The primacy of economics: an explanation of the comparative success of economics in the social sciences.
Demsetz, Harold
I
The strong export surplus economics maintains in its trade in ideas
and methods with the other social sciences is an important indicator of
the success of economics. Not much has been said about the source of
this success, but it has been attributed largely to advantages offered
to other social sciences by the economics tool kit. Thus, Gary Becker,
who has earned Commander-in-Chief ranking in the EEF (Economics
Expeditionary Forces), attributes the interdisciplinary influence of
economics to our relentless and unflinching application of "The
combined assumptions of maximizing behavior, market equilibrium, and
stable preferences..." (Becker [1976]). This view, but with a
different emphasis, is shared in by Hirshleifer [1985], my distinguished
colleague, who leads an active EEF group now reconnoitering
sociobiology:
What gives economics its imperialist invasive power is that our
analytical categories - scarcity, cost, preferences, opportunities, etc.
- are truly universal in applicability. Even more important is our
structured organization of these concepts into the distinct yet
intertwined processes of optimization on the individual decision level
and equilibrium on the social level of analysis. (p. 53)
The emphasis here is on the broad scope of phenomena that can be
explained with our tool kit. Such breadth suggests the possibility of
unifying the social sciences in an economics-led hegemony.
Brief statements such as these cannot be taken as adequate
representations of full views, but there is a disposition among most
economists to accept the interdisciplinary influence of economics as a
measure of its success and to identify its tool kit as the source in
this success. The most important exception is R. H. Coase [1977], who
doubts that the interdisciplinary influence of economics will continue.
He believes the economics tool kit is easily mastered by practitioners
of other social sciences when they find it useful. As Coase judges the
situation, a sustained influence from economics requires that economics
and the other social sciences share interests in the same problems.
The nub of the disagreement between Coase and those, like Becker and
Hirshleifer, who remain optimistic about a continuing strong influence
from economics, turns on two issues that are not discussed explicitly.
One relates to the definition of a "problem." Those who are
optimistic seem to be distinguishing between problems according to whether their solutions do or do not depend importantly on scarcity and
maximizing behavior. Interpreted this way, many problems across the
social sciences are of the same type. Coase, on the other hand,
distinguishes between problems according to differences in the factual
knowledge needed to understand them. For Coase, understanding the firm
is a different problem from understanding the marriage relationship
because factual knowledge about one does not transfer to the other. For
Becker, the essential similarity between these problems rests in utility
maximization subject to constraints.
This difference in interpretation raises a second issue, one that is
more substantive. Coase's view is that the tools of one social
science discipline, in this case economics, are easily learned by
practitioners of another, but that factual knowledge is not. Those
optimistic about the interdisciplinary influence of economics implicitly
have the view that mastering the tools of economics is more difficult
than Coase presumes; repeated practice in their use is needed to become
their master. It is difficult to judge which side has the best case. I
am even puzzled as to how to define a researcher's discipline if he
or she is trained in the tools of one social science and applies them to
problems in another. One possibility is to determine whether the
researcher's work appears in economics journals or in the journals
of other social science disciplines. I am most familiar with interactive
work between law and economics. Persons working in this
interdisciplinary area but who were trained initially in economics seem
to be publishing disproportionately in law journals. This would seem to
mean that they are mastering the facts of rules of law and of the cases
that help determine these; if true, this would seem to support the view
of optimists rather than that of Coase. On the other hand, economists in
law schools are being replaced rapidly by the increasing number of law
professors who have been trained in the tools of economics, and this
supports Coase's view.
The disagreement we have been discussing is relevant to the success
of economics if this is measured by the interdisciplinary influence. The
criterion of success adopted by the present paper differs from this.
Economics may be judged the more successful social science because it
has explained phenomena within its traditional boundaries better than
the other social sciences have explained phenomena within their
respective traditional boundaries. The primacy of economics may be
established in this sense even if economics had never influenced other
social sciences.
The relevance of this second notion of success can be illustrated by
referring again to the question of interdisciplinary influence. There is
undeniable truth in Becker's notion that we economists are much
more prone to use our tools to reformulate and investigate problems in
other disciplines than practitioners in these disciplines are prone to
extend the use of their tools to economics, but why are we more
confident than other social scientists? The answer, I believe, is that
economists have been more successful in dealing with the traditional
problems of their own discipline than other social scientists have been
with the problems in their own disciplines, and, so, we are led to a
source of primacy different from interdisciplinary influence - success
within the traditional boundaries of a discipline. Success breeds
confidence, and sometimes over-confidence.
A similar question can be raised about Hirshleifer's explanation
of the success of economics - that our analytical categories, scarcity,
cost, preferences, opportunities, are truly universal in applicability.
If this is so, why have these categories emerged from the study of
economic behavior and not from the study of behavior in the other social
sciences? Political science need not have waited for Buchanan and
Tullock's Calculus of Consent [1962] before applying
individualistic utility maximization to political problems.
Becker's Treatise on the Family [1981] need not have preceded the
use of costs and benefits by sociologists to study marriage. Legal
scholars, immersed as they have been in the study and resolution of
conflict, could have seen the relevance of scarcity constraints without
waiting for Tullock's Logic of the Law [1971] and Posner's
Economic Analysis of Law [1972] to instruct them. And why did Posner not
write his influential text before being exposed to economics?(1) That
economics has sparked these important works indicates that the tools of
economics, even if they are universally applicable, are not universally
easy to develop. They emerge from the study of the economic system, and
this brings us back again to a notion of primacy based on success within
the traditional boundaries of economics.
Even Coase's view forces us to consider this view of success.
The various social sciences may work on different problems, as Coase
claims, but why has economics been more successful with respect to its
problems than the other social sciences have been with respect to
theirs?
II
The source of the success of economics, I shall argue, lies in the
particular characteristics of the problem that has been central to its
inquiry during the last two centuries. These characteristics are not
equally present in the problems faced in other social sciences, and it
is this difference that accounts for the greater success of economics.
The problem I refer to is the search for an understanding and an
evaluative judgment of resource allocation in a complex, decentralized system. Because its solution rested on the role of prices in guiding
producers, investors, and households in the supply of and demand for
resources in the production of goods for use by those who played little
or no part in their production, it was the specialized and commercial
aspects of decentralization that were especially important, and this is
what I shall mean by decentralization.
This was not the only topic that interested economists, as the scope
of topics indexed in Smith's Wealth of Nations and Marshall's
Principles of Economics clearly reveals, but resolving the coordination
problem of a decentralized economic system was the primary goal of both
classical and neoclassical economists. Smith's Wealth of Nations,
Ricardo's Political Economy and Taxation, Mills' Principles of
Political Economy, Marshall's Principles of Economics, and
Pigou's Economics of Welfare all have the analysis of
decentralization as their main purpose.
The solution to the decentralization puzzle, hammered out during the
first 200 years of economics, is a remarkable achievement. Three aspects
of the inquiry have been instrumental in its solution and in causing
this solution to be so much a part of the success of economics. These
are (1) the large degree to which our understanding and evaluation of
the economic system is significantly affected by knowledge of how
decentralization works, (2) certain aspects of commercial activity that
facilitated the solution of the decentralization problem, and (3) the
successful modeling of the inquiry by our classical and neoclassical
predecessors.
As to the importance of the inquiry, it is clear that most positive
and normative questions about the economy, whether they are asked by
economists, media persons, or policy makers, can be answered only if one
understands how commercial activities are coordinated in a decentralized
economic system. These questions include a familiar litany of topics -
tariffs and international capital flows, taxes and growth, occupational
choice and wage differentials, entry barriers and price-cost margins,
agricultural programs and supplies of food stuffs, free agency and
professional baseball, shopping malls and externalities, and so on. An
understanding of decentralized commercial activity is required if one is
to deal sensibly with a large fraction of the economic phenomena in
which we and others are interested. It is not enough to understand how
an isolated individual, a Robinson Crusoe before Friday, allocates the
resources at his command so as to maximize his utility. Competition,
price formation, and decentralization itself form no part of the
solution to the Crusoe problem. Because of this, its solution is not
very important.
The aspects of the commercial decentralization problem that
facilitated its solution are two. Consider that whether a firm is
purchasing inputs or selling outputs, whether a household is allocating
income among goods or between consumption and saving, or whether the
investor is allocating wealth across firms and time, these commercial
activities offer the economist commensurate money value measures of
activity. Theoretical recognition of and empirical support for broad
generalizations are considerably more difficult if commensurate
measurement is absent. The inquiry into decentralization is advantaged
in this respect because commercial activity relies on monetary
measurement and because markets reveal the prices upon which such
measurement rests. The second facilitating aspect of commercial activity
is that it is guided to a large extent by wealth considerations. The
importance of this to the success of economics is discussed later.
Of course, the importance of a task signifies little for the success
of a discipline if the task remains unaccomplished. The third reason for
the success of economics is that the adroit modeling of its central
inquiry by our classical and neoclassical predecessors allowed it to be
substantially and successfully completed before World War II began.(2)
The classical economists framed the problem in terms of resource
allocation, and they demonstrated the importance of rational behavior
guided by self-interest and constrained by competition. Neoclassical
economists fine-tuned and clarified the analysis and made it more
powerful by adding marginalist logic.
The modeling avoided complications that if attended to would have
delayed discovery of the principles of decentralized coordination. The
avoided complications are those we associate with planning, a legal
system, crime, information cost, and non-commercial activity. No serious
attempt was made to deal with the state, the firm, or the household. The
characterizations of these institutional arrangements in neoclassical
theory are correctly described as "black boxes," but they
served a purpose by allowing economists to ignore planning, even of the
limited sort that takes place within firms and households, and this
enabled them to focus instead on coordination achieved through
impersonally determined prices. This focus is different from one that
seeks to understand the personal psychology of persons and the inner
workings of the institutions through which personal interactions take
place. Hence, tastes were taken as given and the organizations, such as
firms, through which persons interacted on a personal basis were
slighted.
Collusion was a mere footnote. And this is as it should have been,
since collusion substitutes managed coordination, or planning, for
decentralization. Crime and ignorance were also slighted. And this is as
it should have been. The key distinction between decentralization and
centralization is not the degree to which ignorance and crime are
present but the degree to which individuals are able to control others.
The closest approaches to the information problem came late in the
neoclassical period when Mises [1936] and Hayek [1945] wrote noteworthy,
but very general, comparisons of the quality of information available
through socialist and market organizations. The nature of private
ownership and of the legal system that underlies it were slighted
because the components of these that are essential to a discussion of
the price system relate primarily to only two features - the exclusivity
and exchangeability of private rights.
These premises restricted the inquiry to that of understanding
coordination in a private propertied, competitive, unplanned commercial
system characterized by specialized activities and populated by
well-informed, law-abiding, self-interested, rational persons who are
strangers to each other but who exchange goods and services.
This conceptualization has been repeatedly criticized for excessively
abstracting from reality. The criticism has been answered by defending
abstraction (Friedman [1953]). Two notions underlie the defense. One is
that a model's power to predict and not its realism is the arbiter
of its usefulness. The second is that abstraction from reality is
essential if a theory is to offer generalizable predictions.
I have no great disagreements about this, but my topic forces me to
demur in some respects. Predictive power is an important arbiter of a
theory's success, but this does not answer the substantive
question. Is predictive power enhanced or impaired by abstraction?
Abstraction is necessary for generalizations, but the more useful
generalizations derive from the slighting of aspects of the problem
thought to be unimportant and not from those thought to be very
important, so what matters is the manner in which abstracting is, and is
not, practiced. To be useful, a theory must make concessions to realism,
especially with respect to variables thought to play more important
roles in explaining the phenomena under study. Complete abstraction
yields pure mathematics, not empirically relevant science. Complete
accurate representation yields descriptive classification, not
generalization. The truly useful theory is a mixture of realistic and
abstract representation. I state this to emphasize my belief that the
neoclassical conceptualization, contrary to what its critics say, is a
realistic portrayal of those characteristics that are important in an
inquiry into the commercial activities of large, decentralized economic
systems. The most frequent criticisms of this portrayal are that people
are not motivated exclusively by narrow self-interest and that they are
not always rational in pursuing their goals. Each of these is considered
next.
III
The realism of the narrow self-interest motivation cannot be judged
without attention to the context within which decisions are made.
Between close friends and family members altruistic motivations assume
an importance not found in dealings between strangers. The purchaser of
wheat does not know those whose efforts went into its production and
delivery, and he or she seldom thinks sympathetically about these
suppliers when deciding on purchases. Most activity in the large,
decentralized, commercial economy is between strangers who are
represented not by familiar faces but by impersonal prices. Realism is
served, not sacrificed, if narrow self-interest is relied upon to
interpret behavior in the commercial economy. Abstraction from reality
in the decentralized economy would be extreme indeed if, instead of
placing reliance on self-interest, the model were to assume that
altruism plays a large role in decision-making; this is so not because
persons in business differ from other persons but because the
circumstances of choice differ.(3)
The relevance of circumstances is attested to by modern sociobiology.
The propensity to behave altruistically has been shown to depend on the
degree of genetic relatedness between the interacting parties. Many
economists, especially those who are involved in interdisciplinary work,
see this finding as supportive of the notion that economics ties its
findings too tightly to "baser features" of man's nature.
They are wrong in this. This sociobiological finding implies that
altruistic behavior is unimportant if dealings are between persons
unrelated to each other, and it is dealings of this sort, and not those
between relatives and close friends, that are of paramount importance in
the large, decentralized commercial system.
Economists need not look to sociobiology for this distinction. They
have the writings of Adam Smith. In his Wealth of Nations, Smith
characterizes behavior as steadfast in its pursuit of self-interest. In
his Theory of Moral Sentiments, he characterizes behavior as often
sympathetic to the feelings of others. These different descriptions of
human behavior are not inconsistent with each other. They describe
behavior under different circumstances. Interactions in the Wealth of
Nations take place in the world of commercial activity. They are between
persons who bear no kinship or friendship to each other and who, most
often, are not even known to each other. The sympathetic feelings
described in the Theory of Moral Sentiments are between persons who are
related to each other or who are close friends. This arena is contained
within the household or the small community. Smith even observes that
the intensity of sympathetic feelings is correlated with the degree of
relatedness between the interacting persons. These views are completely
in agreement with modern sociobiology; the one element missing from
Smith's works is a reference to the selfish gene, but, then again,
Smith's works have not been searched with an eye toward uncovering
this reference.
The argument just made merits repeating with respect to irrational
behavior. Rational calculation may be undermined by emotional feelings.
There is little doubt that some decisions have the appearance of
irrationality, and that emotional considerations account for this
appearance. "Appearance" rather than "fact" because
emotions are not ad hoc. They are incorporated into our decision-making
mental machinery through evolutionary or heavenly processes, and, in
subtle ways, they presumably enhance survival or serve other useful
goals. To describe their influence as deleterious is therefore to rush
to judgment, but let us accept this judgment for the sake of argument.
What types of decisions would be most subject to influence by emotions?
It is difficult to make convincing argument that emotions play much of a
role if dealings are between persons who do not know each other and who
generally are reacting not to persons but to impersonally determined
prices. Emotions will have more influence on interactions between family
members, friends, and enemies. As between strangers, cool calculations
of a rational sort are the order of the day.
In sum, the neoclassical conceptualization abstracts from reality
when persons are interacting with fellow workers, friends, neighbors,
and family, and it brings reality into the analysis when persons
interact with others through the commercial world of the large,
decentralized market economy. To assure yourself of this, ask and answer
the following questions:
On the relevance of narrowly conceived self-interest:
* What fraction of commercial activity turns importantly on
friendship? What fraction is significantly influenced by altruistic
motives? Only a small fraction. (With apologies to economists who suffer
from a desire to be sociologists.)
On the relevance of rationality:
* What fraction of business decisions are made on the basis of
emotion? What fraction on the basis of systematic calculation? Answers:
small to the first question, large to the second.
On the relevance of competition:
* How many goods are sold at prices high enough to yield
significantly abnormal profit for long periods of time? Not many. (With
apologies to the Justice Department's Antitrust Division.)
* For how long a period is tactical behavior by incumbent firms,
whether or not based on asymmetrical information, able to forestall the
competition of efficient potential entrants? Not long. (With apologies
to practitioners of single-play games.)
On the knowledgeability of commercial transactors:
* What fraction of the typical consumer's and typical
businessman's commercial purchases turn out to be significantly
different from the quality they expected? A very small fraction.
* What is the ratio of this fraction to an analogous fraction that
tracks dealings with the state? Very, very small.
* Are expectations realized more often in commercial transactions
than in noncommercial transactions? Divorce rates now over 50 percent
say, you bet they are.
This correspondence between conceptualization and commercial reality
enabled neoclassical economists to draw conclusions that have been
sustained empirically for a wide range of situations. The gathering of
evidence was aided substantially by the commensurate measurability of
commercial activity. Useful theory and supporting evidence contribute to
the solution of a problem that in its nature is of great importance to
both economics and policy. These account for the success of economics.
This three-part explanation of the success of economics should make us
less apologetic than we seem to be about Marshall's definition of
economics. Marshall begins his Principles of Economics [1890] by
defining economics as the
...study of mankind in the ordinary business of life; it examines
that part of individual and social action which is most closely
connected with the attainment and with the use of the material
requisites of well-being.(4)
Interpreted as describing what economists should do or as what they
do today, the definition is obviously too circumscribing, especially to
those who value the application of economics beyond its traditional
boundaries. For them, it seems terribly narrow, dull, and bourgeois. But
it is a good representation of what neoclassical economists actually
studied when Marshall wrote, and it is a representation that is focused
on those studies of economics that most account for its success within
its own boundaries. I include among these the studies, such as those of
Pigou, that were most concerned with the question of social optimality.
That neoclassical economics could reach defendable and even persuasive
conclusions about social optimality is rather remarkable and, on
reflection, undermining of the notion that the economics encompassed by
Marshall's notion was a dull affair.
I have said little about rational behavior in the contexts set
forward by Knight [1921] and Simon [1947]. Knight emphasized the absence
of rationality under the condition he named "uncertainty." He
describes this condition as one in which there is so little experience
with phenomena related to the decision at hand that it is impossible to
calculate empirically based probabilities necessary for rational action.
The emphasis is on the absence of experience. Decision-making cannot be
guided by standards of utility or profit maximization if we assume the
existence of this condition, and so, in a rather casual and brief way,
Knight substitutes emotion for rational calculation. His arm-chair
psychoanalyzing leads him to describe businessmen as
"optimistic" about outcomes under uncertainty, and he alleges
that this leads them to over-invest and, on average, to earn negative
returns. Simon takes a similar position, but he criticizes the
economist's use of rational calculation by supposing that many
business problems are so complex that coping with them would require
mental capacity (rather than, as in Knight, require experience) beyond
that possessed by mere mortals. Because this "bounded
rationality" makes rational calculation impossible, Simon puts
forward a decision criterion different from maximization of utility or
profit. His substitute is "satisfying behavior." Satisfying
behavior reflects a willingness to settle for outcomes that fall short
of being optimal but that exceed a subjective standard of minimal
acceptable satisfaction. What this subjective standard is surely depends
on psychological disposition, for it involves acceptance in the absence
of the capability to judge what is best in terms of benefits and costs.
Both concepts are rather useless in the analysis of the decentralized
commercial system, and this for three reasons. First, it is never the
case that experience is completely lacking or that problems are so
complex as to render rational thought processes useless. The pure cases
put forward by Knight and Simon are virtually (I would say entirely)
empty of empirical relevance. Second, no attention is given by Knight
and Simon to the conditions that inform us as to when actual decision
problems approach these pure cases sufficiently closely to make the
psychology of the decision-makers, rather than the rational
interpretation of "objective facts," the dominant force that
guides decisions. Because no operational guidelines for uncertainty and
bounded rationality are provided, it is not possible to assess the
empirical relevance of these guidelines. Third, the emotion-based
decision procedures put forward by Knight and Simon as substitutes for
rational calculation are so inadequately described that it is impossible
to assess whether they are operative in a given decision situation. For
these reasons, they offer no practical alternative to presuming action
is based on rational considerations.
Other sources of the belief that rational behavior is too strong an
assumption are experiments that purportedly uncover decision errors
that, because they are systematic, are judged to be inconsistent with
rational solutions to the problems put before the subjects of these
experiments. The findings in these experiments are difficult to take
very seriously. The results of a handful of experiments cannot offset
the evidence from a multitude of situations every day in. which we see
that less is bought if price increases and in which we see resources
flowing out of low rate of return uses and into high rate of return
uses. Moreover, the results of these experiments are difficult to
interpret because they confront their subjects with choices that are not
straightforward, that are unfamiliar to them, and that involve extremely
small payoffs. Rather than ask a subject if he or she prefers more of a
good to less, the subject is confronted with unfamiliar
probability-based lotteries in a situation in which the subject is never
quite sure what rating scale is really being applied to his or her
decisions.(5)
In assessing these attempts to fault the assumption that behavior is
motivated by narrowly conceived self-interest and is guided by the
rational pursuit of this, it is important to remember that the object of
the central inquiry of economics is behavior in the large, decentralized
commercial economic system. In this arena, few decisions, if any, are
made under conditions of uncertainty, of bounded-rationality, or of
extreme unfamiliarity. Buying and selling, producing and consuming, and
saving and investing are activities that are frequently repeated, often
by specialists, and are undertaken under circumstances that if not
entirely familiar are far from unusual. Even if the criticisms of the
rational behavior assumption that we have been discussing are given full
weight in circumstances likely to bring them into play, these
circumstances are not those that describe the overwhelming number of
decision problems faced in the commercial world. Remembering this brings
us back to the proposition that the modeling of this world by our
classical and neoclassical predecessors was quite realistic.
IV
There remains a question of why the other social sciences do not seem
to have progressed as much within their traditional boundaries as
economics has within its own. Practitioners in these other social
sciences are as clever..., well, almost as clever, and in the case of
lawyers perhaps more clever, as are economists. They are quite capable
of devising conceptual models appropriate to the problems they normally
confront in their sciences.
One explanation for their more limited progress is that their
sciences do not contain a problem that is as important in the totality of their disciplines as decentralization is in economics. I suspect this
is true but do not know it for a fact. If true, practitioners of other
social sciences need to solve many different problems before their work
can impact their disciplines as much as the study of decentralization
has impacted economics.
Another part of the explanation is that although practitioners of
these sciences have methods for making measurements, these measurements
generally are specific to the problem being studied and are not
commensurate across different problems. This makes useful generalization
difficult. There are technical problems in devising a commensurate unit
of measures in these sciences but the chief problem is a different one.
It is the reluctance by practitioners in these disciplines, and by the
general population also, to credit wealth with having great explanatory
power for the noncommercial behavior studied in these disciplines. This
defendable reluctance accounts for the popularity of the notion that
"economists know the price of everything and the value of
nothing."
Less poetic but more correct in substance is the notion that the
wealth consequences of one's actions explain much of what happens
in the world of commerce but much less of what happens in the
non-commercial world. There exists a high correlation between personal
wealth and personal utility when it comes to decisions concerning
commercial goods, and this makes the wealth consequences of decisions a
very important predictive index for commercial behavior. Practitioners
of sociology and other social sciences certainly do not deny the
relevance of wealth consequences to the behavior they study, but they
believe these consequences fail to explain this behavior to the degree
that they explain commercial behavior. Decisions pertaining to marriage
and to the having and raising of children for example are influenced by
wealth consequences, but not as much as are mergers between firms and
investments in new subsidiaries. Similarly, voting in national elections
is difficult to explain solely by appealing to wealth consequences, for
one person's vote has no perceptible wealth consequences. The
weakening of the explanatory power of wealth consequences in regard to
non-commercial behavior makes it difficult to apply a single analytical
framework to the set of problems on which other social scientists work,
and it raises a major obstacle to the development of a single
commensurate unit of measure.
Let me be quite clear about this. When economists analyze the
consumption behavior of households, the employment choices of workers,
and the investments of capitalists, their conclusions are largely drawn
from the wealth consequences that flow from alternative decisions. We do
not have much to say about tastes and how these may differ across
persons and situations, but, in principle, variations in tastes also
explain variations in behavior. Our focus, not exclusively but most
often, is on wages, prices, rates of return, and budget constraints.
This works quite well in practice if most tastes change only slowly. In
effect, we identify commercial activities by the fact that wealth
consequences are important for them. Differences in wealth consequences
track differences in utility levels well for these activities. If
quantities did not respond much to price changes, if investments did not
respond much to rate of return changes, if work patterns did not respond
much to wage changes, the price system would be of no importance to
resource allocation. The sensitivity of behavior to price or, more
accurately, to wealth consequences, is high for goods that we identify
as commercial goods, and neoclassical economics has had much to say that
is useful because it dealt mainly with these goods. Arguably, the
sensitivity of non-commercial behavior to wealth consequences is not as
high, and sensitivity to other considerations, such as religion,
culture, upbringing, is higher. The other social sciences therefore have
a task more difficult than that which faced neoclassical economics. A
heterogeneous mixture of several important considerations must be
related to different taste patterns and to resulting differences in
behavior. This is not to deny the relevance of the logic of economics to
most elements in this mixture. Rather, it is to say that the difficulty
in explaining behavior even through economic logic is greater than for
commercial activity because the important channels of causation are more
numerous and are less correlated with a single unit of measurement.
Obviously, the severity of this problem varies. Criminal activity is
motivated strongly by narrow self-interests; these interests are
measured well by wealth and they are pursued rationally. Here, the
problems to which I allude are minimal. They are stronger for problems
of passion, marriage, child-bearing, and patriotic fervor.
Marshall senses this toward the end of Appendix C of his Principles,
titled "The Scope and Method of Economics." He sees advantages
and disadvantages in extending the scope of economics, so it is
incorrect to view his position to be one of discouraging
interdisciplinary work. Rather, he points to a cost of extrapolating
economics beyond its normal boundaries. He makes the following point:
Economics has made greater advances than any other branch of the
social sciences, because it is more definite and exact than any other.
But every widening of its scope involves some loss of this scientific
precision; and the question of whether the loss is greater than the gain
resulting from its greater breadth of outlook, is not to be decided by
any hard and fast rule.
Within the scope of the few pages surrounding this quotation,
Marshall gives no supporting argument for his claim that inexactness accompanies the application of economics outside its normal boundaries,
but his emphasis on the commercial context of economics leaves no doubt
that he realized the advantages offered to economists by the presence of
prices. More broadly interpreting prices as wealth, we can translate
Marshall's work as claiming that a major source of inexactness in
the other social sciences derives from the diminished ability of wealth
to explain behavior outside the commercial context. This interpretation
is consistent with Marshall's definitional claim that economics
"...examines that part of individual and social action which is
most closely connected with the attainment and with the use of the
material requisites of well-being."
Marshall, being so expert on the relation between margins and totals,
surely would agree that inexactness is a cost worth bearing if doing
more interdisciplinary work brings the marginal returns from this work
closer to equality with work within the traditional boundaries of
economics. The investment of much effort in interdisciplinary work would
have been difficult to justify on grounds of marginal equalities before
the decentralization problem had been solved, and, in fact, not much
such investment took place then. The decentralization inquiry was in its
essence completed by World War II, and it was not until the decade of
the 1960s that work by economists began to extend seriously into other
disciplines. The extension has continued at a more significant pace to
the present.
But it is not only in regard to interdisciplinary work that the
efforts of economists have been extended. Side by side with their
explorations into other disciplines, economists have also looked more
closely at aspects of commercial behavior that were neglected by our
predecessors when they searched for a solution to the decentralization
problem. I refer to those "black boxes" in neoclassical
economics. Because we have begun to look into these boxes, we have
progress in our understanding of the problems resolved by the firm, by
different private ownership arrangements, and by the special provisions
that frequently attach to market agreements. There remains much about
these that we do not yet understand. As has been made apparent from the
lack of useful advice from Western economists to policy makers in
Eastern Europe attempting to convert economies from communism to
capitalism, we know much less about our institutions, or, at least, much
less about creating them, than our predecessors presumed. This work,
like interdisciplinary work, waited upon completion of the central
inquiry of economics.(6) But unlike much interdisciplinary work, the
study of the firm and of contractual agreements continues the
neoclassical tradition of focusing on behavior for which wealth
consequences remain the dominant consideration. However, neither this
work nor interdisciplinary work presently offer a problem of
paradigmatic significance equal to the decentralization puzzle. Perhaps
none is needed, but one wonders if the next 200 years of economics will
be as successful as its first 200 years. Only time will tell. In the
meantime, we can be grateful to find our professional plates filled with
interesting food for thought. The sensible thing is to come to the table
and join the feast!
1. Posner's text was written a few years after he joined the
University of Chicago Law School. Although he had a proclivity for
economic reasoning before. coming to Chicago, as revealed by some of his
work in the law, he developed this quite extensively through interaction
with economists at Chicago. However, his serious education in economics
probably began before this at Stanford where, as law school professor,
he met Aaron Director who had taken up residence at Stanford after
retiring from Chicago and from editorship of the Journal of Law and
Economics.
2. The major exceptions to this have been the inadequacy of
neoclassical treatments of oligopoly, aggregate employment, and economic
development. Oligopoly, of course, strains the decentralization
presumption by allowing decisions of individual firms to have an impact.
Fluctuations in employment and differences in rates of economic
development are time-dependent topics whose solutions are resistant to
analyses based on a decentralization model whose essential nature is
static.
3. Even strangers may react altruistically on those rare occasions
when a community is struck by some catastrophe. For a short period of
time, stranger treats stranger as if in the same family. But the study
of decentralization cannot be based on the rare event. Its objective is
to understand resource allocation under normal circumstances, and so,
again, narrow self-interest is the proper motivation to use.
4. In the first two paragraphs of later editions of Marshall's
Principles he modifies the exposition to stress even more the importance
to be attached to economics as a study of man in the context of
commercial activity:
For the business by which a person earns his livelihood generally
fills his thoughts during by far the greater part of those hours in
which his mind is at its best; during them his character is being formed
by the way in which he uses his faculties in his work, by the thoughts
and the feelings which it suggests and by his relations to his
associates in work, his employers or his employees.
5. For a detailed discussion of some of these experiments, and also
of other criticisms of the rational behavior assumption, including the
desire to substitute Darwinian notions of natural selection for rational
behavior, see the Fourth Commentary, "Profit Maximization and
Rational Behavior," in Demsetz [1995].
6. This is virtually true, but not literally. Knight undertook
serious discussion of the firm in 1921, and Coase wrote his
path-breaking article on the firm and long-term contracting in 1937.
However, both works were neglected until the 1960s. It was only then
that modern work on the firm and on contractual arrangements became an
important concern of economists.
REFERENCES
Becker, Gary S. The Economic Approach to Human Behavior. Chicago:
University of Chicago Press, 1976.
-----. Treatise on the Family. Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University
Press, 1981.
Buchanan, James M., and Gordon Tullock. The Calculus of Consent. Ann
Arbor: University of Michigan Press, 1962.
Coase, Ronald H. "The Nature of the Firm." Economica, 4,
1937, 386-405.
-----. "Economics and Contiguous Disciplines." Journal of
Legal Studies, June 1978, 201-12.
Demsetz, Harold. The Economics of the Firm: Seven Critical
Commentaries. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1995.
Friedman, Milton. Essays in Positive Economics. Chicago: University
of Chicago Press, 1953.
Hayek, Friedrich A. von. "The Uses of Knowledge in
Society." American Economic Review, September 1945, 519-30.
Hirshleifer, Jack. "The Expanding Domain of Economics."
American Economic Review, December 1985, 53-68.
Knight, Frank H. Risk, Uncertainty, and Profit. Hart, Schaffner, and
Marx, 1921; republished New York: Harper & Row, 1965.
Marshall, Alfred. Principles of Economics, 8th ed. London: Macmillan
Publishing Co, 1948; 1st edition, 1890.
Mises, Ludwig von. Socialism. (First English edition published by
Jonathan Cape, London, in 1936; Liberty Classics, 1979.
Posner, Richard A. The Economic Analysis of Law, 2nd ed. Boston:
Little, Brown and Co., 1977.
Simon, Herbert. Administrative Behavior. New York: Macmillan, 1947.
Tullock, Gordon. The Logic of the Law. New York: Basic Books, 1971.