The distribution of wealth and the efficiency of institutions.
Eaton, B. Curtis ; White, William D.
THE DISTRIBUTION OF WEALTH AND THE EFFICIENCY OF INSTITUTIONS
This paper explores the effect on economic efficiency of the
distribution of wealth and systems for enforcing property rights. We
construct a two-person, two-period economy in which each person can
consume, plant, transfer or steal corn. We find circumstances in which
redistribution of wealth is Pareto optimal and in which increasing
sanctions against theft to their maximum level is not. These results
suggest that it is not only important to consider distribution in the
design of property institutions, but also that redistribution itself may
serve to increase the efficiency of systems of property rights.
I. INTRODUCTION
A fundamental insight of economics is that property rights may
foster creation of wealth. Nevertheless, property rights which can be
freely violated serve no function, so that to be meaningful, they must
be enforceable. Effective enforcement requires the existence of
enforcement systems to monitor violations, impose sanctions and provide
for restitution of stolen property.
An effective enforcement system produces obvious desirable effects.
By deterring theft and providing for restitution, it assures that
individuals will appropriate the fruits of their labors, and hence
enforcement serves to increase efficiency. It is a standard observation
in the literature on crime and punishment that the possibility of crime
may lead potential victims to alter their behavior in
efficiency-reducing ways. The possibility of street crime may, for
example, empty the streets [Neher 1978]. Conversely, the establishment
of an effective enforcement system can return people to the streets both
by deterring theft, or reducing the probability that it will occur, and
by providing for restitution in the event theft occurs and the thief is
apprehended. We refer to these efficiency-enhancing effects of
enforcement as deterrence and restitution effects.
However, the benefits of operating an enforcement system must be
weighed against its costs. Such a system may be resource using, and may
yield undesirable as well as desirable effects. Thus, maintaining a
criminal justice system entails direct costs--resources to operate a
police force, courts and prisons--and indirect costs in that potential
criminals may modify their behavior to adjust to the prospect of
sanctions in efficiency-reducing ways (see Becker 1968, Usher 1986). A
criminal may, for instance, dissipate resources in the face of expected
sanctions, or otherwise deploy them in an inefficient fashion to escape
appropriation. Hence, the tendency of criminals to exhibit apparently
high discount rates observed by Wilson and Herrnstein [1985] may reflect
the prospect of sanction rather than indicate a strong preference for
immediate gratification, as they suggest. Likewise, the reduced risk of
appropriation may explain the willingness of criminals to pay large
transactions costs to maintain secrecy in Swiss bank accounts. We refer
to these efficiency-reducing effects of enforcement systems as sanction
effects.
Cheung [1970] and others have observed that the costs of enforcing
property rights may depend on their distribution.(1) Ehrlich's
[1973] finding that there is a positive relation between the level of
crime and the degree of income inequality is supportive of this view.
Beyond this, it has frequently been suggested that redistribution may
increase respect for property rights along with monitoring and
sanctions. The notion that giving people more to lose can render them
more law abiding is central to liberal theories of rehabilitation. It is
also embedded in efficiency wage models, where high wages are shown to
be economical to the extent they increase the efficacy of sanctions and
extend an employer's basis for control. (See for example Eaton and
White [1983], Yellen [1984]).
Any wealth transfers to individuals must, of course, come from
other individuals. Redistribution may serve to control behavior not only
because it gives those who potentially may violate property rights more
to lose, but also because it reduces what is left for them to steal. For
instance, Johnson [1986] draws on this notion to explore the role of
ritual gift giving to guests during potlach ceremonies among the
Kwakiutl Indians. He argues that in the Pacific Coast salmon fisheries,
where yearly harvests were highly variable, gifts from tribal groups who
had experienced a good year (typically potlach hosts) to those who had
experienced a lean one (typically guests) served, through the resulting
redistribution of wealth, to deter theft in both ways.
In this paper we focus on the role of wealth distribution in a very
simple general equilibrium model in which deterence, restitution, and
sanction effects are possible. Our model is a two-person, two-period,
corn economy. Both individuals in our model have the option of consuming
initial endowments of corn in the first period or planting them for
harvest in the second period. The yield in the second period exceeds the
amount planted. But whereas property rights are assumed inviolate in the
first period, they are not in the second; corn is safe in hand, but not
on the stalk. Attempts to enforce property rights may entail deterrence
and restitution effects--individuals plant corn they otherwise would
have consumed because they feared theft. However, enforcement may also
entail sanction effects--those intending to steal anyway may consume
corn instead of planting it since they anticipate its confiscation through sanctions.
The enforcement mechanisms we consider involve a probability of
apprehension and wealth-constrained sanctions. We discover that whether
a particular mechanism produces an efficient or an inefficient outcome
is very much dependent on the distribution of the economy's initial
endowment of corn. Indeed, when the mechanism produces an inefficient
equilibrium, Pareto-optimal redistribution is a distinct possibility.
Our model captures the externalities which are associated with
theft and with attempts to control it. Since theft uses resources, it
raises other economic issues which we have ignored. Benoit and Osborne
[1987] examine the role of distribution in a model where the only
economic problem raised by the possibility of theft is that it is
resource using. Hence their analysis is complementary to ours, as are
their results. They too discover that distribution plays a central role
in determining the efficiency of any system of property rights.
The balance of this paper is organized as follows. In section II we
present our model. In sections III and IV, we explore equilibria of the
model. In section V we examine comparative statics with respect to the
distribution of wealth. In section VI we close with a brief discussion
of our results.
II. A TWO-PERSON, TWO-PERIOD CORN ECONOMY
We begin our examination of the role which the distribution of
wealth plays in supporting property institutions by developing a
primitive two-person, two-period, corn economy. The preferences of the
two individuals, One and Two, are captured in the following linear
utility functions: (1) [U.sub.i]([x.sub.i],[y.sub.i]) = [x.sub.i] +
[y.sub.i], i = 1,2, where [x.sub.i] is corn consumed in period 1 and
[y.sub.i] is corn consumed in period 2.(2) The aggregate initial
endowment of corn is W units, and [W.sub.i] denotes i's initial
endowment. Thus (2) [W.sub.1] + [W.sub.2] = W. We assume throughout that
[W.sub.1] [is greater than or equal to] [W.sub.2]. A unit of corn
planted in period 1 yields G > 1 units in period 2. Since utilities
are linear in aggregate corn consumption and G exceeds unity, efficiency
or Pareto-optimality requires that all the corn be planted in period 1
and the harvest consumed in period 2.
The Problem
We assume that either individual can eat some or all of his
endowment in period 1, where there is an inviolate property right in
corn for one period. However, once corn is planted and ready for harvest
a question arises. How much of the total harvest will One appropriate
and how much will Two appropriate? To answer this question, we need an
assumption regarding the technology of corn harvesting. It seems natural
to assume that each individual will harvest half of the corn in the
field. That is, in the absence of an institution of property, corn in
the field is common property.
The equilibrium of the common property model depends on the
magnitude of G. Let [z.sub.i] denote the quantity of corn planted by
individual i. Thus (3) [z.sub.i] = [W.sub.i] - [x.sub.i], i = 1,2, that
is, the individual plants what he does not consume in period 1.
Objective functions, [V.sub.i](z), can then be written as (4)
[V.sub.i](z) = ([W.sub.i] - [z.sub.i]) + G([z.sub.1] + [z.sub.2])/2,
where z = ([z.sub.1], [z.sub.2]). The first term is [x.sub.i], equal to
[W.sub.i] - [z.sub.i], and the second is [y.sub.i], equal to one-half
the total harvest.
The partial derivative of [V.sub.i](z) with respect to [z.sub.i] is
-1 + G/2. This derivative is positive if and only if G exceeds two.
Hence in a Nash equilibrium, each individual will plant all of his
initial endowment if G exceeds two, and none of it if G is less than
two. In the former case there is no interesting economic problem since
the economy is on its utility possibilities frontier. Thus we assume
that G is less than two. For simplicity, we let (5) G = 3/2 In this case
the sum of utilities in the common property equilibrium is W, which is
less than the maximum potential utility, 3W/2.
Now we have a problem--the economy is inside its utility
possibilities frontier--that an institution of property rights might
solve. Before we proceed, we should be clear about the nature of the
economic problem our model captures. Given an institution of property,
harvesting the other person's corn is theft. As noted above, there
are two distinct economic problems associated with theft: it wastes
resources, and it creates an externality. We are ignoring the first of
these--theft is not resource using in our model. It does however create
a negative externality--theft reduces the private return to planting
corn and hence may induce either or both individuals to plant no corn,
forcing the economy inside its utility possibilities frontier.
This externality is quite similar to the externality associated
with common property. If, for example, we were to simply promulgate property rights by announcing that "in period 2, [Gz.sub.i] is the
property of individual i," but provided no enforcement mechanism,
then each (amoral) individual would steal half of the other's
harvest. Consequently, neither would capture all the returns to the corn
he plants. Anticipating this externality, neither would plant any corn,
and the economy would be inside its utility possibilities frontier just
as it was when corn in the field was common property.
An enforcement mechanism that uses sanctions to deter theft and
pays restitution to victims of theft may solve this problem. However, it
may also create a negative externality borne by the thief. Suppose, for
example, that the enforcement mechanism does not fully deter theft, so
that one individual steals from the other in equilibrium. Sanctions then
imply that the thief cannot capture all the returns to the corn he
plants; that is, there are sanction effects. In our model, the sanction
effect sometimes leads the thief to plant none of his corn. This in turn
implies that maximal sanctions are not necessarily optimal.
These two externalities, the first associated with theft, and borne
by the victim of theft, and the second associated with the attempt to
control theft, and borne by the thief, imply that the design of
efficient property institutions is a delicate matter. Increasing the
effective sanction for theft mitigates the externality which the
potential victim of theft bears, but it increases the externality which
the potential thief bears.
Institutions of Property
There are many possible systems of property rights. To produce a
tractable model, we choose to examine a system which can be
characterized by two parameters. Each individual is endowed with a
nominal property right to the corn he plants--if individual i plants
[z.sub.i], then [Gz.sub.i] is nominally i's property in period 2.
An enforcement mechanism exists, characterized by the parameters P and
[Lambda]: 0 [is less than or equal to] P [is less than or equal to] 1, 0
[is less than or equal to] [Lambda] [is less than or equal to] 1. P is a
probability of apprehension and 1 characterizes the sanction imposed on
the (apprehended) thief. The enforcer is an external policeman--not One
or Two--who is presumed to be incorruptible.
If individual i steals from j, he will be apprehended with
probability P. In the event that he is apprehended, i is forced to
return all of the stolen corn to j and, in addition, is forced to pay a
sanction to j. The sanction paid to j is [Lambda][Gz.sub.i]; that is,
the thief pays a proportion [Lambda] of his corn harvest to the
victim.(3)
If both individuals steal, the situation is more complex. A thief
may choose not to report the theft of his own corn if by doing so he
increases the probability that his own transgression will be discovered.
Hence the enforcement mechanism may or may not come into play. And if it
does come into play, the probability that either thief is caught will be
less than P, given a fixed effort from the enforcer. For these reasons
it is not clear what we ought to assume regarding the probability of
apprehension in this case. Guided again by tractability, we assume that
when both individuals steal, the probability of apprehension is zero.
Note that while the magnitude of sanctions is here bounded by the
thief's tangible wealth, it is straightforward to extend our
analysis to consider other sorts of sanctions: for example, sanctions
involving loss of life or liberty. It is sufficient for our purposes
that the utility cost of sanctions be finite. In this regard, observe
that even the death penalty has not always proved adequate to deter
theft. In any case, society routinely sets limits on the magnitude of
sanctions--the U. S. Constitution, for instance, prohibits cruel and
unusual punishments. Such limitations may reflect humanitarian
considerations or concerns about misapprehension, the perverse incentives that can be created when multiple types of offenses are
involved (see Stigler [1970] on this sanction effect), or other sanction
effects.
Equilibrium
The structure of the game we analyze is this: at the beginning of
period 1 both individuals simultaneously choose [x.sub.i] (or
[z.sub.i]); at the beginning of period 2 both individuals simultaneously
choose how much corn, if any, to steal from the other; decisions with
respect to theft having been made, thieves are instantaneously
apprehended, and restitution and sanctions instantaneously paid.
Rational choice with respect to [x.sub.i] (or [z.sub.i]) in period
1 requires individual i to anticipate his own choices and j's
choices in period 2. Hence the appropriate equilibrium concept is
perfect Nash equilibrium, which ensures that individuals correctly
anticipate both their own and each others actions in period 2. That is,
perfect Nash equilibrium ensures that decisions are perfectly informed
and individually utility maximizing. The common property equilibrium we
found above is a perfect Nash equilibrium since, when making his own
planting decision in period 1, each individual correctly anticipated
that he would appropriate half of the total harvest in period 2.
In the common property equilibrium, both individuals plant all of
their corn when G > 2 and none of it when G < 2. These corner
solutions are obviously driven by the linearity of the basic
model--utility is linear in [x.sub.i] and [y.sub.i], and corn harvested
is linear in corn planted. Not surprisingly, this linearity, in
conjunction with the linearity of the property institution, produces
corner solutions in the property rights model as well--in any pure
strategy equilibrium each individual plants all of his corn or none of
it. Hence we can greatly simplify the analysis by restricting individual
strategies to these extreme cases. That is, we assume that [z.sub.i] (or
[x.sub.i]) is either zero or [W.sub.i]. A version of the paper in which
we do not use this simplifying assumption is available from the
authors.(4)
III. PERIOD 2 EQUILIBRIA
Our assumption of a perfect Nash equilibrium requires that we begin
the analysis by characterizing the equilibrium of the period 2 game of
theft, taking period 1 planting decisions as given. Since there are four
possible combinations of planting decisions in period 1, we must
consider four possible subgames in period 2: Subgame I, in which z =
(0,0); Subgame II, in which z = ([W.sub.1] ,0); Subgame III, in which z
= (0,[W.sub.2]); Subgame IV, in which z = ([W.sub.1],[W.sub.2]). In
Subgame I, there is no corn to steal and hence no theft. In Subgame II,
Two will steal half of One's corn since Two has no corn of his own
and hence nothing to lose in the event that he is apprehended.
Similarly, in Subgame III, One will steal half of Two's corn.
All of the interesting possibilities arise in Subgame IV where each
individual is both a potential thief and a potential victim of theft. If
i chooses to steal from j, he will steal as much as possible, half of
j's harvest, since both the probability of apprehension and the
sanction are independent of the amount of corn stolen. The payoffs in
this game of theft are presented in Table I. An S denotes the strategy
"steal" and a D the strategy "don't steal," and
the first entry in each strategy combination is One's strategy and
the second Two's.
With strategy combination (D,D) each individual consumes his own
harvest, (3/2)[W.sub.1], and with combination (S,S) each individual eats
half of his own harvest and half of the other's. With strategy
combination (D,S), Two steals and One does not. In this case realized
payoffs depend on whether Two is apprehended. If he is, One's
consumption is (3/2)([W.sub.1] + [Lambda][W.sub.2]) and Two's is
(3/2)(1-[Lambda])[W.sub.2] since there is full restitution and Two pays
sanction (3/2) [Lambda][W.sub.2] to One. If Two is not caught,
One's consumption is just (3/2)[W.sub.1]/2 and Two's is (3/2)[
[W.sub.2]+[W.sub.1]/2] since Two has successfully stolen half of
One's corn. The payoffs associated with strategy combination (D,S)
are obviously symmetric to those associated with (S,D).
The equilibrium of this two by two matrix game depends upon the
nature of the enforcement mechanism, on (P,[Lambda]). The circumstances
in which both property rights are honored--(D,D) is an equilibrium--are
of central interest. Given strategy D for Two, One will prefer strategy
D if (6.1) (3/2)[W.sub.1] [is greater than or equal to]
(3/2)[P(1-[Lambda])[W.sub.1] + (1-P)([W.sub.1]+[W.sub.2]/2)] and, given
strategy D for One, Two will prefer D if (6.2) (3/2[W.sub.2] [is greater
than or equal to] (3/2)[P(1-[Lambda])[W.sub.2] +
(1-P)([W.sub.2]+[W.sub.1]/2)] When both of these inequalities are
satisfied, (D,D) is an equilibrium strategy combination in Subgame IV.
These inequalities can be written in a more compact way. (7.1) P
[is greater than or equal to] R/(R+2[Lambda]), (7.2) P [is greater than
or equal to] 1/(1+2[Lambda]R), where R is defined to be
[W.sub.2]/[W.sub.1]. R parameterizes relative wealth and is bounded by
zero and one since, by assumption, [W.sub.1] [is greater than or equal
to] [W.sub.2]. Notice that if (7.2) is satisfied, then so is (7.1),
since R [is less than or equal to] 1. Hence (D,D) is the equilibrium
strategy combination whenever (7.2) is satisfied. From (7.2) we see that
large values of P, [Lambda] and R tend to produce the equilibrium in
which property rights are respected in Subgame IV.
Strategy combinations (D,S) and (S,S) are also equilibria of
Subgame IV for certain values of the parameters P, [Lambda] and R.
However, strategy combination (S,D) is never an equilibrium
combination--that is, in Subgame IV if just one individual steals in
equilibrium, the poorer individual is the thief. We record results for
Subgame IV in proposition 1. In each of the three cases the first
inequality pertains to One's choice and the second to Two's.
Binding inequalities are indicated by asterisks.
PROPOSITION 1: Equilibria of Subgame IV
A. (D,D) is an equilibrium if
P [is greater than or equal to] R/(R+2[Lambda]),
[.sup.*P] [is greater than or equal to] 1/(1+2[Lambda]R). B. (D,S)
is an equilibrium if
[.sup.*P] [is greater than or equal to] R/(1+2[Lambda]R),
[.sup.*P] [is less than or equal to] 1/(1+2[Lambda]R). C. (S,S) is
an equilibrium if
[.sup.*P] [is less than or equal to] R/(1+2[Lambda]R),
P [is less than or equal to] 1/(R+2[Lambda]).
These results are illustrated in Figure 1. In the upper-right
portion of the figure neither individual steals, in the middle of the
figure, Two steals but One does not, and in the lower-left portion, both
of them steal. The dashed lines indicate how the partition of the
parameter space responds to an increase in R--that is, a reduction in
inequality.
IV. PERFECT EQUILIBRIA
The fact that Subgame IV, in which both individuals planted their
corn in period 1, has three types of equilibrium in period 2 means that
we must consider three different games in period 1. The first game we
consider is the one in which there would be no theft if both One and Two
planted their corn, which requires that the institution, (P, [Lambda]),
be in the upper-right portion of Figure 1. This game seems to be the
most interesting of the three, and consequently we discuss it at some
length. We simply present results for the other two with minimal
commentary.
Game One: P [is greater than or equal to] 1/(1+2[Lambda]R)
In period 1 an individual's strategy is either to plant all
his corn, denoted by A, or none of it, denoted by N. Observe that in
Game One, P is always greater than 1/3. In Table II we present the
payoffs or utilities associated with the four possible strategy
combinations. The payoffs associated with strategy combinations (A,A)
and (N,N) are straightforward. With strategy combination (A,N), in the
first period One plants his corn and Two eats his, and in the next
period, Two steals from One. Hence Two's expected consumption is
[W.sub.2], what he eats in the first period, plus the expected value of
his theft in the second period, (1-P)(3/2)([W.sub.1]/2). One's
consumption is (3/2)[W.sub.1] if Two is caught and (3/2)[W.sub.1]/2 if
he is not, and his expected consumption is therefore (3/2)[W.sub.1][P+
(1-P)/2]. The payoffs associated with (N,A) are, of course, symmetric to
those associated with (A,N).
The first thing to note about Game One is that (N,N) is never an
equilibrium--at least one individual will plant his corn. Suppose, for
example, that Two chose N. One would then anticipate that Two would
steal from him in period 2 if he chose A. Whether One then chooses A or
N depends upon the probability of apprehension, or more insightfully,
the probability of restitution, since Two will pay full restitution if
he's caught. As you can easily verify, when P exceeds 1/3, which is
always the case in Game One, the restitution effect is strong enough to
induce one individual to choose A if the other chooses N. Hence, (N,N)
is never an equilibrium when P > 1/3. (On the other hand, (N,N) is
always an equilibrium when P < 1/3.)
Now suppose that i does plant his corn, and consider j's
strategy choice. If j also chooses A, he will anticipate that there will
be no theft in period 2 and his utility will therefore be
(3/2)[W.sub.j]. If j chooses N--to eat his corn in period 1--he will
anticipate successfully stealing (1/2) of i's harvest with
probability 1-P, and his expected utility will therefore be [W.sub.j] +
(1-P) (3/4)[W.sub.i]. Hence i choosing A and j choosing N is a subgame
perfect equilibrium if (8.1) [W.sub.j] + (1-P)(3/4)[W.sub.i] [is greater
than or equal to] (3/2)[W.sub.j], or if (8.2) (3/2)(1-P) [is greater
than or equal to] [W.sub.j]/[W.sub.i]. Because P [is greater than or
equal to] 1/3 in Game One, it's clear that if someone does choose N
it won't be the richer individual since (8.2) can never hold when
[W.sub.j] > [W.sub.i]. That is, One will never choose N in Game One.
Letting i = 1 and j = 2, condition (8.2) can be written as (8.3) 3
[is greater than or equal to] 3P + 2R. If this inequality is satisfied
then (A,N) is the subgame perfect equilibrium, and if it is not
satisfied (A,A) is the equilibrium. (Both are equilibria if (8.3) holds
with equality.) Note that large values of P and significant equality in
the distribution of wealth (large values of R) work to produce the
efficient equilibrium in which all the corn is planted. In particular,
the inefficient equilibrium in which Two does not plant his corn is
impossible if the distribution of wealth is equal (if R = 1), or if P =
1.
It makes sense that it will be the poorer individual who
inefficiently eats his corn in the first period and steals in the
second. Suppose that i does plant his corn. Then for individual j, the
opportunity cost of not planting the corn is the increased quantity of
corn that is foregone, equal to (1/2)[W.sub.j], and the inducement is
the corn that would be stolen in period 2, equal to (3/4)[W.sub.i]
(1-P). Thus the opportunity cost is proportional to one's own
wealth, and the inducement is proportional to the other
individual's wealth.
We record our results in proposition 2 and illustrate them in
Figure 2. The first restriction in each case pertains to One's
choice and the second to Two's. The restrictions pertaining to
One's choice are always satisfied in Game One, and hence those
pertaining to Two's choice are binding, and therefore marked by an
asterisk. PROPOSITION 2: Perfect Equilibria of Game One Game One
Restriction: P [is greater than or equal to] 1/(1+2[Lambda]R) A. (A,A)
is an equilibrium if
3PR + 2 [is greater than or equal to] 3R,
[.sup.*3]P + 2R [is greater than or equal to] 3.
No theft in period 2. B. (A,N) is an equilibrium if
3P [is greater than or equal to] 1,
[.sup.*3]P + 2R [is less than or equal to]3.
Two steals in period 2.
When (8.3) holds with equality, Two is indifferent between
strategies A and N. If Two chooses A, the economy is on its utility
possibility frontier, and if he chooses N, the economy is inside the
frontier. Since Two is indifferent between these options, we see that
One bears the full utility cost, equal to [W.sub.2]/2, if Two chooses
strategy N instead of strategy A. This result implies that
Pareto-optimal redistribution of wealth prior to planting decisions in
period 1 is a possibility in Game One. Given the initial distribution of
wealth, if (P,[Lambda]) is at a point like A in Figure 2, then there is
a redistribution of wealth from One to Two which transforms the
inefficient (A,N) equilibrium into an efficient (A,A) equilibrium in
which both individuals are better off.
Two is, of course, always better off if One redistributes wealth to
him. Hence to discover the conditions under which Pareto-optimal
redistribution is possible, we can focus on One's utility. Suppose
that the initial distribution, [Mathematical Expression Omitted], is
such that (8.3) holds with strict inequality, so that the equilibrium
without redistribution is (A,N). Then One's utility is
[Mathematical Expression Omitted]. Now consider the subsequent
distribution, [Mathematical Expression Omitted], such that (8.3) holds
with equality. [R.sup.1] is the most unequal distribution which produces
an efficient equilibrium. Given [R.sup.1], One's utility in the
efficient equilibrium is [Mathematical Expression Omitted].
Pareto-optimal redistribution is possible when (9.1) [Mathematical
Expression Omitted] Using the (implicit) definition of [R.sup.1] and the
identity [Mathematical Expression Omitted], condition (9.1) can be
reduced to (9.2) 3[P.sup.2] - 2P + 4[R.sup.0] - 1 [is greater than or
equal to] 0. For any (P,[Lambda]) in Game One, if [R.sup.0] [is greater
than or equal to] 1/4, then (9.2) is satisfied. Hence, if the
equilibrium of Game One without redistribution is (A,N) and if
[Mathematical Expression Omitted], then it is always Pareto-optimal for
One to redistribute just enough corn to Two so that the equilibrium with
redistribution is (A,A). If [R.sup.0] < 1/4, then redistribution may
or may not be Pareto-optimal. We've illustrated this case in Figure
2. If (P,[Lambda]) lies above the dashed line (3[P.sup.2]-2P+4R-1=0) and
below the solid line (3P+2R=3), then redistribution is Pareto-optimal.
Game Two: 1/(1+2[Lambda]R) [is greater than or equal to] P [is greater
than or equal to] R/(1+2[Lambda]R)
In Game Two if both individuals plant their corn in period 1, the
equilibrium in period 2 is (D,S)--One respects Two's property
right, but Two does not respect One's. Hence payoffs in Game Two
will differ from those in Game One (presented above in Table II) for
strategy combination (A,A). One's payoff is
(3/2)[P([W.sub.1]+[Lambda][W.sub.2]) + (1-P)[W.sub.1]/2], since One eats
all of his own corn and a proportion [Lambda] of Two's when Two is
caught, and eats just half of his own corn when Two is not caught.
Two's payoff is (3/2)[P(1-[Lambda])[W.sub.2] +
(1-P)([W.sub.2]+([W.sub.1]/2)], since Two eats a proportion 1-[Lambda]
of his own corn if he is caught, and all of his own corn and half of
One's if he is not.
In Game Two anything is possible in the sense that there are
permissible parameter values such that any of the four possible strategy
combinations is a perfect equilibrium. The possibilities are summarized
in proposition 3, and illustrated in Figure 3. Asterisks again indicate
binding restrictions, and the first restriction is applicable to One and
the second to Two. PROPOSITION 3: Perfect Equilibria of Game Two Game
Two restrictions:
1/(1+2[Lambda]R) [is greater than or equal to] P [is greater than
or equal to] R/(1+2[Lambda]R) A. (A,A) is an equilibrium if
[.sup.*P][1+(1+2[Lambda])R] [is greater than or equal to] 1+3R,
[.sup.*3][Lambda]P [is less than or equal to] 1.
Two steals in period 2. B. (A,N) is an equilibrium if
3P [is greater than or equal to] 1,
[.sup.*3][Lambda]P [is greater than or equal to] 1.
Two steals in period 2. C. (N,A) is an equilibrium if
[.sup.*3]P[1+(1+2[Lambda])R] [is less than or equal to] 1+3R,
[.sup.*3]P [is greater than or equal to] 1.
One steals in period 2. D. (N,N) is an equilibrium if
[.sup.*3]P [is less than or equal to] 1,
[.sup.*3]P [is less than or equal to] 1.
Two points are worth making: the first concerns sanction effects
and the second concerns the possibility of Pareto-optimal redistribution
from Two, the poorer individual, to One. If the institution is described
by point V in Figure 3, then a small increase in P or [Lambda]
transforms the efficient equilibrium, in which both individuals plant
their corn and Two steals from One in period 2, into the inefficient
equilibrium in which Two does not plant his corn and continues to steal
from One. This result illustrates how the property institution can
seriously distort the thief's incentives. At V the thief plants his
corn just as efficiency demands, but a small increase in P or [Lambda]
induces him to eat his corn in period 1 so that he can avoid the
sanction in the event that he's caught in period 2. Interestingly,
it is One who bears the burden of inefficiency. On the boundary
separating these two types of equilibria, Two is indifferent between
strategies A and N. If he chooses N instead of A, total utility is
smaller by [W.sub.2]/2, which is identical to the (expected) sanction
which Two pays to One if he chooses A. Hence One bears the entire burden
of foregone utility if Two chooses N.
Now consider point Z in Figure 3. At Z, One is indifferent between
A and N. If One chooses N, the economy is inside its utility possibility
frontier, and if he chooses A, the economy is on the frontier. Since One
is indifferent, Two bears the entire burden of the inefficiency. Because
the boundary separating these two regions shifts downward as the
distribution of wealth becomes more unequal, it's now possible that
redistribution from Two to One is Pareto-optimal. That is, if the
property institution is in region (N,A) but close enough to the boundary
with region (A,A), Two will transfer just enough wealth to One to
transform the inefficient (N,A) equilibrium into an efficient (A,A)
equilibrium. Game Three: P [is less than or equal to] R/(1+2[Lambda]R)
In Game Three if both individuals plant their corn in period 1, the
equilibrium in period 2 is (S,S)--property rights are not respected. For
both individuals, the payoffs in Game Three associated with strategy
combination (A,A) are then 3([W.sub.1]+[W.sub.2])/4 since total utility
is 3([W.sub.1] +[W.sub.2])/2 and each gets half the total. (The payoffs
for the other strategy combinations are those presented in Table II
above.)
In Game Three there are three possible equilibria, (N,N), (N,A),
and (A,A). The possibilities are summarized in proposition 4. The first
inequality pertains to One's choice and the second to Two's,
and an asterisk indicates a binding restriction. The equilibria in parts
B and C entail a third restriction on R. If this restriction is not
satisfied, then the set of parameter values that satisfy all relevant
restrictions is empty. PROPOSITION 4: Perfect Equilibria of Game Three
Game Three restriction:
P [is less than or equal to] R/(1+2[Lambda]R) A. (N,N) is an
equilibrium if
[.sup.*P] [is less than or equal to] 1/3,
[.sup.*P] [is less than or equal to] 1/3. B. (N,A) is an
equilibrium if
[.sup.*P] [is less than or equal to] 1/3R,
P [is greater than or equal to] 1/3,
[.sup.*R] [is greater than or equal to] 1/3. C. (A,A) is an
equilibrium if
[.sup.*P] [is greater than or equal to] 1/3R,
P [is greater than or equal to] R/3,
[R.sup.*] [is greater than or equal to] 1/[Square root 3]. As in
Game Two, Pareto-optimal redistribution from Two to One is again a
possibility.
V. DISTRIBUTION AND EFFICIENCY
We have already seen that the distribution of wealth plays a
crucial role in determining the equilibrium of our model and that
Pareto-optimal redistribution is a possibility. This, of course, means
that distribution and efficiency cannot be disentangled--efficiency
demands that both individuals plant their corn, but whether any property
institution induces them to do so depends on the distribution of wealth.
In this section we briefly present some comparative static results that
illustrate just how central the role of distribution is in this model.
When P is less than 1/3, neither individual ever plants his corn
and distribution is therefore irrelevant. Hence we ignore this portion
of the parameter space in Figure 4. (The last panel in the figure
depicts the portion of the parameter space on which we focus.) The
shaded areas in each of the first eleven panels indicate the
institutions which produce inefficient results. In the upper-right
shaded area, Two fails to plant his corn, and in the lower-left shaded
area One fails to plant his. One has the entire initial endowment of
corn in panel 1 (R = 0), and distribution gets progressively more equal
in panels 2 through 11. As the distribution gets more equal, the
upper-right shaded area gets progressively smaller, while the lower-left
shaded area initially increases and subsequently decreases.
Interestingly, when the initial endowment is equally distributed,
inefficiency is never a possibility, and when it is unequally
distributed, there are institutions which induce either individual to
behave inefficiently.
VII. DISCUSSION
As we observed in the introduction, it is evident that the
allocation of property rights can affect their efficiency. Who has what
can make a difference. It is also evident that when there are
externalities associated with both theft and the use of sanctions, the
effects of changes in distribution on efficiency cannot be predicted a
priori. Society is faced with a balancing act between deterrence and
restitution effects on the one hand, and sanction effects on the other.
Because the relative importance of the two types of externalities, as
well as the direct costs of operating enforcement systems, may vary,
they must be evaluated on a case by case basis.
From a policy perspective, our analysis suggests two broad
conclusions. First, it is important to consider the underlying
distribution of wealth in designing enforcement systems. For example, we
discover circumstances in which increasing the magnitude of sanctions
and/or the probability of apprehension may reduce the efficiency of
property institutions so that output falls. Second, it is evident from
our analysis that redistribution itself may increase efficiency. That
is, holding sanctions and the probability of apprehension fixed,
circumstances exist in which it is optimal to redistribute wealth.
A key empirical question is whether in practice the magnitude of
distribution effects is large enough to merit attention. That is, does
(or could) distribution really matter in determining the costs and
benefits of operating enforcement systems? We offered a number of
empirical examples to motivate the discussion in our introduction. But
we view these as suggestive, rather than conclusive, and see a
challenging research agenda emerging out of the analysis presented here.
One promising area for research is the impact of changes in the
distribution of wealth on economic efficiency when the structure of
enforcement systems remains fixed. Extending the type of analysis
performed by Ehrlich [1973] to consider changes in wealth distribution
over time is one possibility. Another promising area for research is to
explore the use of redistribution as a control variable in enforcement
systems as Johnson [1986] does in his analysis of potlatching. There
have been a number of studies of the development of systems of
regulation to address common property problems in resource management,
for example in oil fields [Libecap and Wiggins 1985] or fisheries
[Karpoff 1987]. A common observation in these studies is that small
operators receive favorable treatment. The standard interpretation is
that favorable treatment reflects equity concerns and political
lobbying. While not ruling out this possibility, we note a second
possible explanation, namely that enforcement costs may be lower when
small operators are given more to lose. [Tabular Data 1 and 2 Omitted]
[Figures 1 to 4 Omitted]
(1)See also Bush's [1972] discussion of the formation of
property right systems and Umbeck [1981] on the development of early
property right systems in the California gold fields. (2)One might
object that if [x.sub.i] were zero, the individual would starve. To
blunt this objection we could assume that there are many goods in the
economy (berries, nuts and game as well as corn), but that corn is the
only scarce good. (3)We have analyzed the model with a more conventional
variant of the property institution in which the sanction paid by the
thief is some absolute amount S if [Gz.sub.i] > S, and [Gz.sub.i]
otherwise. That is, the sanction for theft is a fixed, corn-constrained,
sanction. This version of the model is considerably more complex, but
produces the same general insights. For this reason we consider here the
less conventional but more tractable proportional sanction. (4)Without
this restriction on strategies, there are cases in which the model has
no equilibrium in pure strategies. In these cases, the equilibrium of
the simplified model is different from the equilibrium of the
unrestricted model.
REFERENCES
Becker, Gary S. "Crime and Punishment: An Economic
Approach." Journal of Political Economy,
March-April 1968, 169-217. Benoit, J. P. and M. J. Osborne.
"Crime and the Redistribution of Wealth." Working paper,
Department
of Economics, Columbia University, 1987. Bush, Winston C.
"Individual Welfare in Anarchy," in Explorations in the Theory
of Anarchy, edited
by Gorden Tullock. Blacksburg, VA: Virginia Polytechnic Institute
and State University, 1972,
5-18. Cheung, Steven. "Transaction Costs, Risk Aversion, and
the Choice of Contractual Arrangement."
Journal of Law and Economics, April 1970, 23-42. Eaton, B. Curtis
and William D. White. "The Economy of High Wages: An Agency
Problem." Economica,
May 1983, 175-81. Ehrlich, Isaac. "Participation in
Illegitimate Activities: A Theoretical and Empirical
Investigation." Journal of Political Economy 81(3), 1973,
521-65. Johnsen, D. Bruce. "The Formation and Protection of
Property Rights Among the Southern Kwakiutl
Indians." Journal of Legal Studies 15(1), 1986, 41-68.
Karpoff, Jonathan M. "Suboptimal Controls in Common Resource
Management: The Case of the Fishery."
Journal of Political Economy, 95(1), 1987, 179-94. Libecap, Gary
D. and Steven N. Wiggins. "The Influence of Private Contractual
Failure on Regulation:
The Case of Oil Field Unitization." Journal of Political
Economy, 93(4), 1985, 690-714. Neher, Philip A. "The Pure Theory of
the Muggery." American Economic Review 68(3), 1978, 437-45.
Stigler, George. "The Optimal Enforcement of Laws."
Journal of Political Economy, 78(3), 1970,
526-36. Umbeck, John. A Theory of Property Rights with
Application to the California Gold Rush. Ames, Iowa:
Iowa State University Press, 1981. Usher, Dan. "Police,
Punishment, and Public Goods." Public Finance 41(1), 1986, 96-115.
Wilson, James Q. and Richard J. Herrnstein. Crime and Human Nature. New
York: Simon and Schuster,
1985. Yellen, Janet T. "Efficiency Wage Models of
Unemployment." American Economic Review, 74(2), 1984,
200-205.
B. CURTIS EATON and WILLIAM D. WHITE, Simon Fraser University and the
University of Illinois at Chicago. We would like to thank the
participants of more than a dozen workshops, two anonymous referees, and
Tom Borcherding for valuable suggestions.