Rationality, evolution, and acquisitiveness.
Demsetz, Harold
A classic article has "staying power" and impact.
Alchian's 1950 article "Uncertainty, Evolution, and Economic
Theory" has plenty of both, and there is no need to extol its
obvious virtues. Yet, I am sure that Alchian would find things to modify
in this article were he to rewrite it today, some forty-five years after
its publication. One task I set for myself here is to supply some food
for thought should Alchian be tempted to engage in a rewrite. I also
discuss arguments and concepts put forth by other economists whose
writings have influenced perceptions about rationality and evolution,
thus moving the discussion beyond the limits of Alchian's article.
The meaning of rational economic behavior is discussed next. Finally, I
explore how rational behavior might be a product of evolution.
The notion of evolution as the shaper of economic institutions has
been a minor theme in economics for two centuries. It is present in the
works of Malthus and Smith, whose writings later influenced Darwin,
Marx, and Schumpeter. The evolution theme even played a role in the late
nineteenth century policy debates about the Sherman Antitrust Act. Many
of the leading economists of that time, particularly those who helped to
create the American Economics Association, opposed the Sherman Act. One
of the more important economists, John Bates Clark, who was not among
those most enamored with evolutionary concepts, wrote:
Combinations have their roots in the nature of social industry and
are normal in their origin, their development, and their practical
working. They are neither to be depressed by scientists nor suppressed
by legislators. They are the result of an evolution, and are the happy
outcome of a competition so abnormal that the continuance of it would
have meant widespread ruin. A successful attempt to suppress them by law
would involve the reversion of industrial systems to a cast-off type,
the renewal of abuses from which society has escaped by a step in
development.(1)
Clark's negative view of the efficacy of an antitrust law,
shared by many leading economists of the time, had little influence on
legislative matters. The Sherman Act became law.
These earlier references by economists to evolution are mainly casual
and superficial, and in this respect they do not anticipate and are no
substitute for Alchian's discussion. Alchian's unique
contributions were to use evolution analytically in a model of economic
behavior and to offer it as a substitute for rationality. Alchian's
critique of the presumption that economic behavior is to be explained by
rational action, which means profit maximization in the case of the firm
of neoclassical theory, constitutes a fundamental challenge to one of
orthodoxy's cherished principles. Section I of the present paper
discusses the difficulties in analyzing economic behavior without
recourse to rationality, and it illustrates these by reference to
Alchian's article.
I.
Four major themes run through "Uncertainty, Evolution and
Economic Theory." The first is the difficulty that uncertainty
creates for the neoclassical assumption that businessmen maximize
profit, or, to put this more broadly, the difficulty that uncertainty
creates for the rational behavior assumption. The second is that there
is a process at work - natural selection - that determines which
business decisions lead to viable outcomes and which do not. I take for
granted and do not discuss the proposition that a natural selection
process is at work. The third theme relates to the particular filter
that is used by the evolutionary process when it comes to business
decisions; the filter that Alchian puts in place is the test of whether
decisions result in positive profit. The fourth theme is that decisions
that survive this filter are disseminated through the economy by the
imitative efforts of other firms.
The difficulty in behaving rationally (and irrationally also). Knight
[1921] was the first prominent economist to attack the notion that all
or that most economic decisions are guided by rational calculation.
Simon [1947; 1957; 1959] launched his attack at about the same time as
Alchian. Although all three take roughly the same position in regard to
the limits of rationality, they differ somewhat as to the source of
these limits.
Knight rejects rational behavior if decisions must be made under
conditions of uncertainty, which he distinguishes from conditions of
risk. To a large extent, he denies the ability to calculate rationally
if experience relevant to the decision problem is absent. With
sufficient experience, probability distributions can be inferred, and
these can be, and are, used to cope with risk through rational
calculation (as in the provision of insurance). Failure of rationality,
then, is a reflection of the paucity of experience. Alchian rejects
rational behavior on the basis of similar reasoning, but his rejection
seems to extend even into conditions that Knight would describe as risk
rather than as uncertainty. To Alchian, a major obstacle to rational
maximizing is the lack of a one-to-one correspondence between decision
and outcome; two different decisions can lead to the same outcome,
although possibly with differing probabilities, so how can one decision,
but not the other, be identified as rational maximizing? However, both
Knight and Alchian stress inadequacies of available information.
Simon's rejection is based on inadequacies of the human mind. The
mind possesses only a limited capacity for understanding complex
relationships and for handling large masses of data. Decisions cannot be
made on the basis of rational calculation if they require mental
capabilities beyond this limit. The differences between these views are
fairly obvious, but the three are similar in that all cite the
difficulty of making rational calculations in a world in which
information is imperfect.
However, rejecting rational calculation leads to another problem. If
we do not decide rationally, how do we decide? One might think the
answer should be that we decide erratically or, perhaps, randomly, but
this is not the answer given by these three economists. Simon
substitutes "satisficing" - a decision criterion that accepts
the desirability of settling for something less than the best and better
than some lower bound - for maximizing. Since Simon is very much
concerned about our mental limitations, he presumably believes, but does
not demonstrate, that satisficing makes fewer mental demands than does
maximizing. Knight does not comment much on substitute methods of making
decisions, but he clearly sensed a problem here for he briefly describes
his belief about the manner in which businessmen, facing uncertainty,
decide on their investments. He asserts the presence of a psychological
tendency for overly optimistic estimates of the likely outcomes of their
investments. Optimism leads to more investment than is needed, leading,
on average, to negative returns and lower product prices.
Neoclassical theory uses maximization to guide its deductions because
this seems a sensible or desirable decision criterion, but this
criterion seems to spring willy-nilly from within the mind. The same is
true for satisficing, optimism, pessimism, etc. It seems that
Simon's satisficing criterion is chosen voluntarily by persons
whose decisions are being frustrated by the limited capabilities of
their minds. Knight's optimism is a starkly ad hoc psychological
quirk. All these criteria suffer from the absence of a more basic
explanation for their existence and survival in the psyche, and the same
is true for maximization. Alchian looks not to the inner workings of the
mind but to evolution for the criterion that determines the viability of
business decisions, or at least so it seems. This criterion is whether
businesses realize a positive profit from their decisions. Neoclassical
theory, like Alchian's criterion, while it holds to maximization of
profit by businessmen also requires the realized maximum to be positive
if business activities are to meet the market test. In this respect,
Alchian's selection criterion seems a quite easy extension from
economic theory. But this is not so.
The positive profit criterion. Positive profit is an appealing
evolutionary filter. Firms experiencing positive profit on a continuing
basis usually survive; firms experiencing continuing losses usually
fail, or they are reorganized. But these facts are also consistent with
rational behavior. In fact, it is rational behavior that lies behind
neoclassical theory's reliance on a non-negative profit to define
equilibrium. Alchian cannot rely on neoclassical theory to buttress his
choice of the positive profit criterion, for he is arguing against the
use of a rational behavior postulate. He proposes positive profit as a
survival filter that natural selection, not rational behavior, applies
to business decisions. To distinguish positive profit from maximum
profit in this way requires that its source should be different from
rational pursuit of ends. Positive-profit criterion, like ice ages, must
be part of the environment in which business decisions are made.
Alchian's objection to profit maximization, it must be remembered,
is based on our inability to link business decisions to outcomes.
Positive profit in Alchian's argument, therefore, cannot be
predictively forward looking. If it were, he would be justified in
presuming that business decisions can be linked to profit outcomes, or,
at least, to the algebraic sign of these outcomes. To satisfy
Alchian's needs, positive profit must be to business decisions as
the ice age was to the survival of species. The positive-profit
criterion must be external to our decisions; its application must not
rely on human calculation if we are to avoid relying on rational
behavior indirectly. From this perspective, positive profit is simply an
ex post fact the occurrence of which leads to the survival of a firm,
much as ice age temperature led to the survival of only some animals.
Unfortunately, the demonstration of this independence is lacking, and,
on consideration, it seems very difficult to supply.
Positive profit clearly is not independent of thought processes.
Profit is itself a result of conscious calculation, and positive profit
is a filtering criterion that we choose to impose on ourselves. If
positive profit is to have meaning, there must be some reason to think
our calculation methods are at least roughly accurate and that positive
profit is not being confused with negative profit. That is, we must
think that these methods taken in their entirety make sense, and if they
do not make sense we no longer know what is accomplished by a natural
selection filter that relies on calculations of positive profit.
That positive profit is not exogenous to the economic system, and
that it is not a necessary criterion of success, is suggested by the
soft budget constraints and subsidies that have characterized socialist
economies and to a lesser extent our own also. Despite negative profit,
socialist firms of all types continue to survive, and so does our own
Continental Bank and Chrysler Corporation. Positive profit, therefore,
is not necessary to survival, nor is its application independent of
conscious thought, whether rational or irrational. Subsidies might be
treated as just another source of revenue, one that converts loss and
prospective failure into profit and survival, but this would make the
positive profit filter much too tautological since any method of
survival can be interpreted as a source of revenue. Alchian's
discussion makes it clear that he means business profit to depend on
voluntary exchange across markets. The firm receives revenue from
customers or financial market creditors. If this revenue is less than
the firm's cost, loss results.
But why does loss imply business failure? Is it because consumers are
unwilling to pay more for the same quantity of purchases? Is it because
the legal system bars the firm from using violent means to obtain
resources? Is it because suppliers of inputs refuse to take less for
their inputs? Is it because lenders refuse to make capital available to
a firm whose prospects are not promising? Is it because creditors can
shut down the firm or reorganize it? All these are reasons for the firm
to fail if profit is negative, but all of them suggest a dependency on
rational calculations made by consumers and suppliers of inputs.
The failure of a firm is brought about by the reaction of creditors
to losses they bear. This reaction makes sense only if the firm's
history of losses can be used to predict its future. If a firm that
suffers a series of losses is thought to be just as likely to enjoy
great profit in the future as a firm that has a record of rising
profits, creditors have no more reason to refuse to lend to the first
firm than to the second. A reliable system of forecasting future profit
on the basis of past profit is implied, and this suggests, of all
things, the possibility that rational behavior is at work. If there were
no reliable forecasting system, lenders would be as likely to recapture
their capital and realize a profit from funds provided to firms with a
record of negative profit as from funds provided to firms with a record
of positive profit. The positive-profit filter seems to require
rejection of the very condition that made it appeal to Alchian, this
condition being our asserted inability to map today's decisions
into probabilistically reliable forecasts of tomorrow's outcomes.
If lenders pay no heed to the past profit of potential borrowers and
if consumers are quite willing to purchase randomly from firms - one way
to interpret irrational behavior - there is no compelling reason for
firm survival to be associated with positive profit. Survival would be
random. Suppose survival is not random but accords with the pattern that
is described by Alchian's use of the positive profit filter. If we
wish to use this fact to deny the relevance of rational behavior, we are
obligated to explain the source of this filter in terms not easily tied
to rational calculation. This, we have just seen, is difficult to do.
Even if such an explanation could be given, the positive-profit
criterion would not seem capable of explaining survival as well as
another criterion that requires no more, or only a little more,
information. A survey of business firm profits is necessary to determine
which firms enjoy positive profit and which do not, but this reveals a
profit ranking or, with slightly more information, a rate-of-return
ranking. Why not assume that the filter natural selection applies to the
economic system associates a higher probability of survival with a
higher rate-of-return ranking? Just as thicker skin increased the
probability of surviving the ice age, so a higher profit rate increases
the probability of surviving the competitive age. This criterion brings
the natural selection filter closer to that of profit maximization, but
without requiring, as pure maximization would seem to require, that
there is a comparison of all possible opportunities. Moreover, it would
be consistent with the factually greater willingness of lenders to favor
higher rate-of-return firms. Of course, a criterion based on relative
profit (rates) smacks much more of rational calculation.
Irrationality and budget constraints. The appeal of the
positive-profit criterion to Alchian undoubtedly is related to the
notion of feasibility or of the need to satisfy budget constraints. A
firm that has earned a positive profit finds its resources undiminished
by its past activity and available for use in the next period. A firm
that has suffered a loss has diminished the resources available to it
during the next period. Carried to an extreme with a string of negative
profits, and coupled to requirements that lenders of capital lend only
to positive-profit firms, the negative-profit firm cannot continue at
the same level of activity because to do so requires more resources than
it possesses.
A later analysis by Becker [1962] of the relationship between price
and quantity is similar to this view of the problem, but it is based
quite explicitly on the role of budget constraints. Becker demonstrates
that budget constraints imply a negative relationship between a
good's price and the quantity of it that is sold even if buying
behavior is not rational. In his analysis, the budget constraint divides
the choice set into the possible and the impossible. He shows that if
product prices are allowed to vary, consumer purchases change in
accordance with the law of negatively sloped demand. This happens
because at least some consumers of the good whose price has risen
relatively will find it impossible to purchase as many units as they
could have if the price had not risen, even if their purchase intents
are determined randomly rather than rationally. It is a well-drawn
demonstration of the power of budget constraints. Yet, for reasons
similar to those brought to bear above on the positive-profit criterion,
it is not fully convincing as a demonstration of the redundancy of
rational behavior in our models. Whence the budget constraint? That
there is a budget constraint seems to require rational decisions by
others. Goods are not made available by others to those who cannot pay
for them; funds to buy these goods are not made available by lenders.
The people behind the budget constraint behave as if they husband their
resources. Without this behavior, budget constraints lack meaning as
long as wealth exists in the community.
These aspects of the budget constraint reflect social interactions.
Becker's analysis would seem to be independent of rational behavior
in an economy like that of Robinson Crusoe, in which the operability of
the budget constraint derives not from the decisions of others but
directly from the limits set by real resource availability. Alter the
mix of resources and some previously exercisable opportunities are no
longer possible. But this establishes only a pseudo law of negatively
sloped demand. The statistical relationship between opportunities
exercised and the relative supplies of inputs, although it conforms in
appearance to what one would expect from the law of negatively sloped
demand, is in fact only the appearance. It reflects only the
impossibility of doing that which nature does not allow to be done. The
law of negatively sloped demand is more than a demonstration of this. It
is also a claim that all who purchase a good will purchase less of it if
its price is raised, even though nothing bars them from purchasing more
of the good by doing with less of other goods.(2) This proposition will
be violated by Becker's example of random purchases, since some
random (irrational) purchasers do buy more of the good whose price has
risen. It is only the total of purchases that must fall because of
operable budget constraints.(3)
Alchian's and Becker's arguments do suggest that patterns
of observations that we explain in terms of rational behavior can also
result from behavior that is not rational. However, as imaginative and
informative as these arguments are, they cannot be sustained in full
without appealing to rationality or without introducing a natural
selection explanation that remedies the shortcomings of their present
arguments. As they stand, rational behavior seems to be at work below
the surface of their analyses. Consider, for example, Alchian's
reliance on imitation to propagate success.
Propagation through imitation. The firm is not a biological organism.
It does not mate with another firm and sexually breed biological
offspring. A firm that experiences positive profit might grow; it might
even spin off parts that follow the very practices that made the
"parent" firm a positive-profit firm (Nelson and Winter
[1982]). To some extent, through processes such as these, we might
predict a slowly increasing sphere of influence for business practices
that happen to have worked well. But there are limits to the rate at
which a firm can grow efficiently (Penrose [1959]; Marris, [1974]). More
important, we know factually that the sphere of influence for successful
practices is extended more rapidly than it could be through internal
growth only, and that this is accomplished primarily through imitation
by rivals. The growth in fast food retailing was achieved not just by
MacDonald's growth, as rapid as this was, but by the imitation of
MacDonald's methods and organization by rival chains.
Alchian recognizes the importance of imitation and relies upon it to
spread successful business practices. However, imitation, like positive
profit, is difficult to disassociate from behavior that at least appears
rational. Conscious and generally correct forecasting is involved. Past
success must be separated from past failure, projections from these past
histories must be made and must be correct on average, and successful
histories must be imitated more often than unsuccessful histories. If
imitation were guided by randomly exercised choice, both unsuccessful
and successful business practices would be adopted. The rush of
resources into profitable markets and out of unprofitable markets, which
we know to happen, cannot be explained by random choice. If imitation is
to lead to adoption of successful and rejection of unsuccessful
variants, there must be some predictive value to the projections made
from past records. Imitation, in extending the sphere of influence of
successful variants, depends on rationality-supporting conditions.
II.
To this point, I have argued that it is difficult to give meaning to
natural selection for economic actions without placing some reliance on
rationality. Far from being an alternative to natural selection,
rationality may be a product of natural selection, but let us begin this
section simply by assuming as fact that we behave rationally. To
understand the economic consequences of this fact, it is necessary to
have some agreement as to what we mean by rational behavior and about
the goals this behavior is expected to pursue. The meaning of rational
behavior is discussed here. Goals are discussed in the last part of this
paper.
Defining rational behavior. There is a clear difference between the
rationality implicit in positive economic theory and that gleaned from
the axioms of choice that are used to buttress utility theory (e.g.,
completeness of ordering, continuity of choice alternatives,
independence from irrelevant alternatives, and transitivity). Positive
economic theory links decisions to the service of our goals, and it uses
rational behavior to instruct us about the nature of the linkage. The
monopolist's output rate is set so that marginal revenue equals
marginal cost because he seeks maximum profit. The axioms of choice, in
contrast, do not depend at all on goal fulfillment. Consider that these
axioms can be satisfied by a Roman general whose battle decisions are
made on the basis of the pattern taken by a slaughtered chicken's
entrails. Pattern one is judged to forecast a better chance of winning,
pattern two a somewhat slimmer chance, and pattern three not much chance
at all. His choice psychology is transitive if his preference of one
over two and two over three leads him to prefer one over three, yet he
may be defeated as many times as he wins by following signals he
deciphers from these entrails. The problem here may be a belief in
"superstition" or it may be in a failure to measure correctly
the correlation between the shape of entrails and the winning of
battles, but either deficiency is consistent with the notion that the
rationality of decision rules cannot be determined only by their
consistency with the axioms of choice. Let there be two rules of
decision making. The first satisfactorily achieves results but sometimes
violates transitivity. The second seldom achieves desired results but
never violates transitivity. Which rule should, or does, a rational
person prefer?
The ability of a rule to deliver results depends in part on its
internal logic, but only in part. Good results depend also on whether a
rule is well suited to the conditions under which it must be applied. A
rule for making decisions that yield desired outcomes in a world
populated by persons of good will may not work well in a world populated
by persons deeply suspicious of each other. Moreover, if we are to rely
on rationality to understand economic outcomes, we must have some notion
about the goals that guide its application. Many more people would be
living the life of a monk if perfection of the ascetic side of our lives
was of utmost importance to us.
Precondition for behaving rationally. Goal-oriented decision rules
rely on the existence of many stable correlations between events. If
these correlations change through time, they should change slowly.
Without steadiness over time in at least some of the relationships
between natural events it becomes impossible to devise useful rules of
decision making. Because rain tends repeatedly to come in the spring,
and because dampness repeatedly results in the sprouting of seeds,
patterns in the occurrence of these events can be observed and learned
and useful rules of farming can be devised. What I mean by rationality
is the ability to recognize patterns in worldly phenomena, to project
the conditions that govern these patterns into the future, and to select
patterns and extrapolations from these that help to achieve desired
goals. Assertedly, business decisions conform with this notion of
rationality.
To the extent that reasoning ability of this sort is influenced by
genetic endowment, it is plausible to think of our current state of
intelligence as a product of natural selection. Intelligence experts
believe that the variability in intelligence that is explained by
genetic differences is between 40 and 80 percent, with the remainder of
variation being explained by such things as family and cultural
environment. Thus, natural selection is indirectly at work in filtering
business decisions, and the criterion it has evolved might depend very
much on rationality as described above. Projections of expected profit
and risk of profit are made on the basis of past experience with
correlation patterns. From the limited choice sample these provide, the
best profit-risk combination is chosen, and persons who supply
additional resources to the firm will be influenced in making their
supply decisions by their projections of the results they expect to
realize. This is not simply profit maximization because risk matters and
because not all possible profit-risk combinations are contained in our
experiences. It is the best of what is available on the basis of a
profit-risk tradeoff. Expectations seldom are confirmed exactly.
Different decisions may yield the same results. These realities do not
undermine a claim that businessmen rely heavily on rational thought
processes. However, even if such behavior were both plausible and
reflective of natural selection, it would not carry us very far in
understanding economic outcomes. Two types of issues arise. First, why
is reasoning power devoted to the extent that it is to improving our
material well-being? Our rationality could be, and is to some extent,
directed to serve purposes other than improvement in our material
well-being. If we are to understand rational behavior, we must be able
to draw conclusions about the directions in which our preferences will
guide our choices and actions. Secondly, why do we not observe much, if
any, improvement through time in the reasoning power of other species?
Most other species have existed over an evolutionary time span much
greater than humans, yet no other species seems to have developed
reasoning power equal to that which is characteristic of humans. From
the ameba to the chimpanzee, survival seems to depend largely on
characteristics very different from reasoning power (as defined here).
Progress in answering these questions requires that we delve into the
nature of our preferences or goals.(4,5)
III.
Economic theory avoids the task of describing or explaining the goals
we pursue, and, instead, to a large extent, it takes goals as
unspecified givens. Theory allows us to discuss the tradeoff between
apples and oranges or between income and leisure because it presumes
these are utility conferring goods and activities, but it gives no
justification for the presumption. Even so, economic theory allows us to
understand economic behavior without explicit justification of the goals
it assumes. This is because economists think rationally (as defined
above). We implicitly use recurring patterns of behavior to infer
plausible goals. Apples are a good because we take the fact of repeated
past purchases of apples as evidence of this. In its practical
application to the details of economic behavior this implicitly
empirical procedure works quite well, so that an explicit analysis of
human wants is not needed. There is good reason to avoid saying more
about our wants than can be inferred from our past behavior, for theory
offers no economics-based explanation for why we want some things and
not others.(6) The explanation is to be found in a combination of
medical facts (apple consumption provides needed nutrients) and natural
selection theory (taste patterns influence survival probabilities and
reflect natural selection).
The acquisitive species. The same technique for inferring our
preferences can be applied to a more general description of our
proclivities. What it reveals is that we are an acquisitive species. We
prefer more (generalized) wealth to less. This is similar to the notion
of insatiability of wants that we employ in theory, but it is not
exactly the same. Not much, if any, evidence is given, or even could be
given, to support the notion that our wants are insatiable. In fact,
people often behave as if their wants are, or have been, satiated (e.g.,
"I cannot eat even one more slice of pizza"). This fact is
obscured by our tendency to use insatiability tautologically. Thus,
altruistic behavior is not interpreted as a violation of insatiability
but, rather, as evidence that helping others confers positive utility on
us. People retire early and earn less than they could, but this is not a
problem for insatiability because we allow leisure to enter positively
into our utility functions. But if we are to interpret behavior in this
way, honesty would seem to require us to substitute the notion that we
behave with "purpose" for the notion that our wants are
"insatiable." Rather than being a description of our wants,
our use of insatiability makes it a description of the choice situations
we seek to analyze. These are situations in which resources are too
meager to meet the demands for them that would be brought forth with a
zero price. The fact that some goods or resources are superabundant
(i.e., free) is not used to refute the insatiability of our wants. It is
used to delineate the situations we wish to study, those for which the
price system is the allocator of resources.
Here, I wish to use acquisitiveness in a less tautological way than
we use insatiability. Acquisitiveness means not only a preference for
more wealth (for self, family, and friends) over less. It also means the
realization that more wealth can be had. Generalized wealth, of course,
means command over goods. Which items enter our utility functions
positively (goods) and which negatively (bads) depends partly on
available supplies and partly on exogenous considerations, including
natural selection among the latter. Acquisitiveness can be cast into a
specific proposition such as "the typical person in each generation
seeks wealth greater than that enjoyed by the typical person in the
prior generation" and even that he seeks this increment to wealth
"if securing it requires him to work somewhat harder than did the
typical person in the prior generation." Acquisitiveness is thus
described by wealth comparisons through time as "wanting more and
realizing that more can be had." My claim is that the typical
person believes that an increase in wealth is desirable (our preference)
and possible (our understanding of "nature"). Not
everyone's wants, at all times, are acquisitive in this sense, or,
if they are, not everyone is capable, at all times, of acquiring more
wealth, but acquisitiveness in this sense is a valid description of our
perceptions for a large fraction of the world's population. It is
not tautological, however. There can be ascetics. More importantly,
acquisitiveness may not be an equally strong characteristic of people
who live in different cultures, and it is difficult to say if a
society's culture reflects the particular perceptions of its people
or if these preferences are shaped by the society's culture. As I
shall argue below, acquisitiveness does not seem to be a characteristic
that is as strong in other animals as it is in the human.
Although acquisitiveness is not tautological, analyzing economic
activity in ways that reveal its presence is not always easy. As an
example of this difficulty consider the behavior of parents and children
in Becker's [1976] discussion of altruistic behavior toward parents
by a "rotten kid." A selfish child finds it in his interest to
behave "altruistically" toward his parents, taking some of his
own wealth and giving it to his parents. The parents reciprocate by
leaving their estate to the child. This transpires despite the essential
selfishness of the child because of an empirical assumption that the
parents are able to make much better use of funds than is the child. A
sacrifice today by the child results in an increase in his parents'
wealth that is larger than the sacrifice, so that when the child
receives his inheritance he has made a very good return on his
investment. His parents reciprocate his "altruistic" donation
of wealth by designating the child as their heir, and it is in their
interest to do so in order to secure the donation that they can convert
into a sum much greater. The seemingly altruistic actions of child and
parents simply reflect an implicit contract from which both parties
gain, such gain coming from the investment skills of the parents. The
egocentric ends of all parties are served, and the same "deal"
could have been struck just as well between strangers. Yet, what is
essentially acquisitive behavior is hidden behind a cloak of seeming
altruism.(7)
No carefully devised empirical test of our acquisitive propensity is
offered here, but there is evidence consistent with its existence as a
prevailing force. This is found in the long-term trend in living
standards experienced by Western industrialized nations over the last
two or three centuries, and there has been an accompanying broadening of
this phenomenon through much of the world's population.
Evidence of acquisitiveness is not equally strong for any other
species, even though much of what individuals in these species do is
purposeful. Taking in nourishment, mating, and protecting territory, for
example, seem purposeful, and they serve the self-interests of
individual members of these species insofar as we or natural selection
have defined self interest. Nonetheless, this behavior is not
acquisitiveness or, at best, it is very weak acquisitiveness. No
persistent trend of improvement in wealth has been exhibited by other
species. Natural conditions good enough to stave off starvation, to
mate, and to defend against attack do not seem to whet appetites for
still higher living standards but simply seem to satisfy each
generation. Squirrels do not behave as if they want much more than a
supply of nuts ample to attract and support a mate and to feed
offspring. We do not observe wealth accumulation beyond these amounts
even when external conditions are good enough to permit such
accumulation. The absence of confirming behavior for other species may
be due to a true lack of concern about accumulating more than very
limited amounts of wealth (a question of goals), or it may be due to an
inability to understand past correlations and to execute forward looking
plans or devise solution institutions based on these correlations
(questions of intelligence and rationality).(8)
One may argue that animals in other species do want more, but
populations always rise to Malthusian limits and undermine growth in
living standards. But this happens either because there is no
willingness to accept fewer offspring or because there is insufficient
reasoning power to develop rules of behavior suited to the goal of
material improvement. Dogs simply refuse to inventory more than a few
bones no matter how many you throw at them, and they see no value in
staying behind their owners' fences when the season attracts them
to the opposite sex. The human species, or a large percentage thereof,
is unique in its penchant for birth control. Birth rates are
deliberately held below biologically feasible limits even when resources
are ample to support these limits biologically. No doubt there are many
life-style motivations for this, but important among these is a desire
to maintain or increase personal and family wealth.(9)
The very possession of wealth, as distinct from the act of acquiring
wealth, has a net beneficial effect on the probability of surviving.
Wealth, health, and longevity are positively correlated. Although good
health and long life do facilitate the accumulation of wealth, the
primary direction of causation surely is the reverse. Whether or not
acquisitiveness is genetic, a significant part of reasoning power does
seem to be inherited. This allows acquisitiveness to influence the
outcome of natural selection. Assume two persons that possess different
powers to reason. Both are acquisitive, but the person with superior
reasoning power is more successful in acquiring wealth. This greater
wealth confers a higher probability of surviving on the person possessed
of genetically superior reasoning power, implying that acquisitiveness
facilitates a more rapid breeding of intelligence into the human
species. The strength of this effect is open to debate.
Other links between intelligence and probability of survival surely
exist, but these must be preferential to humans if we are to use them to
explain a seemingly rapid (by comparison to other species) increase in
our reasoning power. A link between intelligence and survival like that
which obviously exists when it comes to defending one's self and
fending off dangers does not easily satisfy this requirement, since it
is a link that should be present in all species. Acquisitiveness seems
both to promote the selection of intelligence (through its health and
defense implications) and to be especially strong in humans. I do not
argue that acquisitiveness is itself inherited, although it may be, only
that it is and has been a characteristic of the preference pattern of a
large part of human populations. Under property-right conditions similar
to those devised in Western civilizations, persons have been able to
accumulate wealth through generations. The social or cultural ability to
do so, when linked to positive correlations between intelligence and
wealth accumulation, on the one hand, and between survivability and
wealth accumulation on the other hand, should have encouraged a more
rapid selection of reasoning power, and the force of this should have
been at its strongest during periods when wealth was insufficient to
pull large fractions of population through the child-bearing years.
Societies that have not devised similar institutions for encouraging or
tolerating wealth accumulation in large fractions of their populations
will not have benefited from this source of accelerated evolution in
intelligence. Other sources for such improvement may exist, but unless
they correlate negatively with Western property-right institutions, the
absence of these institutions places a special burden on rapid
improvement in reasoning power.(10)
1. Quotation taken from "The Limits of Competition" by J.
B. Clark as reprinted in The Modern Distributive Process (1888).
2. This of course assumes that preference systems remain unchanged
and that we are not dealing with Giffen paradox goods. Becker's
analysis is consistent with these assumptions.
3. For a different type of objection to Becker's analysis, see
Kirzner [1963]. Also note Becker's rejoinder [1963].
4. The current vogue among students of animal behavior is to call
attention to the cognitive abilities of "lower" animals. This
provides evidence of continuity of development of these abilities from
lower to higher life forms. However, the discovery of a
chimpanzee's use of a tree branch as a tool by which to secure
food, while demonstrating that humans are not unique in the use of
tools, also demonstrates, by virtue of the length of time it has taken
to make this discovery and the apparent absence of (many) other examples
in the totality of chimpanzee behavior, that there is a considerable
difference between the degree of reliance placed on rational thought
processes by humans and by chimps.
5. If we were to probe the relationship between rational behavior and
natural selection, it would be necessary to give a large role to
imperfect information. That inheritable aspects of superior reasoning
have a greater probability of surviving, other things equal, is due to
imperfect information. Limited knowledge cannot be used effectively by
those possessing poor reasoning power. So, over time, in a variety of
interactions between persons possessed of different reasoning competence
and, much more important, in a variety of interactions between persons
and nature, those with superior reasoning ability will fare better. The
natural selection of superior rationality is made possible because of,
not in spite of, imperfect knowledge. Ironically, the very condition
that Knight, Simon, and Alchian use in different ways to limit the role
of rational behavior, imperfect knowledge, is one source of
evolution-related improvements in reasoning power.
6. This is not quite true. Once apples are empirically determined to
enter our utility function positively, we can show that some conditions,
such as those that pertain to age and income, may increase or decrease
the utility value we place on apples (Stigler and Becker [1977].
7. Other examples of seemingly altruistic behavior may be given.
Tit-for-tat negotiating strategies overcome problems facing persons
locked into a prisoner's dilemma, but they work because they yield
a mutual net gain to the interacting parties, given the underlying
assumptions of tit-for-tat models. The voluntary acceptance of an
increased probability of death in order to reduce the probability of
death of one's blood relatives is another example. Since 50 percent
of a child's genes are identical to those carried by one of his
parents, the probability that this strain of genes will be perpetuated
by this seemingly altruistic behavior is increased if the probability of
death of the parent who puts herself or himself in harm's way is
increased by less than half the reduction in the probability of death
that results for the child. From the perspective of this paper, the
proper classification of these actions is egocentric, not altruistic.
8. The skeptic who is well informed in biological matters will point
to examples of investments made by animals, such as the beaver's
construction of a dam. The small number of such examples and their
insignificance when compared to the accumulative urge in humans makes of
these examples the exceptions that prove the rule.
9. Smaller family size results in an increase in the per capita wealth in the family unless, as is possibly true of farming with old
technology, there are increasing returns to family size. Since per
capita wealth correlates positively (and causally) with probability of
survival, acquisitiveness confers a survival advantage to the typical
family member through its negative impact on family size. But smaller
family size, aside from this wealth effect and simply by virtue of there
being fewer children, also reduces the probability that the family gene
pool is passed to succeeding generations. Just what the optimal family
size is from the perspective of propagating a family's gene pool is
unclear, but the positive effect of per capital wealth on the survival
of the individual implies a smaller family size is optimal than if there
were no such wealth effect. If acquisitiveness leads to properly
proportioned reductions in the sizes of families, it will raise the
probability of survival of the human gene pool. To put the matter more
briefly, in an affluent setting the biological maximum birth rate may be
too large to maximize the probability that a family's gene pool
survives. Something like acquisitiveness may be required if survival of
the gene pool is to be maximized.
10. To such propositions, one would need to add caveats about
different methods of accumulating wealth, since some of these (crime,
rent-seeking of certain sorts, war, etc.) may have a deleterious effect
on the aggregate wealth of a society. Having said this, thereby
prompting readers to recognize that a society benefits more or less from
acquisitiveness depending on the guidance it gives to acquisitiveness,
it nonetheless remains an assertion of this paper that acquisitiveness
has been a powerful agent for the more rapid progress in intelligence
enhancement that seems to have taken place in the human species.
REFERENCES
Alchian, A. A. "Uncertainty, Evolution, and Economic
Theory." Journal of Political Economy, June 1950, 211-21.
Becker, G. S. "Irrational Behavior and Economic Theory."
Journal of Political Economy, February 1962, 1-13.
-----. "A Reply to Kirzner." Journal of Political Economy,
February 1963, 82-3.
-----. "Altruism, Egoism, and Genetic Fitness: Economics and
Sociobiology." Journal of Economic Literature, September 1976,
817-26.
Clark, John B. "The Limits of Competition," in The Modern
Distributive Process: Studies of Competition and Its Limits. Boston:
Ginn & Company, 1888. Originally published in the Political Science
Quarterly.
Demsetz, H. Seven Critical Commentaries on the Economics of the Firm.
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press (forthcoming 1995). See especially
Commentary Four for a discussion of rational behavior and the
"overshooting" phenomenon.
Kirzner, I. "Rational Action and Economic Theory." Journal
of Political Economy, August 1962, 380-85.
-----. "Rejoinder." Journal of Political Economy, February
1963, 84-5.
Knight, F. H. Risk, Uncertainty, and Profit. New York: Harper and
Row, 1965; first published in 1921.
Marris, R. The Economic Theory of Managerial Capitalism. London:
Macmillan, 1974.
Nelson, R. R., and S. G. Winter. An Evolutionary Theory of Economic
Change. Cambridge, Mass.: Belknap Press of Harvard University, 1982.
Penrose, E. The Theory of the Growth of the Firm. Oxford: Basil
Blackwell, 1959.
Schumpeter, J. A. The Theory of Economic Development. Cambridge,
Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1934.
-----. Capitalism, Socialism, and Democracy. New York: Harper, 1950.
Simon, H. A. Administrative Behavior. New York: Macmillan, 1947.
-----. Models of Man. New York: John Wiley & Sons, 1957.
-----. "Theories of Decision Making in Economics." American
Economic Review, 1959, 253-84.
Stigler, G., and G. Becker. "De Gustubis Non Est
Disputandum." American Economic Review, March 1977, 76-90.
HAROLD DEMSETZ, Professor of Economics, University of California in
Los Angeles.