Testing for efficiency in lotto markets.
Scott, Frank A., Jr. ; Gulley, O. David
I. INTRODUCTION
When some agents behave irrationally or when some markets operate
inefficiently, opportunities exist for others to profit. The profit
motive tends to eliminate these opportunities so that markets will tend
to be efficient. Interest in the efficiency of markets has led to much
empirical testing. An enormous amount of work has been done in the field
of finance investigating the efficiency of various financial markets.
Another area where individual rationality and market efficiency are
prominent is wagering markets. While the economic significance of
financial markets dwarfs that of wagering markets, gambling events offer
excellent natural experiments for examining the same sort of economic
behavior exhibited in financial markets. One gambling instrument,
state-sponsored lotto games, is particularly interesting because of the
way the mathematical expected value of a bet is determined.
Lotto differs from most other lottery products because the expected
monetary value of a ticket depends on the behavior of other bettors. The
expected value also depends on the amount of money rolled over (if any)
from the previous drawing's jackpot. Repeated drawings of a lotto
game thus present consumers with a range of betting opportunities, some
more favorable than others. In deciding whether to purchase tickets,
bettors must evaluate the expected monetary return, which requires them
to forecast sales. A rational expectations equilibrium in the lotto
market will not exist unless bettors' individual forecasts lead to
an overall level of sales and ex post expected value that conform to their original expectations.
There are several aspects of lotto that make its study worthwhile. As
with financial markets, a significant portion of the population
participates. Just like investors, lotto players must formulate
expectations about the return on their investment. Expected monetary
return depends on the behavior of other players. Unlike investing in the
stock market, however, the outcome of the purchase of a lotto ticket is
based on objective probabilities. As Thaler and Ziemba [1988, 162] point
out, the conditions for learning are optimal in lotto because there is
quick and repeated feedback. If an efficient market equilibrium does not
exist in lotto, we should not be optimistic about finding one in more
complicated financial markets.
The next section introduces the notions of efficiency developed by
Fama [1970] and applies them to wagering markets. The third section
follows with an explanation of the lotto game and how the expected
monetary value of a bet is determined. The fourth section contains tests
of the weak form of market efficiency using data from the Kentucky,
Massachusetts, and Ohio lotto games. Finally, in the fifth section
strong-form efficiency is evaluated using these same games and applying
the concept of a rational expectations equilibrium.
Unsurprisingly, we find that very rarely do lotto games offer a
positive net expected return, thus meeting the requirements of weak-form
efficiency. More importantly, we find general support for the existence
of a rational expectations equilibrium in lotto markets. In most cases
individual bettors' decisions to play generate a level of sales
that conform to their original expectations of the expected value of a
lotto ticket.
II. EFFICIENCY IN WAGERING MAVKETS
A capital market is efficient if there are no investment strategies
that will yield abnormally high returns. Fama [1970] defines efficiency
to mean that security prices reflect all the information contained in a
given information set. If the information set is comprised of only
historical prices, the market is weak-form efficient. If the information
set includes all publicly available information, the market is
semi-strong-form efficient. The inclusion of insider information as well
makes the market strong-form efficient.
Interest in efficiency has led to much empirical testing of the
efficiency of financial markets. Most work finds that markets are by and
large efficient, but there are exceptions. LeRoy [1989] and Fama [1991]
provide recent surveys of the prodigious research on capital market
efficiency. Richard Thaler writes a regular column on
"Anomalies" in the Journal Economic Perspectives. Many
examples for the column come from the field of finance.
The notion of efficiency can be applied to other areas. Wagering
markets present an excellent opportunity to test for efficiency. In
considering horseracing and lotteries, Thaler and Ziemba [1988] modify
Fama's definitions to fit wagering markets. They define weak
efficiency to exist if there is no betting opportunity available that
will yield a positive net expected return, i.e., there are no ex ante
profitable betting opportunities. Strong efficiency exists if all bets
have expected values equal to (1-t) times the amount bet, where t is the
takeout rate, i.e. the proportion of each bet retained by the betting
agency.
Considerable work has been done on the efficiency of the horserace betting market.(1) Snyder [1978] finds that while one can earn
above-average returns by following certain betting strategies, positive
returns are not to be expected due to the take-out rate collected by the
tracks. Ali [1977] finds that bettors tend to overbet longshots and
underbet favorites, and in a later paper [1979] finds that different
types of bets, which should be identically priced according to the
efficient markets model, are in fact so priced. Asch and Quandt [1987]
take a similar approach, but find some inefficiencies. Asch, Malkiel,
and Quandt [1984] find that net profits may be possible in place and
show betting.
Betting on football (American and English) differs slightly from
horseracing in that it is not pari-mutuel. Zuber, Gandar, and Bowers [1985] examine betting on National Football League (NFL) games and
suggest a strategy that would have produced net positive returns during
their sample period. Sauer, Brajer, Ferris, and Marr [1988] apply that
strategy to a later period and demonstrate that the inefficiencies
disappear. Golec and Tamarkin [1991] also study NFL betting and find
that bets on underdogs or home teams are potentially profitable, if
transactions costs are low enough. Pope and Peel [1989] investigate
betting on English football, where prices are fixed by bookmakers and
differ across firms. They find that this market meets the most important
criterion for efficiency, namely, no trading rule generates abnormal
profits.
Because most lottery products have a negative and unchanging expected
monetary return, only limited research has been done on the efficiency
of lottery markets. Chernoff [1981], Thaler and Ziemba [1988], and
Clotfelter and Cook [1989] evaluate the possibility of favorable
investment opportunities arising from popular and unpopular numbers in
lotto and numbers games. Cook and Clotfelter [1990] derive the
relationship between the expected value of a lotto bet and sales and
rollover, but then investigate economies of scale rather than testing
for the possibility of abnormal returns.
III. EXPECTED VALUE OF A LOTTO BET
The three most common lottery products are instant (or scratch-off)
games, numbers games, and lotto. To win the grand prize in a typical
lotto game, a player buys a one-dollar ticket and must correctly match
six numbers drawn randomly without replacement from, say, forty-four
numbers. This is called a 6/44 game. The probability of any ticket
winning the jackpot in a 6/44 game is 1 out of 7,059,052.(2) Lesser
prizes are often awarded for matching fewer than six of the numbers.
Lottery agencies take out from 40 to 50 percent of each dollar bet, some
of which covers operating costs and the rest of which is turned over to
the state.
Lottos have several interesting features. If the jackpot is not won
on a given draw, the jackpot (minus prize payments for any partially
correct tickets) is rolled over into the jackpot for the next drawing.
These rollovers can create jackpots in the tens of millions of dollars.
In addition, lottos are pari-mutuel games, which means that there can be
multiple winners. Winning ticket holders share equally the grand prize.
Finally, the grand prize usually is paid out over a twenty-year period.
The advertised jackpot is naturally the undiscounted sum of the twenty
annual payments.
The expected monetary value of a $1 lotto ticket thus depends on
several factors, namely, the structure of the game, the value of
previous jackpots (if any) rolled over into the current jackpot, and the
number of tickets bought in the current drawing. Formally, expected
monetary value is
(1) EV = [probability] x [jackpot] x [share] + [expected value of
smaller prizes],
where
probability = probability that any given ticket matches six numbers
drawn randomly without replacement from forty-four possible numbers,
i.e., probability that any ticket wins the grand prize;
jackpot = dollar amount rolled over from previous unawarded jackpots
plus proportion of current sales not retained by the lottery agency;
share = expected share of the jackpot if a winning ticket is held;
and
expected value of smaller prizes = expected value of any smaller
prizes awarded to players who correctly match fewer than six of the
winning numbers.(3)
If bettors choose their numbers randomly, the probability
distribution of winning tickets follows the binomial distribution.(4)
Thus in a 6/44 game with one million players each randomly selecting
their integer combination, the probability that, for example, exactly
two players pick the winning combination is
n[C.sub.k][p.sup.k][(1-p).sup.n-k], where n = 1,000,000, k = 2, and p =
1/7,059,052.(5) Since the probability of any ticket matching the six
correct numbers is very small, and the number of tickets purchased is
typically very large, then the Poisson probability distribution serves
as a good approximation to the binomial distribution. As is shown by
Saunders and Moody [1987] and also by Cook and Clotfelter [1990], the
expected monetary value of a one-dollar ticket thus becomes
(2) EV = [1/N][R + (1 - t)N][1 - [e.sup.-pN]],
where N is total ticket sales this drawing, R is rollover, t is the
takeout rate, and p is the above-defined probability of holding a
winning ticket.
The expected monetary value of a lotto bet thus follows well-defined
laws of probability and depends on readily available information. Since
different values of sales and rollover cause expected value to vary from
drawing to drawing, the responses of bettors can be analyzed. In
addition to the monetary return of the bet, there also exists a
nonmonetary return (i.e. the value derived from watching the numbers
being drawn on television, thinking of how any prize money would be
spent, etc.) The expected total return thus can be written as
(3) E[TR] = EV + E[PL],
where EV is as defined in equation (2) and E[PL] is the anticipated
pleasure or nonmonetary return from betting.
As do previous authors who analyze efficiency in other betting
markets, however, we do not attempt to formally incorporate such
nonmonetary returns in our empirical analysis. Snyder [1978] points out
the difficulty in disentangling, at least statistically, the pecuniary and nonpecuniary aspects of a bet. He concludes that the presence of
these (unmodeled) nonpecuniary aspects merely strengthens his finding of
efficiency in the horserace betting market.
We argue that this reasoning can be applied to our analysis as well.
We seek to determine if pervasive market forces actually work toward
efficiency in lotto markets. Before concluding that lotto markets are
inefficient, caution must be exercised, because such a finding may be
due to misspecification. The existence of a pleasure component that is
not explicitly incorporated may cause us to think that we have
discovered an inefficient market when in fact all that we have found is
that the pleasure component swamps the financial component.
If, however, we find that even in the presence of a pleasure
component which we are not able to incorporate explicitly, lotto markets
tend to be efficient, then either of two conclusions is possible. One is
that financial forces do not work towards efficiency, and that whatever
direction they do work, they are exactly offset by pleasure forces
working in the opposite direction. Alternatively, it may be that
financial forces work towards efficiency, and pleasure forces are
relatively insignificant. While we are willing to admit that the first
alternative is possible, we find the second explanation much more
convincing.
We conclude that lotto offers an opportunity to test for market
efficiency that is perhaps superior to horseracing or football because
ex ante probabilities are objective and not subjective, and because
lotteries do not involve all the nonmonetary consumption benefits of
attending a track and watching the horses race or watching a football
game.
Winning the lotto is, however, an extremely low probability event.
Even if a given draw is characterized by a positive net expected return,
the dollar expenditure and transactions costs of covering even a small
proportion of the possible combinations would be prohibitive for most
players. This aspect of lotteries makes market efficiency tests all the
more interesting, because we are most likely to reject efficiency in
situations like lotto where the economic incentive to optimize expected
return is so small.
IV. DATA
Before proceeding further, a brief discussion of data is in order. We
employ data from four lotto games in three states. The Kentucky Lotto is
a 6/42 game which started out with weekly drawings but soon moved to
twice-weekly drawings. Actual jackpots have been announced at the
beginning of each drawing period, and so are only indirectly driven by
sales. The sample period runs from November 1989 until January 1991.
Massachusetts Megabucks is a 6/36 game with twice-weekly drawings. A
predicted jackpot is announced at the beginning of each drawing period,
but the actual jackpot depends on rollover and sales during the drawing
period. The sample period runs from July 1984 until December 1990.
Massmillions is a 6/46 game with weekly drawings. As with the
Megabucks game, its jackpot is determined by rollover from previous
draws and actual sales during the period. The sample period is from May
1987 until December 1990. The Ohio Super Lotto is a 6/44 game with
twice-weekly drawings. Jackpots are announced at the beginning of each
drawing period. The sample period is from August 1989 until September 1990.(6)
V. BETTOR BEHAVIOR AND A TEST OF WEAK EFFICIENCY
The take-out rate in lottery games is very high compared to other
forms of gambling; therefore it is natural to ask why anyone would play
lotto. As mentioned above, lotto obviously provides a thrill. Clotfelter
and Cook [1989] offer several explanations of bettor behavior and use
responses from surveys of players to back up their hypotheses. Some
bettors play for fun, while others play hoping for financial gain.
Quiggin [1991] attempts to reconcile the risk-seeking behavior implicit
in lottery play with the observation that individuals in general display
risk aversion. He modifies the Friedman-Savage expected utility model
and is able to rationalize the observed structure of prizes in lottery
games.
As discussed above, we do not formally model the nonmonetary returns
of a lotto bet. Our purpose is to test whether financial forces act to
move the market toward efficiency. It is sufficient for our test that
bettors have different reservation prices, these being a function of
bettors' attitudes toward risk and the utility (if any) derived
from betting. The different reservation prices imply a downward-sloping
demand curve for betting. The price of a dollar bet on the lotto is
$1-EV, i.e., the purchase price minus the expected value of a ticket. As
the expected value of a lotto bet rises, the price of a bet falls. Lower
prices induce more players to participate in the game, and existing
players are likely to purchase additional tickets.(7)
Weak-form efficiency exists if there are no betting opportunities
that have a positive net expected value (Thaler and Ziemba [1988]). For
a large enough rollover and a small enough level of sales, the expected
value of a $1 ticket (from equation (2)) can be more than $1. The
potential for profit from such a situation would likely encourage
additional betting, which would reduce the expected value to no more
than $1. Using data from the lotto games described above, we can test
for weak-form efficiency.
The expected values of a one-dollar lottery ticket over repeated
draws for each of these games are plotted in Figures 1-4. For the
Kentucky Lotto in Figure 1, expected value varies from $0.09 to
$0.58.(8) These figures assume that bettors realize the announced
jackpot is the undiscounted sum of twenty annual payments and are able
to calculate present value.(9) If that is so then the Kentucky Lotto
market is weakly efficient. If bettors use the announced (undiscounted)
jackpot the expected value would vary from $.18 to $1.17.
Figure 2 contains expected values for the Massmillions game.
Discounted present values of the jackpot are used, rather than
undiscounted values. Expected values range from $.28 to $.95. Expected
values never exceed the dollar price of a ticket, hence the Massmillions
market is also weakly efficient. Figure 3 contains the Megabucks
expected values, also using discounted present value of the jackpot.
Only once in six years did the game yield a positive net expected
return. Figure 4 contains the Ohio Super Lotto expected values, which
range from $0.16 to $0.76. Again, weak efficiency is indicated. That
expected returns are consistently negative suggests risk-seeking
behavior or nonpecuniary returns or both on the part of bettors.
Weak-form efficiency requires relatively simple bettor behavior: they
must be able to recognize the potential for abnormal profits. Their
collective response then eliminates this potential. We now turn our
attention to strong-form efficiency, which involves more sophisticated
bettor behavior: the ability to forecast the expected value of a lotto
ticket given the information available to them.
VI. STRONG EFFICIENCY AND A TEST OF A RATIONAL EXPECTATIONS
EQUILIBRIUM
If bettors knew ex ante what the expected value of a ticket would be
in each drawing, then an analysis of lotto demand would be like any
other commodity whose price is known with certainty. It is not so
simple, however, because the expected value of a ticket depends on the
behavior of other bettors and is only known with certainty ex post.
Bettors must project expected value based on what they think other
bettors will do.
Strong-form efficiency exists if all bets have expected values equal
to one minus the takeout rate (Thaler and Ziemba [1988]). Both Kentucky
and Ohio claim ultimately to return 50 percent of each bet to players in
the form of prize money, and Massachusetts pays out 60 percent. From
Figures 1-4 it is clear that expected values vary significantly from
drawing to drawing, both exceeding and falling short of one minus the
takeout rate. Strong form efficiency would seem not to be supported by
the data in Figures 1-4.
With lotto games, however, such a simple test is not sufficient. As
equation (2) indicates, the expected value of a lotto ticket depends on
the structure of the game (i.e. the probability), the dollar amount
rolled over from previous drawings, and the number of tickets purchased
by bettors. The odds structure of the game does not change from drawing
to drawing; however, rollover and sales do. The combined effect of
rollover and sales on expected value can be seen if we plot the
relationship between expected value and sales for different values of
rollover. A different convergence path (i.e. the relationship between
expected value and sales) exists for each value of rollover. Figure 5
illustrates the convergence path in the Massmillions game for selected
rollover amounts.
Figure 5 indicates that in the Massmillions game, if there is no
rollover and sales equal $4,400,000, a one-dollar ticket has an expected
value of $.19. If sales equal $8,800,000 then expected value rises to
$.31. If $4,000,000 has been rolled over from previous drawings and
sales equal $8,800,000, a one-dollar ticket has an expected value of
$.58. In the limit, as sales approach infinity, expected value converges
to one minus the takeout rate.(10)
Now, in practice which is more important in determining expected
value, sales or rollover? During the period between May 1, 1987 and
December 7, 1990, sales typically ranged from between one and five
million dollars, with an average per draw of $2,055,000. Rollovers
ranged from zero to $22,554,000. Since expected value only approaches
one minus the takeout rate in the limit, and since bettors under
ordinary circumstances are only willing to buy a limited number of
tickets, in any given draw of an actual lotto game expected value will
depend largely on the size of the rollover. Over the feasible range of
sales there will still likely be a significant difference between
expected value and one minus the takeout rate, even if bettors behave in
the manner that we have described. A simple comparison of expected value
with one minus the takeout rate thus does not constitute a meaningful
test of strong-form efficiency.
Since a direct test of strong-form efficiency is not possible, we
propose the following test of market efficiency instead. At the
beginning of each drawing period, information is available to bettors on
the amount of rollover, whether the draw will be held on a weekday or
weekend, and previous sales trends. Bettors will decide whether to play
the lotto based on their reservation price and their assessment of the
expected return. The expected return depends on other bettors'
behavior; therefore each bettor must generate his or her own forecast of
total sales. The relevant question becomes: do lotto players make
systematic errors in their forecasts of sales and hence expected value?
The concept of a rational expectations equilibrium is useful here. If
lotto players make systematic forecast errors then the lotto market is
not in equilibrium. If expectations are not correct on average, then
expectations will not be confirmed by the outcomes of the game and
rational players will adjust their expectations. Let us use Figure 5 to
illustrate. Suppose that when rollover is zero the typical bettor
forecasts sales to be $8.8 million. If this bettor finds the projected
expected value of $0.31 attractive, he or she will buy lotto tickets. If
actual sales when rollover is zero are only $4.4 million instead of $8.8
million, the realized return on a lotto ticket will only be $0.19, which
is less than expected. If bettors comprehend and are able to process
that information, then they will buy fewer tickets in subsequent
drawings with similar rollovers.
A rational expectations equilibrium occurs when expectations generate
an outcome that conforms to those expectations. In the context of lotto
this means that bettors forecast sales and expected value, and then
decide whether to play based on that forecast. Equilibrium means that in
aggregate, bettors' decisions to play generate a level of sales
that conform to their original expectations of sales and hence, expected
value.
Testing for a rational expectations equilibrium in this context
involves more than determining whether bettors' forecasts of sales
are orthogonal to the information set available at the beginning of each
drawing period, which is the standard test of rational expectations. In
our model bettors are not concerned about sales per se, instead they
care about the expected value of a bet. That requires them to take their
sales forecast and combine it with their understanding of probability to
generate a forecast of expected value, because it is their projection of
expected value that determines whether and to what extent they purchase
lotto tickets.(11)
To perform the test we regress the outcome of the lotto drawing, ex
post expected value (computed from equation (2)), on the information
available to bettors at the beginning of each drawing period. This
includes rollover, whether a Wednesday or Saturday draw, the official
prediction of the jackpot, and prizes in competing games. If
bettors' predictions of expected value are fully captured by these
items, then the errors that they make in forecasting expected value will
contain no extractable information, i.e. they will be random. The
residuals of the regression equation would then be uncorrelated with
actual ticket sales. If bettors systematically misforecast expected
value, then the residuals will be correlated with actual sales. A player
could improve his or her expected return by playing the lotto only when
other bettors have underforecast expected value.(12)
Results for the Massmillions game are contained in Columns A and B of
Table I. Massmillions drawings are held on Friday nights. Rollover is
known at the beginning of each drawing period. The lottery agency
announces a projected jackpot based on its own forecast of sales. In
separate regressions investigating lotto demand Massmillions players
displayed some sensitivity to the Saturday Megabucks lotto.
The information set available to bettors thus contains Massmillions
rollover, Megabucks rollover, the estimated jackpots for both
Massmillions and Megabucks, and a time trend. Bettors are assumed to
forecast expected value using a quadratic functional form. Hence ex post
expected value is regressed on the items in the information set plus
squared terms for Massmillions rollover and Megabucks rollover. When the
residuals from this regression are regressed on Massmillions sales,
there is no significant relationship. This result is consistent with the
existence of a rational expectations equilibrium in the Massmillions
game.
Megabucks drawings occur on Wednesday and Saturday nights. Rollover
is known at the beginning of each drawing period. The lottery agency
announces a projected jackpot based on its own forecast of sales. The
expected value of a Megabucks ticket is regressed on these variables
plus a time trend and rollover squared, and the results are contained in
Column C of Table I.(13) Next, the residuals from this regression are
regressed on ticket sales. These results are in Column D. The
significant negative relationship between sales and the residuals
indicates that bettors systematically underpredict expected value when
rollover is small, and vice versa.(14)
The Kentucky Lotto differs somewhat from the Massachusetts lottos in
that the jackpot is announced at the beginning of each drawing period
and does not depend on sales during the period. The jackpot leads rather
than lags sales. To estimate expected value bettors need to forecast
sales only because the number of other bettors affects the probability
that they will have to share the prize. The expected value regression
for Kentucky thus includes jackpot and its square, a time trend, a
weekly drawing dummy variable for the first twenty-four weeks when
drawings were only held on Saturday nights, and a Wednesday drawing
dummy for midweek draws after a twice-weekly format was adopted.
These results are contained in Column A of Table II. The
significantly negative coefficient for the Wednesday drawing reflects
[TABULAR DATA FOR TABLE 1 OMITTED] the lower sales associated with
middle-of-the-week drawings. The significantly positive coefficient for
the time trend is opposite that of the Massachusetts lottos. Since
Kentucky uses a pre-announced jackpot, if sales decline over time then
the probability of sharing the prize falls and hence the expected value
for a given jackpot rises. This result is therefore consistent with the
negative time trends in the two Massachusetts lottos.
When the residuals from this regression are regressed on sales there
is a significant negative correlation. An analysis of the residuals,
however, reveals an interesting occurrence. Shortly after the
introduction of the Kentucky Lotto, the jackpot rolled over nine times
without a winner and grew to $5,000,000. The accompanying media blitz led to a more than doubling of ticket sales from the ninth draw to the
tenth, when the jackpot was finally won.
[TABULAR DATA FOR TABLE 2 OMITTED]
The residual associated with this drawing is an extreme outlier.(15)
When that particular observation is not included in the regressions, the
correlation between sales and the residuals is not statistically
significant.(16) One possible explanation is that, given the novelty of
the game, Kentucky lotto players had no basis for forming expectations
about other players' behavior. As a group they overreacted to the
large jackpot, driving expected value below what they had anticipated.
More recent jackpots have grown to as large as $10 million without
eliciting such responses.
The Ohio Super Lotto uses pre-announced jackpots just like the
Kentucky Lotto. It is a game that has existed for a number of years,
with fairly minor changes in the determination of the jackpot from time
to time. Thus there should be no novelty effects in the sample period
chosen. The expected value regression includes the announced jackpot and
its square, a time trend, and a dummy for Wednesday draws. Results are
in Column C of Table II, and they contain no surprises. Regressing the
residuals of this regression on sales yields no significant correlation,
which is consistent with a rational expectations equilibrium.
VII. SUMMARY AND CONCLUSIONS
Market efficiency is a critical concept in economics and finance.
Only infrequently do situations arise where relatively clean tests of
rational agent behavior or market efficiency can be conducted.
State-sponsored lotto games do seem to offer such an opportunity,
because the mathematical expectation of a bet depends on, among other
things, bettors' aggregate behavior. In deciding whether to play
each bettor must predict how others will behave and then act on that
prediction.
We find that only on very rare occasions do lotto games offer a
positive net expected monetary return, so that lotto markets are
generally weak-form efficient. The strong-form efficiency requirement
that expected value equal one minus the take-out rate is not meaningful
for a game such as lotto where rollover is one of the primary
determinants of expected value. Hence our application of the concept of
a rational expectations equilibrium to lotto.
Our results offer some support for the existence of a rational
expectations equilibrium. Systematic forecast errors by bettors are not
evident in the Massmillions game and the Ohio Super Lotto. Individual
bettors' decisions to play generate a level of sales that conform
to their original expectations of expected monetary value. That
conclusion is not supported by the Massachusetts Megabucks lotto and the
earliest days of the Kentucky Lotto. It is interesting to note that,
unlike the other three games studied, the structure of Megabucks lends
itself to relatively few rollovers. In Massmillions, Kentucky Lotto, and
Ohio Super Lotto where rollovers occur more frequently and bettors have
more opportunities to learn, bettors' expectations appear on
average to be correct.
1. For a thorough review, see Thaler and Ziemba [1988].
2. The number of possible combinations is given by 44!/6!38!
3. In Massachusetts, for example, these smaller prizes are not
Pari-mutuel and do not vary from drawing to drawing.
4. If players do not choose their numbers randomly, then the binomial
distribution does not describe the probability distribution of bets.
Cook and Clotfelter [1990], however, show that under plausible
assumptions, expected value is asymptotic to the relative popularity of
the particular numerical combination times the proportion of each bet
allocated to the jackpot. They also note that the correlation between
actual "coverage" of combinations bet and the coverage if all
numbers were chosen randomly is close to one.
5. The notation n[C.sub.k] denotes n!/k!(n-k)!
6. Sample periods were chosen such that the structure of each lotto
game remained the same. Each of the games have recently changed formats,
adopting longer odds that lead to more rollovers. The marketing
philosophy seems to be that more rollovers create bigger jackpots and
disproportionate increases in subsequent sales.
7. See Gulley and Scott [1993] for a discussion and estimation of
lotto demand curves.
8. The expected values of a Kentucky Lotto ticket may seem somewhat
low, however, Kentucky offered volume discounts on lotto tickets that
were not available in the other two states. In addition to single
tickets for a dollar, three tickets could be purchased for $2.00 and
eight tickets for $5.00. The average price of a lotto chance in Kentucky
was therefore less than a dollar, and in fact, weighted by the
proportion of each option selected by players, was around $0.66.
9. The present values of the jackpots are computed using the
yield-to-maturity on the twenty-year Treasury bond on the day of the
drawings.
10. The behavior of expected value in the presence of large rollovers
can be understood by inspecting equation (2). Increases in rollover
influence the middle term of the equation, causing expected value to
increase. However, the first and third terms force expected value to
decrease and converge to (1-t).
11. This testing procedure is consistent with the more general model
of betting behavior described earlier in equation (3) that incorporates
both monetary and nonmonetary returns from betting if the two sources of
returns are uncorrelated with each other. We are grateful to the editors
for pointing this out to us.
12. Exploiting such a profit opportunity is difficult in practice
because of the logistical problems encountered in buying a large number
of lotto tickets. Such a strategy is not impossible, however, as was
demonstrated recently when an Australian syndicate attempted to cover
all the numbers in the Virginia state lotto.
13. The time trend variable is included to pick up any factors that
systematically affect sales and expected value over time.
14. Note that as in all tests of rational expectations, ours is a
joint test of rational expectations and the adequacy of our specific
model. It is possible that our model does not fully capture the behavior
of bettors.
15. In the sixteenth week of the newly introduced Kentucky Lotto the
jackpot grew after several rollovers to $3.5 million dollars, before it
was finally won. On the thirty-fourth draw the jackpot grew to $5.0
million dollars. Both were record highs to those respective points in
time, and generated sales frenzies. The residuals associated with these
two observations in the expected value regression are -.017 and -.031,
respectively, by far the largest residuals in the sample.
16. The t-statistic falls from 2.22 to 1.57, which is not significant
at the 10-percent level.
REFERENCES
Ali, M. "Probability and Utility Estimates for Racetrack
Bettors." Journal of Political Economy, 85, August 1977, 803-15.
-----. "Some Evidence of the Efficiency of a Speculative
Market." Econometrica, 47, March 1979, 387-92.
Asch, P., and R. Quandt. "Efficiency and Profitability in Exotic
Bets." Economica, 54, August 1987, 289-98.
Asch, P., B. Malkiel, and R. Quandt. "Market Efficiency in
Racetrack Betting." Journal of Business, 57, April 1984, 165-75.
Chernoff, H. "How to Beat the Massachusetts Numbers Game."
Mathematical Intelligencer, 3(4), 1981, 166-72.
Clotfelter, C., and P. Cook. Selling Hope: State Lotteries in
America. Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1989.
Cook, P., and C. Clotfelter. "The Peculiar Scale Economies of
Lotto." Working paper, Duke University, 1990.
Fama, E. "Efficient Capital Markets: A Review of Theory and
Empirical Work." Journal of Finance, 25, May 1970, 383-417.
-----. "Efficient Capital Markets: II." Journal of Finance,
46, December 1991, 1575-1617.
Golec, J., and M. Tamarkin. "The Degree of Inefficiency in the
Football Betting Market." Journal of Financial Economics, 30,
December 1991, 311-23.
Gulley, D., and F. Scott. "The Demand for Wagering on
State-Operated Lotto Games." National Tax Journal, 46, March 1993,
13-22.
LeRoy, S. "Efficient Capital Markets and Martingales."
Journal of Economic Literature, 27, December 1989, 1583-1621.
Quiggin, J. "On the Optimal Design of Lotteries."
Economica, 58, February 1991, 1-16.
Pope, P., and D. Peel. "Information, Prices and Efficiency in a
Fixed-Odds Betting Market." Economica, 56, August 1989, 323-41.
Sauer, R., V. Brajer, S. Ferris, and W. Marr. "Hold Your Bets:
Another Look at the Efficiency of the Gambling Market for National
Football League Games: Comment." Journal of Political Economy, 96,
February 1988, 206-13.
Saunders, S., and M. Moody. "Great Expectations: or Playing the
Odds in the State Lotteries." Northwest Science, 61(4), 1987,
239-48.
Snyder, W. "Horse Racing: Testing the Efficient Markets
Model." Journal of Finance, 33, September 1978, 1109-18.
Thaler, R., and W. Ziemba. "Pari-mutuel Betting Markets:
Racetracks and Lotteries." Journal of Economic Perspectives, 2,
Spring 1988, 161-74.
Zuber, R., J. Gandar, and B. Bowers. "Beating the Spread:
Testing the Efficiency of the Gambling Market for National Football
Games." Journal of Political Economy, 93, August 1985, 800-06.
FRANK A. SCOTT, JR. and O. DAVID GULLEY, Associate Professor,
Economics, University of Kentucky and Assistant Professor, Economics,
Bentley College. The authors would like to thank Steve Holland, Mark
Toma, members of the Applied Microeconomics Workshop at the University
of Kentucky, and two anonymous referees for helpful comments. Gail
Antonellis, Jennifer Bishop, Thomas O'Heir, Susie Chin, Peter
Ramsey, and Dominic Cypriano provided assistance with collecting the
data. Don Brown provided assistance with the figures. Gulley's
research was supported by a Bentley College Summer Research Grant.