] [greater than] V no
knave becomes a candidate, so all politicians are angels and [Pi] = 1.
If [v.sup.*] [less than or equal to] V then K([v.sup.*]) knaves would
become candidates before any angels join the pool. K([v.sup.*]) may be
sufficiently large that q [center dot] (1 - [s.sub.a]) [center dot] u
[center dot] B(x) [less than] E, in which case the candidate pool is all
knaves and [Pi] = 0. If K([v.sup.*]) is not too large, angels enter
until q [center dot] (1 - [s.sub.a]) [center dot] u [center dot] B(x) =
E and we have a mixed pool.
The probability an angel holds office is now a function of authority
delegated to government, [Pi](x). Suppose we begin with a mixed pool as
soon as x is large enough to attract candidates;(6) this parallels the
exogenous mixed pool in section II. If an increase in x increases
[v.sup.*], fewer knaves become candidates, while if [v.sup.*] falls
fewer angels campaign for office. For fixed values of s, and [s.sub.k],
[Pi] then changes with [v.sup.*]. The derivative of [v.sup.*] with
respect to x is
(4) d[v.sup.*] / dx = {(1 - [s.sub.a]) [center dot] u [center dot]
[T(x) [center dot] B[prime]x)
- B(x) [center dot] T[prime](x)]}/{[s.sub.k] [center dot]
[[T(x)][Xi].sup.2]]}
The sign of d[v.sup.*]/dx is the same as the sign of the bracketed
term in the numerator, which is ambiguous. The increase in benefits from
proper use of power may initially make public office relatively more
attractive to angels. But declining marginal benefit of public goods
provision and increasing marginal cost of misuse imply that increased
discretion eventually has an adverse effect on the composition of the
pool. Figure 2 illustrates the likely relationship between delegation
and [Pi].
An endogenous pool complicates the citizen's constitutional
choice problem. The first order condition for optimal delegation becomes
(5) [Pi](x) [center dot] B[prime](x) = [1 - [Pi](x)] [center dot]
T[prime](x) - [Pi][prime](x) [center dot] [B(x) + T(x)].
The final term in equation (5) reflects the impact of delegation on
the composition of the pool, this is an added benefit if [Pi][prime]
[greater than] 0 but an extra cost if [Pi][prime] [less than] 0. Optimal
delegation with an endogenous pool, [x.sub.e], likely involves
[Pi][prime]([x.sub.e]) [less than] 0. Although [Pi][prime]([x.sub.e])
[greater than] 0 cannot be ruled out at this level of generality,
equation (5) implies this requires a high marginal cost of misusing
power. But equation (4) implies that a large value of T[prime] results
in an increasingly knavish candidate pool. Constitutional constraints
can strengthen selection effects by limiting a knave's reason to
pursue office.(7)
The potential for harm if the discretionary powers of the state fall
into the "wrong" hands is a major argument for constitutional
constraints. As Hume [1964, III, 117-8] wrote, "in contriving any
system of government, and fixing the several checks and controls of the
constitution, every man ought to be supposed a knave, and to have no
other end, in all his actions, than private interest." Brennan and
Buchanan [1985, 55] defend the Leviathan model of government on
worst-case grounds. Constitutional political economy seems dependent on
the empirical assumption of a knavish candidate pool. Many political
scientists and close observers of politics, however, challenge the
validity of this assumption. For instance, Mikva notes
The politicians and other people I have known in public life just do
not fit the "rent-seeking" egoist model that the public choice
theorists offer. ... Not even my five terms in the Illinois state
legislature ... nor my five terms in the United States Congress,
prepared me for the villains of the public choice literature. [1988,
167](8)
Selection effects helps reconcile these views. The delegation of
authority to government affects the composition of the pool of
politicians. We cannot infer the character of politicians without chains
from the average character of politicians under chains. Indeed, the
candidate pool with optimal delegation can consist entirely of angels if
[v.sup.*] [greater than] V, making constitutional constraints appear
inconsistent with the observed character of politicians.(9) The evil
knaves do motivates constitutional constraints, yet in equilibrium only
angels may be chained.
IV. REPEATED ELECTIONS: SORTING KNAVES OUT OF OFFICE
Citizens can vote unsatisfactory politicians out of office. I turn
now to the interaction between electoral sorting and constitutional
limits.(10) A tension exists between the screening and sorting functions
of elections: voters must accept the challenger if they want to dump the
incumbent. Since my interest is the interaction between electoral and
constitutional controls, I simply assume elections cannot simultaneously
sort and screen.
Sorting requires repeated elections. Let a politician's time
horizon be h [greater than] 1 periods with an election each period.
Repeated elections here serve a pure sorting purpose; section V allows
elections an incentive effect by letting knaves behave
opportunistically. The remainder of this paper assumes an exogenous
candidate pool containing m knaves and n angels. Citizens directly and
perfectly observe a politician's behavior, so first period
performance perfectly signals type.(11) Citizens return any incumbent
who has not abused power and vote out of office any politician who has.
Candidates in the first period of their political careers fill all
open seats. The fraction of terms an angel holds office with sorting,
[[Pi].sub.r] is
(6) [[Pi].sub.r] = n [center dot] h/(n [center dot] h + m).
Sorting increases the proportion of terms served by angels,
[[Pi].sub.r] [greater than] [[Pi].sub.0], because angels serve longer
than knaves. The increase in [[Pi].sub.r] increases optimal delegation,
[x.sub.r] [greater than] [x.sub.0]; thus electoral sorting substitutes
for constitutional constraints. The ex post nature of sorting (it
identifies knaves when they shirk) limits its effectiveness. Only
constitutional constraints prevent entirely the possibly substantial
cost of abuse of (nearly) unlimited discretion. The condition which
rules out a corner solution without sorting, T[prime](1) [approximately
equal to] [infinity], also ensures [x.sub.r] = 1 is not optimal with
sorting.
Increasing the frequency of elections or lengthening political
careers improves the efficiency of sorting; equation (6) shows that
[[Pi].sub.r] [right arrow] 1 as h [right arrow] [infinity]. But
continuous electoral review is not optimal since elections are costly
(Barro [1973]).(12) As long as knaves remain in the candidate pool and
electoral review is not instantaneous, [[Pi].sub.r] [less than] 1, which
ensures [x.sub.r] [less than] 1 if T[prime](1) [approximately equal to]
[infinity].
V. INCENTIVE EFFECTS OF ELECTIONS AND CONSTITUTIONAL CONSTRAINTS
Repeated elections make tenure dependent on behavior. Assuming knaves
always abuse power renders reelection incapable of deterring shirking. I
now consider opportunistic knaves, who abuse power only when this raises
expected utility. Early models of electoral control focused primarily on
the incentive effect of retrospective voting (Barro [1973], Ferejohn
[1986]).
Politicians now have a two period time horizon. Citizens vote
retrospectively, first period politicians fill open seats, and electoral
competition does not screen candidates for office. Since an
opportunistic knave may refrain from misusing power to secure a second
term in office, satisfactory first period performance no longer
necessarily identifies an angel. All knaves shirk in their second term
in office. The last period problem complicates the control of shirking
through retrospective voting, but is not crucial in the present model
because angels always behave. The probability of shirking in period two
when incumbents are reelected equals the fraction of knaves in the pool,
[Pi] = m/(m + n).
Interpret the payoffs specified in section III now as per period
payoffs. Let R be a knave's payoff in office when not shirking and
[Beta] [less than] 1 be the utility discount factor. A knave who shirks
in period one returns to private sector employment at a wage of E in
period two. A knave refrains from shirking in the first period if
(7) R [greater than or equal to] (1 - [Beta]) [center dot] v [center
dot] T(x) + [Beta] [center dot] E.
Holding office must provide a higher payoff than private sector
employment, R [greater than] E, for a knave to behave. The coefficient v
is distributed over the interval [0, V]. Reelection is an ineffectual
incentive for the knaves who value shirking the most.
Allowing knaves to respond to incentive effects increases the
proportion of terms in which power is used as intended, [[Pi].sub.i]
[greater than] [[Pi].sub.r], which, everything else equal, allows a
loosening of constitutional constraints, [x.sub.i] [greater than]
[x.sub.r]. The incentive effect of elections seems to substitute for
constitutional constraints. But an increase in discretion increases the
gain from shirking. With x sufficiently large, equation (7) is violated
and knaves misuse power when first elected to office, as previously
assumed. Constraints complement the incentive effect of elections by
limiting the knave's gain from misusing power.
Post-political incentives can control last term shirking by
politicians: making a pension or criminal prosecution contingent on performance can supplement electoral defeat as a deterrent. Lott [1990]
demonstrates that post-political affect how often final term
representatives vote, the form of last period shirking identified by
Lott [1987].(13) But the benefit from shirking increases with x, while
several factors limit the extent to which the punishment can increase
with x. First, an upper bound on punishment exists, after which the
marginal penalty must be zero. Second, timing could limit the maximum
punishment; life imprisonment is less of a penalty for an elderly former
politician. Third, the penalty is discounted while the benefits of
shirking occur now. Impatient knaves, the ones least likely to respond
to electoral incentives, are similarly unlikely to respond to penalties.
Finally, a politician might avoid prosecution by going into exile.
Unlimited delegation tends again to overwhelm the incentive for knaves
to behave.
VI. DISCUSSION
Constitutional constraints and elections have been regarded as
substitutes in preventing the misuse of power by politicians. My
analysis indicates a complicated interaction between constraints and
elections. Constraints complement electoral controls which affect
politicians' payoffs (selection and incentive effects) while
electoral controls preventing undesirable politicians from holding
office (screening and sorting effects) substitute for constraints.
Constitutional controls are designed to prevent abuse of power, while
the sorting and incentive effects require on-the-job failure to remove
politicians from office. Preventive measures are most appropriate to
prevent abuses of power which result in significant, irreversible costs
in a short period of time. Screening and sorting do not reduce the
probability of the abuse of power to zero if screening is imperfect or
if knaves remain in the candidate pool. If the marginal cost of abuse of
unlimited power is very high, constraints on government remain optimal.
The framework of my model is favorable electoral controls. The common
interest framework rules out possible disagreements among voters in
directing their elected officials. Differences of opinion can lead to
the nonexistence of equilibrium under majority voting, creating
additional discretion for politicians. The well-intentioned politician
causes no harm in this model. Hence constraints impose a very real cost
on citizens if elections insure good politicians hold office. And
detection of shirking occurs with certainty by the end of one term in
office. Relaxing these assumptions strengthens the importance of
constitutional constraints. Emergence of a role for constraints in an
environment so conducive to electoral control is surprising.(14)
Delegating extensive authority to government indirectly undercuts the
effectiveness of elections by increasing a knave's payoff.
Delegation could additionally directly undermine electoral controls.
Citizens may be unable to enforce any controls on a politician with
sufficient power (to expropriate, jail or exile opponents without
trial). By subverting democracy politicians can delay (perhaps forever)
the imposition of electoral punishment. Ferdinand Marcos declared
martial law in 1972 and did not face a competitive election for 14 years
Constitutional limits have a clear advantage over elections on this
score.
1. See Barro [1973], Lott and Reed [1989], Banks and Sundaram [1993],
Reed [1994]. Ferejohn [1986] and Dixit, Grossman and Helpman [1997]
examine electoral control in the absence of a common interest. The
impact of a super-majority voting rule (Buchanan and Tullock [1962]) and
the protection of minorities, two common elements of a constitution,
cannot be analyzed within a representative citizen framework.
2. Coate and Morris [1995] and Brennan and Hamlin [1995] employ a
similar categorization of politicians. An alternative form of
heterogeneity has politicians differ in their cost of producing public
goods (Banks and Sundaram [1993], Reed [1994]).
3. A single agent avoids the issue of separation of powers. Sutter
and Tabarrok [1997] extend the model to multiple agents.
4. An alternative argument for constitutional constraints is the
inability of the best-intentioned public servants to raise welfare.
5. An equal opportunity cost across types ensures that selection
effects result from the payoffs of holding office. Perhaps, as Brennan
and Hamlin [1995] argue, private sector employers can effectively
monitor their employees. Good politicians' payoffs in Coate and
Morris [1995] similarly depend on the value of benefits generated.
6. For sufficiently small values of x the candidate pool may be empty
since B(0) = T(0) = 0.
7. Lott and Reed [1989] discuss the possible selection effects of
electoral sorting. Elections reduce the period over which a power can be
misused, while constitutional controls eliminate the opportunity to
misuse this power altogether. The difference is important if knavish
politicians value highly even a limited opportunity to misuse power.
8. For similar criticisms see Kelman [1987], Etzioni [1988, 51-63],
and Kelman [1988, 217-23].
9. Empirical support exists for a largely angelic candidate pool;
Dougan and Munger [1989] for instance find no evidence of widespread
shirking in their study of Senate voting.
10. Lott and Reed [1989], Banks and Sundaram [1993], and Reed [1994]
include a sorting effect of repeated elections.
11. Alternatively citizens might observe an outcome which depends on
an unobserved exogenous variable as well as the politician's
actions. Imperfect observation of action introduces noise in to the
performance signal and reduces the effectiveness of electoral sorting.
12. This conclusion relies on the assumption of perfect observation
of shirking by voters. A shorter term reduces the cost to voters of
misbehavior, and could produce an offsetting decrease in effort exerted
monitoring politicians' performance.
13. Lott [1987] previously showed that a last period did not affect
how representatives vote when they vote. Let p be the utility value of
the punishment imposed for misusing government power, which is imposed
with certainty and only on actual shirkers after completion of the term
in office. A knave in his second term in office shirks if u [center dot]
T(x) - [Beta] [center dot] p [greater than or equal to] R.
14. On the other hand, I have examined the aspects of electoral
control separately. Their combined effect exceeds the effect of any one
component. The screening effect of elections, for instance, strengthens
the selection effect.
REFERENCES
Banks, Jeffrey S. and Rangarajan K. Sundaram. "Long-Lived
Principals, Short-Lived Agents" Manuscript, University of
Rochester, 1993.
Barro, Robert "The Control of Politicians: An Economic
Model." Public Choice, 14, 1973, 19-42.
Brennan, Geoffrey and James M. Buchanan. The Power to Tax. Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press, 1980.
-----. The Reason of Rules. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press,
1985.
Brennan, Geoffrey and Alan Hamlin. "Economizing on Virtue."
Constitutional Political Economy, 6(1), 1995, 35-56.
Buchanan, James M. "The Constitution of Economic Policy."
American Economic Review, September 1987, 243--50.
Buchanan, James M. and Gordon Tullock. The Calculus of Consent. Ann
Arbor: University of Michigan Press, 1962.
Coate, Stephen and Stephen Morris. "On the Form of Transfers to
Special Interests" Journal of Political Economy, December 1995,
1,210-35.
Dick, Andrew R. and John R. Lott, Jr. "Reconciling Voters'
Behavior with Legislative Term Limits." Journal of Public
Economics, 50, 1993, 1-14.
Dixit, Avinash, Gene M. Grossman and Elhanan Helpman. "Common
Agency and Coordination: General Theory and Application to Government
Policy Making." Journal of Political Economy, August 1997, 752-69
Dougan, William R. and Michael C. Munger. "The Rationality of
Ideology." Journal of Law and Economics, April 1989, 119-42.
Etzioni, Amitai. The Moral Dimension: Toward a New Economics. New
York: Free Press, 1988.
Ferejohn, John. "Incumbent Performance and Electoral
Control." Public Choice, 50, 1986, 5-25.
Hamilton, Alexander, James Madison and John Jay. The Federalist
Papers. New York: Mentor Books, 1962.
Hume, David. The Philosophical Works, Volume 3, edited by T. H. Green
and T. H. Grose. Darmstadt: Scientia Verlag Aalen, 1964.
Kelman, Mark. "On Democracy-Bashing: A Skeptical Look at the
Theoretical and 'Empirical' Practice of the Public Choice
Movement." Virginia Law Review, 74(2), 1988, 199-273.
Kelman, Steven. "'Public Choice' and Public
Spirit." The Public Interest, 87, 1987, 80-94.
Lott, John R., Jr. "Political Cheating." Public Choice, 52,
1987, 169-86.
-----. "Attendance Rates, Political Shirking, and the Effect of
Post-Elective Employment." Economic Inquiry, 28, 1990, 133-50.
Lott, John, R., Jr. and W. Robert Reed. "Shirking and Sorting in
a Political Market with Finite-lived Politicians." Public Choice,
61, 1989, 75-96.
Mikva, Abner J. "Foreword." Virginia Law Review, 74(2),
1988, 167-77.
Reed, W. Robert. "A Retrospective Voting Model with
Heterogeneous Politicians." Economics and Politics, March 1994,
39-58.
Sutter, Daniel and Alexander Tabarrok. "Separation of Powers in
a Model of Angels and Knaves." Manuscript, University of Oklahoma,
1997.