The consumption risk of the stock market.
Parker, Jonathan A.
OVER THE PAST century in the United States, the average annual
return on the stock market has exceeded that on short-term government
bonds by 6 percentage points. The natural economic explanation for the
premium on equity is the greater risks associated with investing in the
stock market. However, the large premium that we observe cannot be
explained by the canonical, consumption-based asset pricing model. Risk
is best measured as the extent to which a return alters marginal
utility. Since marginal utility is closely related to consumption, and
consumption moves little with returns, the measured risk of the stock
market is small. (1)
One common informal interpretation of this equity premium puzzle is
that stocks are a good deal. In this view, the model is taken as a
reasonably accurate description of optimal behavior and a poor
description of actual behavior. This normative view of the model and the
data implies that households should increase their holdings of equity
and even borrow to invest in the stock market. (2) Such thinking has
also entered important areas of public policy, most notably in proposals
to allow funds from the Social Security system--whether the current $1
trillion surplus in the trust fund or the entire $10 trillion in
implicit liabilities--to be invested in the stock market rather than
entirely in government bonds as is currently done.
The positive view of the equity premium puzzle is that we simply do
not understand asset prices. Since the puzzle was discovered,
economists' efforts to find a model that rationalizes the premium
have yielded little success. That is, there is as yet no model of a
household investment problem with reasonable levels of risk aversion that explains the variation in returns over time, and the difference in
returns between stocks and bonds in particular. This leaves economists
largely unable to model investment behavior and largely unable to
provide policymakers with guidance for the diversification of the Social
Security system.
This paper proposes an understanding of the risk-return trade-off
between stocks and bonds that departs from the canonical model in two
ways. First, I ignore many issues in asset pricing and focus solely on
the ultimate risk to consumption of a given portfolio choice. That is,
rather than measure the risk to consumption as the contemporaneous response of consumption to returns on the stock market, this paper
measures the risk as the medium-term impact of stock market returns on
consumption. (3) Second, in addition to studying the medium-term risk of
equity as measured by aggregate consumption data, I follow Gregory
Mankiw and Stephen Zeldes and ask whether the risk of equity justifies
its return for the subset of households that hold equity. (4) The main
finding of the paper is that the medium-term risk of equity is much
greater than the contemporaneous risk, both for the representative
household and for the representative stock. holder. For households that
hold equity, the medium-term risk is largely sufficient to justify the
high relative return of equity.
Measuring the risk of equity as the medium-term impact of a return
on consumption has several appealing features. First, this approach
maintains the assumption that the primary determinant of utility is the
level of consumption. This assumption is intuitive and has proved useful
and successful in many other branches of economics. Second, this
approach is consistent with the theory of portfolio choice in that the
medium-term risk and the contemporaneous risk should be approximately
the same according to the canonical model.
Most important, the medium-term risk is a better measure of the
true risk of the stock market under a wide class of extant models used
in the study of household consumption and saving. If consumption
responds with a lag to changes in wealth, then the contemporaneous
covariance of consumption and wealth understates the risk of equity, and
the medium-term risk provides the correct measure. This slow adjustment
is a well-documented feature of consumption data: consumption displays
excess smoothness in response to wealth shocks, a result that predates
the equity premium puzzle. (5) Existing explanations for the slow
adjustment of consumption include direct costs of adjusting consumption,
nonseparability of the marginal utility of consumption from factors such
as hours worked that themselves adjust only slowly, constraints on
borrowing or changes in risk that hinder consumption smoothing, and
constraints on information flow or calculation such that household
behavior is "near-rational." The common feature of these
models is that consumption responds slowly to an unanticipated change in
stock market wealth, so that only after some time is the full impact
observed in the movement of consumption.
The medium-term risk provides a robust measure of the risk of
equity in that it allows us to remain to some extent agnostic about the
particular optimization problem faced by households. This robustness
feature is valuable because the correct model of household saving and
portfolio choice has to date escaped discovery. But robustness comes at
the price of not understanding the time variation in the process for
stock returns, which has been the focus of much recent research on the
equity premium. Instead, this paper addresses the question of whether
stocks, given their riskiness, provide reasonable or exceptional returns
within the context of a wide class of models. This approach leads to
three main findings.
First, the contemporaneous covariance of consumption and stock
market returns is misleading. The medium-term risk of equity is close to
an order of magnitude greater than that implied by the contemporaneous
covariance. This result is related to the fact that the
consumption-based capital asset pricing model performs better at long
horizons. (6) This finding is consistent with the slow adjustment of
consumption to a change in wealth, and inconsistent with the textbook
model in which consumption adjusts instantaneously to a return.
Second, even when measured after consumption has adjusted to a
return, the consumption risk of equity remains insufficient to justify
the return. Risk aversion estimated from the medium-term risk, despite
being much lower than risk aversion estimated from the contemporaneous
risk, is still implausibly high and so rejects the set of assumptions
embodied in this measure. For the typical household, consumption rises
by less than 1 percent over a horizon of two years following a 10
percent innovation in stock market prices. Estimated levels of
medium-term risk imply that the coefficient of relative risk aversion
for the representative household would have to be around 40 to
rationalize the equity premium. This is true whether consumption is
measured as flow consumption or as total consumption expenditure.
The third finding, and the main result of this paper, is that the
medium-term consumption risk of equity and the return of equity are
consistent with reasonable levels of risk aversion for those households
that hold stock directly. The marginal investment decision that
determines the risk-return trade-off in equilibrium may not be faced by
households that do not hold equity. Mankiw and Zeldes and subsequent
papers investigate the contemporaneous risk of equity for stockholders
and conclude that the consumption of stockholders covaries more with
returns than does the consumption of the typical household. (7) Using
data from the Consumer Expenditure Survey (CEX) of the Bureau of Labor
Statistics, I show that the covariance of asset returns and the
consumption growth of stockholders over periods from one and a half to
two years is close to two orders of magnitude greater than the
contemporaneous covariance in aggregate data on consumption. Although
these results are subject to considerable statistical uncertainty, a
reasonable decomposition is that half of this increase comes from
measuring medium-term risk rather than contemporaneous risk, and half
from measuring the risk for stockholders using the CEX rather than the
risk for the representative agent using the National Income and Product
Accounts (NIPA). With respect to this second step, there are several
differences between the CEX consumption data on stockholders and the
NIPA consumption data, but the data do not allow a clear decomposition
of the increase in measured risk among these differences. (8) It is
clear, however, that although stockholders do face more equity risk, the
method of aggregation and the population covered in the NIPA data seem
to be important reasons for the lower measured contemporaneous risk of
equity in the NIPA data.
Are the levels of risk aversion implied by average returns and
these levels of risk plausible? In the first set of analyses using the
CEX data, the risk aversion coefficient for stockholders is estimated to
be around 10 to 20. But the period covered by the CEX is one of
unusually high returns in many years. When adjustment is made for the
fact that aggregate measures show an unusually low covariance between
returns and consumption in this period, the return on equity and the
medium-term risk of equity are more plausible. For the preferred measure
of consumption, point estimates of the risk aversion of the typical
stockholder lie between 4 and 8. (9)
Since the consumption risk of equity for the typical household is
significantly less than that faced by households holding equity, stocks
are in some ways a good deal for many households. That is, for the
typical household not now invested in stocks, the expected return on an
investment in equity at the margin outweighs the risks to consumption.
The final section of the paper returns to the implications of these
findings and the questions raised by limited participation in the stock
market.
Measuring the Riskiness of Stocks
Are households allocating their wealth optimally between stocks and
bonds? Or are stocks an undiscovered bargain for most households? The
canonical model for addressing these questions assumes that all
households seek to maximize the expected present discounted value of
utility flows from consumption. Because consumption has diminishing
marginal benefits in any period, households want similar levels of
consumption over time and over future events. When households are
optimally allocating their wealth to consumption and different forms of
saving, an extra dollar invested in stocks instead of bonds increases
the future consumption level that the household expects on average, and
this increase is exactly offset by the increased risk to future
consumption that the extra dollar invested in stock brings. The puzzle
is that if household utility increases with consumption, and only with
consumption in the present, this optimization condition is far from
being met in observed data on consumption and returns. At reasonable
levels of risk aversion, the risk of equity is very small relative to
its return.
To put the question more formally, assume that the representative
household has a utility function of the constant-relative-risk-aversion
form with a coefficient of relative risk aversion [gamma] and the
opportunity to allocate savings between a risk-free asset and a
portfolio of equities that earns the return on the stock market. The
stated optimality condition is
(1) [E.sub.t][[C.sup.[-gamma].sub.t+1](1 + [z.sub.t,t+1])] -
[E.sub.t][[C.sup.[-gamma].sub.t+1]](1 + [r.sup.f.sub.t,t+1]) = 0,
where C is aggregate consumption per capita, [r.sup.f.sub.t,t+1] is
the risk-free real interest rate in the economy between periods t and t
+ 1, and [z.sub.t,t+1] is the return on stocks between t and t + 1. A
dollar invested in equity increases utility in period t + 1 by the gross
payoff of the asset in dollars, 1 + [z.sub.t,t+1] or 1 +
[r.sup.f.sub.t,t+1], times the marginal utility of a dollar,
[C.sup.[-gamma].sub.t+1]. When the investment decision is optimal, the
expected increase in utility from investing one dollar more in stocks is
exactly offset by the expected decline in utility from investing one
dollar less in the risk-free asset.
Following Lars Peter Hansen and Kenneth Singleton, (10) assume as
an approximation that returns and consumption growth are jointly
distributed log-normally conditional on information available in period
t, so that equation 1 can be rewritten as
(2) [E.sub.t][[r.sub.t,t+1]] + 1/2 [var.sub.t]([r.sub.t,t+1]) -
[gamma] [cov.sub.t]([DELTA] ln [C.sub.t+1], [r.sub.t,t+1]) = 0,
where [r.sub.t,t+1] = ln(1 + [z.sub.t,t+1] - [r.sup.f.sub.t,t+1]),
the logarithm of the gross excess return of stocks over the risk-free
rate. Taking the unconditional expectation of equation 2 and
reorganizing yields an equation that can be used to estimate the
relative risk aversion of the representative agent:
(3) [gamma] = E[[r.sub.t,t+1]] + 1/2 [var.sub.c]([r.sub.t,t+1])/
[cov.sub.c]([DELTA] ln [C.sub.t+1], [r.sub.t,t+1]),
where the subscript c denotes the average conditional second
moment: [var.sub.c]([r.sub.t,t+1]) [equivalent to]
E[[var.sub.t]([r.sub.t,t+1])] and [cov.sub.c]([DELTA] ln [C.sub.t+1],
[r.sub.t,t+1]) [equivalent to] E[[cov.sub.t]([DELTA] ln [C.sub.t+1],
[r.sub.t,t+1])]. Estimation of equation 3 requires calculation of
conditional moments, and therefore a choice of conditioning information.
An alternative is to assume that the joint unconditional distribution of
consumption and returns is log normal, so that taking the unconditional
expectation of equation 1 yields
(4) [gamma] = E[[r.sub.t,t+1]] + 1/2 var([r.sub.t,t+1])/
cov([DELTA] ln [C.sub.t+1], [r.sub.t,t+1]).
The average equity premium in U.S. quarterly data from 1959 to 2000
is 0.0529 (5.29 percentage points) with an unconditional standard
deviation of 0.1638. (11) These and all such numbers throughout the
paper are reported at annual rates. The unconditional covariance of
excess returns and the growth rate of real flow consumption over the
same period is 0.00017. These levels of risk and return imply, from
equation 4, that the risk aversion coefficient for the representative
agent is an implausible 379. To put this number in perspective, a
household this risk-averse would be willing to give up more than 24
percent of its consumption to avoid an even-odds gamble in which it
would either win or lose 25 percent of its consumption. Even with a risk
aversion coefficient as low as 10, a household would choose a 19 percent
sure decline in consumption over this gamble. Levels of risk aversion
around 4 are widely considered plausible, and levels above 10 highly
implausible. (12)
We can restate the puzzle by assuming a reasonable level of risk
aversion and asking what the observed covariance of consumption and
returns implies for the equity premium. If the typical household's
risk aversion coefficient were 4, the household would be indifferent at
the margin between stocks and bonds only if E[[r.sub.t,t+1]] + 1/2
var([r.sub.t,t+1]) = 0.00069, or less than one-tenth of 1 percent.
Because stocks return far more, from the perspective of this basic
model, stocks appear to be an amazingly good deal.
Moving beyond the canonical model, first note that the risk of
stocks, the premium on equity, and the intertemporal allocation of
consumption are all jointly evaluated by equations 4 and 3. This is at
odds with the literature on the intertemporal allocation of consumption,
which is in wide agreement that the simple, textbook model of a
representative consumer is false. (13) In particular, the empirical
literature studying consumption and saving behavior suggests that the
following assumptions are at least questionable and at worst quite
misleading: first, that utility is additively separable from factors
that adjust slowly and covary with returns, such as leisure; second,
that uninsurable idiosyncratic risk and borrowing constraints are not
important; third, that consumption can be instantaneously adjusted or,
if there are adjustment costs on some items, such as durable goods, the
utilities derived from these categories are additively separable from
the utility of other consumption; fourth, that aggregate consumption
data accurately measure movements in flow consumption; and fifth, that
households perfectly optimize without informational or calculation
constraints. (14) These findings have not escaped the notice of the
literature on asset pricing. But ever since the discovery of the equity
premium puzzle, macroeconomists have struggled to understand this
combination of high stock returns and low stock risk, to little avail.
There is currently no empirically reasonable, structural model of
household behavior that matches the facts. (15)
It is worth noting that finance theory also does not provide an
understanding of aggregate stock returns and risks. Modern finance
theory prices assets from the assumption of no arbitrage, which means
that risky assets can be priced only in reference to other risky or
nonrisky assets. The return on the aggregate portfolio of stocks can
only be deemed reasonable or unreasonable relative to the prices of a
set of assets that span the returns on this portfolio, that is, relative
to the prices of the assets in this portfolio. (16)
This paper evaluates the risk-return trade-off between stocks and
bonds by focusing on the medium-term risk to consumption rather than
searching for the correct stochastic discount factor to be used to price
assets. Rather than measure the risk to consumption from the
contemporaneous co-movement of consumption and returns, I measure the
risk to consumption by the response of consumption to a return over a
longer horizon, as given by
(5) [cov.sub.c][ln([C.sub.t+1+S]/[C.sub.t]), [r.sub.t,t+1]] or
cov[ln([C.sub.t+1+S]/[C.sub.t]), [r.sub.t,t+1]].
Consumption risk is measured by the covariance of the excess return
of stocks at t + 1 and the change in consumption from t to t + 1 + S,
where S is the horizon over which the consumption response is studied.
To judge whether the medium-term risk is sufficient to rationalize the
equity premium, I calculate the level of risk aversion of the
representative agent implied by each measure. Paralleling much of the
literature on the equity premium puzzle, I calculate risk aversion from
the unconditional moments as
(6) [[gamma].sub.s] = E[[r.sub.t,t+1]] + 1/2 var([r.sub.t,t+1])/
cov[ln([C.sub.t+1+S]/[C.sub.t]), [r.sub.t,t+1]],
where [[gamma].sub.S] denotes risk aversion based on consumption
growth over a horizon of S periods. I also present estimates from the
same equation with the conditional covariance in the denominator. When S
= 0, one recovers the usual estimate, as given by equation 4 for the
unconditional case.
Why evaluate risk using the medium-term risk, as in equations 5 and
6? If households choose their portfolio at time t, and the impact of
this choice and the realized return on stocks take time to appear in the
consumption data, then this measure provides a better measure of the
risk of stocks than does equation 3. To be more concrete, I show that
the medium-term risk of equity would be approximately correct if the
textbook model were true, or if the marginal utility of consumption is
shifted by a stationary variable that covaries with returns. The
medium-term risk is also a better measure when constraints on
information flow slow consumption movements. Finally, aggregate
consumption is constructed using some lagged data. The medium-term risk
correctly measures consumption risk in the presence of this measurement
error.
First consider the textbook model. Households seek to smooth
consumption over time, which is captured by the following consumption
Euler equation for the risk-free rate between t + 1 and t + 1 + S:
(7) [E.sub.t+1][[[beta].sup.S](1 +
[r.sup.f.sub.t+1,t+1+S])[C.sup.[-gamma].sub.t+1+S]/
[C.sup.[-gamma].sub.t+1] = 1,
which implies
(8) [C.sup[-gamma].sub.t+1] = [[beta].sup.S](1 +
[r.sup.f.sub.t+1,t+1+S])[C.sup.[-gamma].sub.t+1+S] -
[[epsilon].sub.t+2,t+1+S],
where [beta] is the factor by which households discount the future,
and [[epsilon].sub.t+2,t+1+S] is the expectation error between actual
marginal utility in t + 1 + S and its expected value in t + 1.
Substituting into equation 1 and noting that the expectation error has a
mean of zero and is uncorrelated with information known at time t + 1
yields
(9) [E.sub.t][(1 +
[r.sup.f.sub.t+1,t+1+S])[C.[-gamma].sub.t+1+S][Z.sub.t,t+1]] -
[E.sub.t][(1 + [r.sup.f.sub.t+1,t+1+S])[C.sup.[-gamma].sub.t+1+S]](1 +
r.sup.f.sub.t,t+1]) = 0.
Under the assumption that consumption and returns are
unconditionally distributed joint normally, risk aversion is equal to
(17)
(10) [[gamma].sub.S] = E[[r.sub.t,t+1]] + 1/2 var([r.sub.t,t+1]) +
cov[ln(1 + [r.sup.f.sub.t+1,t+1+S]),
[r.sub.t,t+1]]/cov[ln([C.sub.t+1+S]/[C.sub.t]), [r.sub.t,t+1]]/
cov[ln([C.sub.t+1+S]/[C.sub.t]), [r.sub.t,t+1]]
The extent to which risk aversion calculated directly from the
medium-term risk as in equation 6 differs from that calculated from the
textbook model depends on the extent to which an innovation to returns
leads to a change in future risk-free rates. Intuitively, according to
the textbook model, if an innovation to returns were to lead to a
significant revision in planned intertemporal substitution in
consumption over the next S periods, then looking S periods out could be
quite misleading. If the only reason for consumption to diverge from
planned consumption between periods t + 1 and t + 1 + S were future
innovations, the medium-term risk would exactly measure consumption
risk.
The size of this additional term is negligible. An upper bound on
this covariance is given by the average unconditional covariance of the
cumulative return from one-period risk-free rates. This upper bound is
two orders of magnitude less than the equity premium at an annual rate,
ranging from -0.0002 at a horizon of one quarter to -0.0008 at a horizon
of ten quarters. Using equation 10 instead of equation 6 throughout the
analysis would lower estimates of risk aversion by 1 percent. In sum, if
the textbook model were true, estimates of risk aversion from the
medium-term risk and from the contemporaneous risk would be very close.
Turning next to more general models in which the medium-term risk
of equity provides an accurate characterization of the risk of equity,
suppose that the marginal utility of the representative agent is shifted
by a variable, [[PSI].sub.t], so that marginal utility is given by
[C.sup.[-gamma].sub.t+1] [[PSI].sub.t+1]. Suppose further that this
variable has a stationary distribution, so that as S gets large, the
distribution of [[PSI].sub.t+1+S] from the perspective of period t is
its unconditional distribution, F(x). That is, for large S,
[[PSI].sub.t+1+S]|t ~ F(x). The factor [[PSI].sub.t+1] captures many of
the extant models of slow adjustment of consumption listed above. This
factor can represent transitory movement, following a market return, in
the share of hours devoted to market work, in the relative productivity
of home production, in the stock of durable goods relative to flow
consumption, in individual consumption risk, in the cross-sectional
distribution of marginal utilities, and so forth. A model in which
marginal utility adjusts at the time of the return, but in which a
stationary confounding variable implies that the contemporaneous change
in consumption does not accurately measure this change, has the property
that, for large enough S, the medium-term risk measures the consumption
risk of equity.
Using the same derivation as for the textbook model, it follows
that risk aversion is given by
(11) [MATHEMATICAL EXPRESSION NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII]
(12) [MATHEMATICAL EXPRESSION NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII]
since the realization of [[PSI].sub.t+1+S] is independent of
information available at time t + 1. Thus the medium-term risk is as
valid a measure of consumption risk in the presence of stationary
utility shifters as it is for the textbook model.
The medium-term risk is also useful for measuring the risk of
equity for some models in which households face constraints on
information, calculation, or adjustment of consumption so that
consumption and marginal utility move only slowly to the new optimal
level following a shock. As a specific example, Xavier Gabaix and David
Laibson add to the canonical model of Robert Merton the assumption that
households face costs of monitoring their portfolio balances, and
therefore check and learn their wealth only infrequently, once every D
periods. (18) Each time a household learns its wealth, it adjusts its
consumption in response to all the market returns during the interval
since it last did so. Assuming that a constant measure of households are
learning their balances and adjusting their consumption at every
instant, aggregate consumption adjusts smoothly and slowly over D
periods to reflect a given return. To evaluate the risk of equity then
requires studying the medium-term risk.
A final reason to evaluate the risk of equity with the medium-term
risk is that aggregate consumption data may measure consumption
responses with delay, even if the true consumption response is
instantaneous. As demonstrated by David Wilcox, (19) serially correlated measurement error is introduced into aggregate consumption data by
sampling error, by the imputation procedures used, and by definitional
difficulties involved in constructing measures of aggregate consumption
from monthly survey data on retail sales.
Measuring Aggregate Consumption and Returns
This section describes the important issues that arise in the use
of consumption and returns data to measure the medium-term risk of
equity. The appendix contains a complete description of the data used.
Consumption is measured in two different ways. First, flow
consumption is defined as real consumption expenditure per capita on
nondurable goods and services less expenditure on education services,
medical care services, housing services, personal business services, and
footwear. This measure of consumption corresponds closely to the
theoretical concept but requires ignoring the remainder of goods and
services that households purchase. Theoretically, this can be justified
if these other goods enter utility in an additively separable manner,
but this is unlikely to be true. In fact, flow consumption
overrepresents goods that are necessities, such as food, and
underrepresents those that are luxury goods, such as household
appliances, medical care, jewelry, and electronics. This is a concern in
measuring the impact of the stock market on consumption because the
response of expenditure should fall more heavily on luxury goods than on
necessities. The typical household reduces its expenditure on luxury
goods by more than on necessities when its wealth declines. This problem
is severe for studying the consumption response to equity because
stockholding is heavily concentrated among wealthier households, for
whom a larger share of expenditure, and of expenditure variability, is
luxury consumption. (20)
To partly deal with this concern, the analysis is also conducted
defining total consumption expenditure as total personal consumption
expenditure less expenditure on education, medical care, and personal
business expenses. This approach is atypical because utility comes from
the service flow from durable goods, not from expenditure on durable
goods. However, the medium-term risk provides the correct measure of
consumption risk even when expenditure on durable goods is included.
Suppose that utility comes also from the service flow from the stock of
a durable good, K,. The stock of the durable good is related to
expenditure as
(13) [K.sub.t+1] = (1 - [delta])[K.sub.t] + [L.sub.t+1],
where [delta] is the rate at which the durable good depreciates. If
there are no costs to households of adjusting the stock of durable goods
that they hold, then expenditure (L,) will be volatile as households
increase or decrease expenditure to adjust their stock, whereas
consumption will remain relatively stable. After the adjustment, the new
level of expenditure will be proportional to the new level of the stock
of durable goods. Using the canonical measure would underestimate risk
aversion, since the contemporaneous covariance of expenditure growth and
excess returns is large, whereas the actual covariance of consumption
growth and returns is significantly lower.
If the growth rate of consumption is stationary, equation 13
implies that the stock of the good, and thus its service flow, is
cointegrated with expenditure. To the extent that a large positive
return leads to an upward revision in the stock of a durable good, this
will still be apparent a few years later in higher expenditure, which is
proportional to the higher consumption flow from the services of this
durable good. This suggests looking at the medium-term response of
expenditure to an excess return, which is exactly what this paper does.
A possible complication is that households seem to face costs associated
with adjusting their stocks of durable goods, and this delays the
adjustment. However, as long as one looks at the response of expenditure
after enough time has elapsed, the adjustment will be complete, and the
change in total consumption will measure the change in utility from both
the service flow from the stock of durable goods and the purchases of
nondurable goods and services.
Both consumption series are deflated by chain-weighted price
indexes constructed from published series. Data cover the first quarter
of 1959 to the fourth quarter of 2000. Excess returns are calculated
over the same period as the difference between the Fama risk-free rate
and the return on the New York Stock Exchange and the American Stock
Exchange composite indexes. The excess return dated t + 1 is the excess
return during the period t + 1.
The Risk of Stocks for the Representative Household
This section uses aggregate consumption per capita to measure the
medium-term risk of equity. Paralleling the previous literature on the
equity premium puzzle, I first estimate unconditional covariances of
excess returns and consumption growth. Second, I analyze conditional
risk both by estimating the response of consumption to innovations in
returns in a vector autoregression and by calculating covariances using
innovations to excess returns. The measures of risk aversion implied by
conditional and unconditional covariances are used to determine whether
the consumption risk of equity is sufficient to rationalize its average
excess return.
The unconditional covariance of consumption growth and excess
returns at horizon S is estimated as
(14) [MATHEMATICAL EXPRESSION NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII]
for which the expected value is the covariance of interest.
Standard errors are calculated as Newey-West standard errors, with the
number of lags equal to the horizon plus one. The risk aversion implied
by each covariance is calculated by replacing the theoretical moments in
equation 6 with their empirical counterparts, and the associated
statistical uncertainty is calculated using the delta method. The
numerator of equation 6 is estimated as 6.63 percent. Since the focus of
this paper is on the consumption risk of equity, this number is taken as
given when making inferences. Standard errors reported for risk aversion
reflect only the uncertainty about the covariance of consumption and
excess returns and not uncertainty about the mean excess return or its
own variance. Because risk aversion is a nonlinear transformation of the
covariance, the standard errors on risk aversion estimates are useful
for inferring the statistical distance from a reasonable (low) level of
risk aversion, and not useful for estimating the statistical difference
from an extremely high level of risk aversion. The latter inference can
be made by examining whether the covariance is statistically different
from zero.
The first row of table 1 reports the unconditional covariances for
each consumption measure and horizon and the risk aversion coefficients
implied by these covariances; standard errors are reported below each
estimate. As discussed in the previous section, the contemporaneous
covariances are extremely low. Since the variance of returns is 0.027,
the covariance implies that flow consumption growth is 0.06 percent
above average when returns are 10 percent above normal. As the table
also shows, such small contemporaneous covariances imply implausibly
high levels of risk aversion. Interestingly, total consumption
expenditure has a lower contemporaneous covariance with excess returns
than does flow consumption, consistent with an important role for
adjustment costs in the dynamics of expenditure on durable goods.
The remaining rows of table 1 show that the covariance of returns
and consumption growth rises significantly with the horizon over which
consumption growth is measured, although this rise is not monotonic. The
covariance of the change in flow consumption over three years and excess
returns is an order of magnitude larger than the contemporaneous
covariance. For total expenditure the increase in covariance is more
striking, but the majority of this increase occurs in moving from the
contemporaneous covariance to a horizon of one quarter. After this, the
covariance doubles as the horizon is increased. The impact of horizon on
the risk aversion coefficient is the inverse of its impact on the
covariance. As risk is measured over longer horizons, the implied levels
of risk aversion decline by an order of magnitude or more for each
series.
One reason this decline might be large is that the economy does not
proceed in three-month-long units of time that neatly align with the
quarters in which the data are measured. If the textbook model were
correct and if consumption portfolio decisions were continuously
reoptimized, the quarterly frequency of the data would imply that the
contemporaneous covariance for flow consumption would be understated by
a factor of two, given the definition of returns. (21) But this
adjustment would not alter the main conclusion that the medium-term risk
is much greater than the contemporaneous risk for flow consumption.
Given adjustment costs, it is unclear what the correct adjustment, if
any, is for total expenditure.
Another possible concern with these results is that the declining
estimates of risk aversion could be due to the fact that estimates using
longer horizons must omit more recent stock market data, for which
consumption data t + 1 + S periods later are not yet available. Thus
estimates with longer horizons do not use data on some of the
spectacular returns on equity in recent periods. This is in fact driving
none of the results. Holding the sample of returns constant across all
horizons--omitting the most recent eleven return observations in all
calculations--makes very little difference. The conclusions are also the
same if the estimates of the mean consumption growth and mean returns
used in calculating the covariance of interest are held constant at
their values calculated for the longest possible sample.
A less skeptical reaction to these results is that reasonable
levels of risk aversion are not far from a 95 percent confidence
interval surrounding these point estimates. One way to assess this
argument is to estimate risk aversion from conditional moments, which is
both a different cut of the data and potentially more precise.
Empirically, the stochastic process of equity returns is such that after
a series of particularly high returns, returns are on average lower, and
vice versa. That is, at horizons of a few years, there is a negative
correlation in returns. Although the predictable component is small
relative to the uncertainty in excess returns, eliminating the
predictability of returns from the covariance of interest may sharpen
inference. However, as noted in the previous section, estimation using
conditional moments requires specifying conditioning information. This
is approached in two ways.
First, I calculate the covariance and risk aversion using the
impulse responses to returns in a vector autoregression (VAR). This
approach has the advantage of providing a clear picture of the
consumption movement that follows an innovation in excess returns and
the advantage (or weakness) Of imposing a smooth response to the
innovation. I estimate a three-variable VAR in excess returns
[r.sub.t-1], the logarithm of consumption (In [C.sub.t]), and the
dividend-to-price ratio [d.sub.t]/[P.sub.t-1], each with four lags. The
dividend-to-price ratio is included because it is a good predictor of
future returns. I take a Bayesian approach, asking the VAR to fit the
unit root in consumption and treating parameters as random. Impulse
responses and confidence intervals are constructed from the estimated
parameters by Monte Carlo methods rather than inversion. The appendix
contains additional details of the method.
Excess returns are ordered first so that the impulse responses
measure the impact of an innovation to returns on consumption. It is
important to note that, as for the covariance, the innovation to returns
is not structural but is an amalgam of structural shocks to the economy
such as news about current labor income or future rates of return. Thus
the estimated impulse response does not measure the marginal propensity
to consume out of stock wealth. It does measure the medium-term risk.
Figures 1 and 2 display the impulse responses of each variable to
an innovation in excess returns. Figure 1 displays the responses of all
three variables for the system that includes flow consumption, and
figure 2 does the same for the system that includes total expenditure.
Both figures display point estimates of the impulse response functions
as well as two-standard-error bands. Both systems show less than a 1
percent change in consumption in response to a 1-standard-deviation
innovation in excess returns (which in each VAR is roughly 7.8 percent
at a quarterly rate). Most of this movement occurs in the first few
quarters following the innovation. In fact, the slope of the impulse
response is not statistically different from zero at five quarters and
beyond. (22) Consumption rises by less than 0.1 percent for a 1 percent
innovation in excess returns at this horizon.
[FIGURES 1-2 OMITTED]
The impulse response of consumption to an innovation in returns
measures the medium-term risk to consumption. The covariance of interest
(at a quarterly rate) is
(15) [cov.sub.c][ln([C.sub.t+1+S]/[C.sub.t]), [r.sub.t,t+1]] =
[[sigma].sub.c]([r.sub.t,t+1]] = [[sigma].sub.c]([r.sub.t,t+1]) x
IR[F.sub.S](ln C),
where IR[F.sub.S](ln C) denotes the impulse response of the log of
consumption at horizon S to an innovation to returns, and
[[sigma].sub.c] ([r.sub.t,t+1]) is the standard deviation of the
innovation to returns in the VAR. To gauge whether the medium-term risk
is enough to justify the average return on equity, I calculate the
implied risk aversion of the representative household by substituting
this covariance into equation 6. (23)
Table 2 shows the point estimates of the medium-term risk and the
implied coefficients of relative risk aversion estimated from each
measure of consumption. Just as for the unconditional covariance,
measured consumption risk rises and estimated risk aversion declines as
the horizon over which consumption risk is measured increases. At a
horizon of a year, the risk aversion coefficient necessary to
rationalize the equity premium is between 30 and 40. Estimates for
horizons beyond three years (not shown) fall to between 20 and 25,
although statistical uncertainty is substantial at this horizon.
Even these implausibly high estimates of risk aversion are on the
low side of those implied by other estimates of the consumption response
to equity innovations in the consumption literature. (24) By estimating
and inverting a VAR, a degree of smoothness is imposed that is not
present in the estimates based on the medium-term risk in table 1.
Therefore I also perform a similar exercise in which no smoothness is
imposed on the covariances. First, innovations to returns are calculated
from rolling regressions on returns, using the same predicting variables
as in the VAR. (The appendix provides details.) By using rolling
regressions, for the majority of the sample, the information set used to
predict returns includes only data known to the agents at the time; the
same cannot be said of the VAR, whose coefficients are estimated from
the entire sample of data. Second, and to be clear, the conditional
covariance is calculated as
(16) [MATHEMATICAL EXPRESSION NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII]
where [E.sub.t][[r.sub.t,t+1]] is the prediction of log excess
returns from the rolling regression.
Table 3 presents the conditional covariances and implied estimates
of risk aversion. These estimates are broadly comparable to those in
tables 1 and 2: the consumption risk of equity rises by close to an
order of magnitude or more as one considers risk over longer horizons.
However, the conditional covariances do not rise as high as the earlier
estimates, and at longer horizons they fall back significantly, although
again sampling uncertainty grows substantially with the horizon.
Figure 3 summarizes the coefficients of relative risk aversion
implied by each estimation method for horizons from zero to nineteen
quarters (five years). Although measures of risk aversion estimated from
the unconditional covariances, from the VAR, and from the conditional
covariances are all in broad agreement at horizons up to two years, they
diverge thereafter. At longer horizons, the smoothing imposed by a VAR
alters estimated risk aversion by an order of magnitude or more. Tables
1 and 3 show why. Even at a horizon of eleven quarters, the estimated
covariances are only one standard error away from zero. There is simply
not enough information in the data to select among point estimates at
horizons greater than two or three years. The discussion and analysis
therefore focus on medium-term risk from one to three years, where there
is some degree of agreement across methods and lower, although still
quite large, statistical uncertainty.
[FIGURE 3 OMITTED]
To sum up, the results so far have three main implications. First,
the declining pattern of risk aversion with the horizon over which
consumption risk is measured is consistent with the slow adjustment of
consumption to changes in wealth, and thus with the literature on
consumption behavior discussed in earlier sections. This pattern is
inconsistent with the textbook model. The contemporaneous covariance is
misleading, and portfolio recommendations, economic models, or
projections that calibrate the risk of equity based on the
contemporaneous covariance underestimate the risk of equity.
Second, the equity premium measured by the medium-term risk to
consumption is less of a puzzle than one would be led to believe based
on the contemporaneous covariance. The covariance between consumption
and excess returns rises by a factor of about ten for flow consumption
and a much larger amount for total expenditure, although the latter
occurs mostly in extending the horizon for consumption by one quarter
from the contemporaneous covariance.
Third, even the lowest point estimate of risk aversion is too high
to be plausible. The medium-term risk to consumption is insufficient to
explain the mean return on equity over the risk-free rate at reasonable
levels of risk aversion. Although the equity premium is now less of a
puzzle, it remains a puzzle.
A potentially important feature of the stock market is that a large
(but declining) fraction of U.S. households do not hold any equity at
all. Thus a leading explanation for the failure of the textbook model in
aggregate data on consumption is that many households face costs of
entering the stock market and so do not hold equity. If some households
are excluded from the equity market, stock market risk will be
concentrated among those households that participate. As a result, these
households face more risk from equities, and the equity premium in
equilibrium is larger, while the covariance of aggregate consumption and
returns can remain low. (25)
Thus, following Mankiw and Zeldes, the remainder of the paper
addresses whether the medium-term risk of equity for the subpopulation of households that hold equity is sufficient to rationalize the premium
on equity. For these households the risk of equity for wealth and
consumption may be more substantial. However, to evaluate this
hypothesis requires household survey data on consumption and
stockholding.
The Consumer Expenditure Survey
This section describes how the CEX is used to construct a series
measuring the consumption growth of households that hold equity. I then
deal with two issues in estimating the medium-term risk of equity, and
after that I present the main results of the estimation.
Interview data from family files of the CEX are used to construct a
series on consumption growth for households holding equity. The CEX
contains the best household-level data on consumption over time in the
United States. The Bureau of Labor Statistics constructs the CEX data
from a series of interviews based on a stratified random sample of the
U.S. population. Each household is interviewed five times, once every
three months, and new households replace, on a monthly basis, those that
leave the sample. In a household's first interview, the CEX
procedures are explained to the household members, and they are asked to
keep track of their expenditure for future interviews. Each subsequent
interview collects detailed information on the past three months'
consumption expenditure. In each household's second and fifth
interviews, demographic and income data are collected, including
information about income and earnings during the previous twelve months.
This information is updated if it changes during the course of the
survey year. In a household's final interview, a set of questions
about assets is asked, including the current "estimated market
value of all stocks, bonds [private bonds only], mutual funds and other
such securities" owned by the household and the amount by which
these holdings have changed over the previous twelve months.
The appendix provides a more complete description of how the series
is constructed, but three features deserve note here. First, I construct
both flow consumption and total expenditure per effective person, but
these concepts do not exactly match the same concepts in the aggregate
data. Along most dimensions, the CEX measure is a closer match to the
theory. Second, some cleaning of the data is undertaken; primarily,
observations with extremely low levels of consumption are dropped, and
the largest and the smallest growth rates of consumption in each period
are dropped, as are all observations in several periods in which survey
changes were made that result in consumption growth not being correctly
measured. Third, households are categorized as holding equity only if
they are holding a positive amount of the types of securities listed
above before their first interview. Households with missing or miscoded
data are not considered stockholders. This definition of households that
own stock excludes many that hold equity indirectly; the CEX does not
ask for information on stockholding in pension funds, although some
households may include investments in Individual Retirement Accounts,
and some may even include pension funds in their response to the survey
question. (26)
In short, for every pair of consecutive observations on consumption
for a household, I construct the change in log consumption per effective
person, for both flow consumption and total expenditure. These
household-level observations are averaged to create a measure of the
growth in consumption per effective person. Averaging only over those
households that report holding equity before their first observation on
consumption gives the consumption growth of households holding equity.
The final series has monthly observations on consumption growth over
three-month-to-three-month periods from the period October to December
1979 to the period December 1997 to February 1998, with eleven dates
missing because of survey changes, for a total of 205 observations on
consumption growth. (27) Finally, the overlapping nature of the data
makes the correlation of covariances quite complex. All inferences are
made using Newey-West standard errors allowing for correlations up to
lags of 3(S + 1) months.
Estimation
There are two important differences between the calculation of risk
from aggregate consumption data and the calculation of risk for
stockholders in the CEX. First, the CEX consumption series has
significantly more measurement error than the aggregate series. Second,
the CEX consumption series covers a shorter time period and a period
that includes unusually high market returns.
The first practical concern about estimation using the CEX is that
there is significant mismeasurement of consumption in the CEX, even
after averaging over a large number of households. (28) I assume that
the measurement error in consumption is classical; that is, it is
additive when consumption is expressed in logarithms and has a mean of
zero conditional on true consumption and returns at all leads and lags?
Let time be measured in months, let t denote the last month of an
observation, and let [DELTA.sub.3] denote the difference operator across
a three-month period. Observed consumption growth is a monthly series of
three-month averages:
(17) [DELTA.sub.3] ln [C.sub.t] = [DELTA.sub.3] ln [C.sub.t.sup.*]
+ [DELTA.sub.3] [eta.sub.t]
(18) = ln [C.sub.t.sub.*] - ln [C.sub.t-3.sub.*] + [eta.sub t] -
[eta.sub.t-3],
where [C.sup.*] is true consumption, C is the observed measure, and
[eta] is the measurement error. Because the measurement error is
uncorrelated with returns, it does not bias estimation of the risk of
the stock market. The theoretical covariance of observed consumption
growth and returns is
(19) [MATHEMATICAL EXPRESSION NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII]
where S is still measured in quarters. Thus calculation of the
covariance using mismeasured data is unbiased. (30)
There is also practical evidence that bias in this context is
small. First note that, ignoring means, the covariance is the
coefficient in an ordinary least squares regression of returns on
consumption growth times the standard deviation of returns. Given this
interpretation, the estimation is akin to the estimation of a
consumption Euler equation, with actual rather than expected returns on
the right-hand side. The CEX data in grouped form have been used in
several contexts to estimate linear consumption Euler equations, and the
consensus of this literature is that there is little finite-sample bias.
(31)
The second practical concern is that the CEX data cover a
significantly shorter time period than the aggregate data and, in
particular, that this period is one of unusually high returns. The
average excess return during this period is 3 1/2 percentage points
higher at an annual rate than during the entire sample. The resulting
movements of household wealth are also striking. During the period for
which the CEX data are available, the ratio of equity wealth to
disposable income rises from 2.07 to 3.72. (32) From 1952 to 1980 the
ratio is relatively stable: it does not rise above 2.79 and has a
standard deviation of 0.23.
Given these extraordinary returns, it is possible that the
covariance in this period is not representative of the covariance over
the entire sample. That is, inference that assumes that this high level
of average returns is expected (as does inference based on equation 14,
for example) will likely underestimate the risk of equity.
To evaluate the importance of this issue, I redo the analysis of
the medium-term risk of equity in aggregate data for the period covered
by the CEX data: the last quarter of 1979 to the first quarter of 1998.
Tables 4 and 5 present, for flow consumption and total consumption
expenditure, respectively, the unconditional and conditional covariances
and the coefficients of relative risk aversion that these levels imply.
The format of these tables is similar to that of tables 1 to 3, although
the horizon does not extend as far. Since the sample size is
significantly reduced for the CEX period, only shorter horizons are
considered. Statistical uncertainty is already quite high at a horizon
of seven quarters.
The booming stock market of the 1980s and 1990s leads to lower
estimates of the covariance of consumption growth and to higher
estimates of risk aversion in this subsample. The contemporaneous
covariances are negative for all cases except the conditional covariance
of flow consumption, which is half its value for the entire sample.
Turning to the medium-term risk, the covariances rise with the horizon,
as was the case in the entire sample, and although the increase is
large, the estimates of medium-term risk are significantly smaller than
those that use the entire sample. At even longer horizons, the point
estimates of the covariances capturing the medium-term risk in the 1980s
and 1990s are negative and thus inconsistent with the textbook model.
Note that, for reasons of comparability, as discussed above, the
numerator of the estimating equation for risk aversion (equation 6) is
calculated from the entire sample. Thus risk aversion is higher in this
period not directly because of higher average returns during the period
but because of lower observed medium-term risk.
Tables 4 and 5 also report, for each consumption measure, the ratio
of the risk aversion coefficient for the medium-term risk of equity in
the 1980s and 1990s to that in the entire sample (1959-2000, from tables
1 and 3). For future use in adjusting estimates from the CEX data, let
these ratios be denoted by [PHI.sub.S]. Risk aversion coefficients
estimated from the smaller sample are typically two times those
estimated in the entire sample but range between 1.1 and 4.7. (33)
In sum, the period over which household-level data are available on
the consumption of stockholders is also a period in which equity markets
performed unusually well and in which the covariance of aggregate
consumption growth and returns was unusually low. Any comparison of the
covariance of stockholder consumption from the CEX with the model must
take account of this fact. Not doing so risks rejecting the
reasonableness of the model because of the fact that household-level
data are available only in an unusual period.
The Risk of Stocks for Stockholders
Is the medium-term risk of equity for stockholders sufficient to
rationalize its high relative return? Tables 6 and 7 report covariance
estimates using the consumption growth of stockholders and measuring
consumption as flow consumption or total consumption expenditure,
respectively. The first point to note is that the unadjusted
contemporaneous covariances for stockholders are at least five times
larger than those estimated using aggregate consumption data over the
entire sample (first row of tables 1, 2, and 3), and larger still than
those estimated using NIPA data and the shorter sample (first row of
tables 4 and 5), which are negative in three out of four cases. These
raw contemporaneous covariances imply risk aversion coefficients of
between 70 and 90 for flow consumption, and between 27 and 30 for total
expenditure. Although both of these estimates are still implausibly
large, they are much smaller than in the NIPA data on all households.
Second, the unadjusted covariances rise significantly as one
extends the horizon over which consumption risk is measured. The
medium-term consumption risk of equity is three to four times greater
than the contemporaneous risk for flow consumption, and over twice as
large for total expenditure. Thus the main finding for the aggregate
data holds here as well: the medium-term risk of equity is significantly
larger than the contemporaneous risk. Although an increase in risk of
two to four times is large, it is interesting to note that the increase
implied by these point estimates is not as large as the increase with
horizon observed in the aggregate estimates.
Vissing-Jorgensen and Brav, Constantinides, and Geczy also document
that the contemporaneous consumption risk of equity for stockholders is
greater than that for all CEX households. (34) But more important, the
consumption risk of stockholders is also larger at horizons of one to
two years. The raw estimates of medium-term risk imply levels of risk
aversion as low as the teens. Although these estimates are close to
reasonable levels of risk aversion and thus close to rationalizing the
equity premium (especially if one measures distance in terms of
statistical uncertainty), these covariances are not adjusted for the
unusual returns of the 1980s and 1990s. (35)
To account for the unusual characteristics of the period during
which household-level data are available, I adjust the medium-term risk
estimated in the CEX by the amount that the medium-term risk of equity
rises in aggregate data when one moves from the subsample covered by the
CEX to the full sample available. That is, I estimate the risk of
returns for consumption and the risk aversion of the typical stockholder
as
(20) [cov.sub.S,SH] = [PHI.sub.S] [cov.sub.S,SH,CEX]
(21) [gamma.sub.S,SH] = E[r.sub.t,t+1] + 1/2
var(r.sub.t.t+1]/[cov.sub.S,SH]
where [COV.sub.S,SH,CEX] is the covariance of consumption growth
over horizon S estimated for stockholders over the short sample covered
by the CEX data, and [PHI.sub.s] is the sample ratio of the medium-term
risk estimated using the full sample of aggregate data available to the
corresponding estimate using only the period covered by the CEX, as
described above and presented in tables 4 and 5.
In tables 6 and 7 the two columns to the right of each raw
covariance present these adjusted covariances and the implied levels of
risk aversion. The medium-term risk to consumption estimated from the
consumption of stockholders and adjusted for the period covered by the
CEX is quite reasonable. When marginal utility is measured as flow
consumption, which omits many luxuries, the covariances show sufficient
risk to consumption that the risk aversion coefficient of the
representative stockholder need only be in the neighborhood of 5 to 10.
When marginal utility is measured by the medium-term movement in total
expenditure, the risk aversion of the representative stockholder need
only be in the range of 3 to 8 to rationalize the equity premium.
How important is looking at the medium-term response rather than
the contemporaneous response? This question is harder to answer, since
the aggregate data in the period covered by the CEX imply a negative
contemporaneous covariance. However, if one adjusts the contemporaneous
covariance by the same factor used at a horizon of one quarter, then the
implied risk to consumption rises by 3.6 times and 5.9 times for
unconditional and conditional flow consumption, respectively, as one
moves from contemporaneous risk to medium-term risk at a horizon of
seven quarters. Although not quite as large as the order-of-magnitude
increase in the aggregate data, this increase is still large.
In sum, the medium-term risk of equity for stockholders in the CEX
is larger than the medium-term risk for the consumption of all
households in the NIPA. Adjusted for the low covariance found in this
period in the aggregate data, the medium-term consumption risk of equity
for stockholders is consistent with the high average rate of return to
stocks and reasonable levels of risk aversion for stockholders.
According to tables 6 and 7, the combination of limited participation
and slow adjustment leaves almost no equity premium puzzle. Before
concluding, I explore this result further in the next section.
The Risk of Stocks for Rich Households, Older Households, and All
CEX Households
This section addresses two questions. First, the CEX data on
stockholders differ from aggregate consumption data in a number of ways.
To what extent does each of these differences drive the main result?
Second, the medium-term risk of stockholders presumably exceeds the risk
for all households because the wealth of stockholders is more highly
correlated with returns than that of the typical household. Is the
consumption risk of those with little labor income (older households) or
with more asset wealth (rich households) larger still? Ultimately,
statistical uncertainty hampers the ability of the data to answer these
questions. The results presented here are therefore informative but not
conclusive.
The CEX consumption series on stockholders differs from the NIPA
consumption data in several respects. The CEX series is aggregated in a
manner consistent with the theory, whereas the NIPA consumption series
is not. NIPA consumption growth is the first difference of the logarithm
of the average level of consumption across the population. This not only
confounds movements in the distribution of consumption with movements in
the typical household's marginal utility, but also includes
households that die, immigrate, emigrate, or are "born" into
the sample between period t and period t + 1. In the CEX the more
theoretically appropriate approach is used of first converting the
household data to logarithms, then differencing for households present
in both t and t + 1, then averaging? Correct aggregation can make a
significant difference in estimating the response of expected
consumption growth to time variation in risk-free real interest rates,
(37) suggesting that correct aggregation may matter for the present set
of results.
Other differences also exist. Consumption in the NIPA includes the
spending of nonprofit organizations, whose objectives probably are not
captured by the same model we apply to households. As noted, the
definitions of consumption are not identical, and the CEX data tend to
measure durable purchases more accurately than small nondurable
purchases for reasons of recall. Further, the CEX sample covers a
different population of households. As discussed in more detail in the
appendix, rural households, military households, and students living in
dormitories are excluded. The CEX is also a nonrandom sample.
To evaluate the importance of these differences between the CEX and
the NIPA data, I construct a series from the CEX that mimics the NIPA
series. I build average consumption per person by period using the CEX
data and sample weights and then calculate the medium-term risk of
equity using this measure of consumption instead of the NIPA data.
Tables 8 and 9, which are similar in format to tables 6 and 7, show that
the consumption risk of equity as measured in the CEX data aggregated to
mimic the NIPA is lower than that measured in correctly aggregated data
on stockholders. However, it is also the case that the estimated
consumption risk of equity is significantly larger in this CEX
consumption series covering all households than it is in the NIPA
consumption data in the comparable period (tables 4 and 5). Raw
covariances estimated in the NIPA data range up to roughly 0.0012,
whereas in this aggregation of the CEX the estimated covariances are as
large as 0.0029. Like the NIPA data, the CEX data show a significantly
larger risk of consumption at horizons of one or two quarters, but
unlike the NIPA data, as the horizon is increased further, the estimated
risk declines. At horizons beyond four quarters, the CEX aggregate has a
lower estimated risk of consumption.
On balance, the CEX pseudo-NIPA data suggest that the medium-term
risk rises over a couple of quarters only, and that risk aversion
coefficients corresponding to these higher estimated risk levels are
around 30 to 50 when the data are not adjusted for the sample, and 15 to
30 when adjusted for the unusual returns of the 1980s and 1990s. These
estimates of medium-term risk aversion are about half those in the NIPA
data and about twice those for correctly aggregated data on
stockholders. These are then the differences due to the definitions and
measurement of consumption and the sample differences. Of course, this
number has a fair amount of statistical uncertainty in addition to being
a rather coarse characterization of many numbers.
How much of this remaining difference is due to restricting the
sample to stockholders, and how much due to correct aggregation? Figure
4 shows the ratio of the medium-term risk of equity for stockholders to
the medium-term risk of equity for all households in the CEX, aggregated
in the same manner as for stockholders. The contemporaneous risk for
stockholders is typically positive, whereas for all households,
correctly aggregated, it is typically negative. For horizons of one,
two, and three quarters, the covariance of stockholder consumption
growth with returns is not much larger than that for all households.
However, for four quarters and beyond, and with the caveat that
statistical uncertainty is high, this ratio is more clearly larger. The
medium-term risk to the consumption of stockholders is on average a
third larger than that for all households in the CEX. Thus the
restriction to stockholders (for the already restricted sample of the
CEX) increases the medium-term risk to consumption by about a third,
whereas correct aggregation increases the medium-term risk by roughly
two-thirds. The restriction to stockholders makes a greater difference
for the contemporaneous risk of equity than it does for the medium-term
risk.
[FIGURE 4 OMITTED]
A second set of questions is whether different subpopulations might
have an even higher medium-term risk of equity or give further clues as
to the correct theoretical model to explain limited participation in the
stock market. One possible reason for limited participation is that some
households have little net worth beyond future labor income. If such
households face restrictions on borrowing to invest in the stock market,
then small costs of entering the market may keep these households from
investing in stocks, even though the marginal investment in stock has
high returns and little consumption risk. Similarly, some households
might hold stocks but be prevented from increasing those holdings
because they find themselves up against the constraint on borrowing. To
shed light on this explanation, I examine two different populations:
older households, for whom future labor income is relatively small, and
richer stockholding households, who, if constrained, are at least
holding more substantial equity wealth.
Table 10 reports the contemporaneous and the medium-term risk for
households in which the average age of the head of the households is
sixty-five or greater (top panel) and households holding more than
$25,000 (in 1982-84 dollars) in securities (bottom panel). Point
estimates suggest that older households do not on average bear a higher
consumption risk of equity than does the typical household. Although
quite uncertain, these levels of medium-term risk are slightly smaller
than those of the typical CEX household. This is consistent with an
alternative view of the world in which elderly households hold large
amounts of Social Security wealth, which is relatively safe and whose
returns are uncorrelated with the market. Although not shown in the
table, there is also no evidence that older households that hold stock
bear any different degree of consumption risk than does the typical
stockholding household. In sum, there is no evidence that households in
which the head is sixty-five or older bear more consumption risk of
equity than do similar households of all ages.
The bottom panel of table 10 finds no evidence that wealthy
households bear more medium-term consumption risk than the typical
household holding stock. Thirty-six percent of stockholding households
are classified as rich, so that this series has more measurement error
than the series for all stockholders. The point estimates vary more with
changes in the horizon but show levels of medium-term risk very similar
to those found for all stockholders in tables 6 and 7. In sum, there is
little evidence of differences among the population of stockholders, but
also little evidence against such differences. (38)
Discussion
This paper judges the reasonableness of equity's risk and
return in a way that is valid under a variety of models of consumer
behavior. The average risk and return of equity relative to a risk-free
investment are close to being consistent with optimal investment
behavior for those households that hold equity, given slow adjustment of
consumption, reasonable levels of risk aversion, and time-separable
expected utility. This main finding raises two questions.
First, what keeps most households out of the stock market? One
explanation is that there are significant fixed costs associated with
learning how to invest, as well as flow costs that this paper ignores,
such as taxes, commissions, mutual fund management fees, and the time
costs of monitoring one's portfolio. However, even given the higher
risk of equity found using the medium-term measure, these costs would
seem to be small relative to the high returns on equity. Additional
market incompleteness, however, may make small costs sufficient. In
particular, some households may not invest in equity because they have
little liquid wealth and would pay high interest rates if they were to
borrow against future income to invest in equity. Complementing this
explanation, markets provide incomplete insurance against changes in
labor income, and idiosyncratic risk can significantly increase the
effective risk of equity at the household level. (39) It would also be
useful to understand the relationship between limited participation and
the distribution of consumption, and in particular whether the
distribution of consumption is becoming bipolar, with stockholders
increasingly more wealthy than nonstockholders.
Second, how do we incorporate the models of the slow adjustment of
consumption from the literature on consumption smoothing into asset
pricing models more generally? This paper provides several clues as to
what the correct structural model of asset pricing might look like. Many
recent models focus on significantly different models of consumer
behavior or utility functions. This paper shows that limited
participation and power utility rationalize the average differences
between stock returns and the risk-free rate in the medium term, but
that consumption smoothing does not capture the high-frequency
relationship. These results imply that one should focus on modifications
of behavior or utility functions that are consistent with power utility
and intertemporal optimization in the medium term. It would be useful to
further test this view, for example by studying whether the medium-term
risk to the consumption of stockholders also explains returns across
groups of stocks or between long- and short-term bonds. (40)
Turning to the implications of this paper, since the average return
on the stock market is consistent with the risk of the stock market for
households holding stock, stocks appear to be a good deal for the
typical nonstockholder in that the average return on equity outweighs
the risks to consumption for a marginal investment. For the typical
household not in the stock market, access to equity offers potentially
large gains. Thus significant welfare gains could be realized if the
government were able to provide access to diversified equity funds in a
manner that avoids the costs or concerns that now keep these households
out of the market (and does not entail large costs to the government),
such as attempted in some proposals to diversify household Social
Security wealth. (41) Although the costs and benefits of such a policy
depend on far more than the issue considered here, this paper does
clarify the current risk of equity that should be used in calculating
the potential welfare gains of such policies; it also makes clear that
the relative risk and return of equity are reasonable for those
households already participating in the stock market.
The findings of this paper support the view that the stock market
boom of the 1980s and the 1990s was driven in part by increased stock
market participation in response to declining costs of stock ownership.
(42) The cost of investing in the stock market has declined
significantly thanks to legal changes and technological improvements in
communications and information processing, and the participation rate
has risen dramatically. The increase in stock ownership shares the risk
of dividends across more households, which, in the steady state,
decreases the correlation between consumption and equity returns for
those households holding equity. This, in turn, reduces the premium
required on equity and so increases its price, leading to a stock market
boom. Whether the quantitative effect of this change in participation is
large or small, accounting for limited participation in the stock market
is important for understanding the true price of equity.
APPENDIX
Data Sources and Methods
Aggregate Data
Data on personal consumption expenditure are extracted from the
U.S. Central data available through Data Resources International (DRI)
and from data available on the World Wide Web site of the Bureau of
Economic Analysis. The data are spliced to form consistent series from
the first quarter of 1959 to the first quarter of 2001. All real data
are chain weighted. (43) Real flow consumption is constructed using
series "by major type of product," whereas real consumption
expenditure is constructed using series "by major type of
expenditure." Chain-weighted real data on consumption cannot be
added and subtracted to generate real measures of different combinations
of consumption goods. Biases arise from differences in rates of price
change and changing shares of consumption. In practice, however, the
exact series can be closely approximated by combining series as one
would when constructing a chain-weighted series from the detailed data.
Thus I construct consumption series and price indexes as follows.
Let
[C.sup.A.sub.t] be total real consumption
[C.sup.S.sub.t] be total real consumption of services
[C.sup.ND.sub.t] be total real consumption of nondurable goods
[C.sup.F.sub.t] be real consumption of footwear (a subcategory of
nondurable goods)
[C.sup.H.sub.t] be total real consumption of housing services
[C.sup.M.sub.t] be total real consumption of medical care services
[C.sup.E.sub.t] be total real consumption of education services
[C.sup.B.sub.t] be total real consumption of personal business
services
[C.sup.M.sub.t] be total real consumption of medical care (category
by type of expenditure)
[C.sup.E.sub.t] be total real consumption of education (category by
type of expenditure)
[C.sup.B.sub.t] be total real consumption of personal business
expenses (category by type of expenditure).
Let [X.sup.i.sub.t] be the nominal consumption of category i in
period t, and let [P.sup.i.sub.t] be the price deflator for series i
derived by dividing the nominal quantity by the chain-weighted real
quantity. Thus by definition, for all i,
(A1) [C.sup.i.sub.t] = [X.sup.i.sub.t]/[P.sup.i.sub.t].
Let [C.sup.T.sub.t] be our series real total consumption
expenditure (total consumption less medical care, education, and
personal business services) and [C.sub.t] be our series real flow
consumption (nondurable and services consumption less footwear, housing,
medical care, education, and personal business services). Since these
data are chain weighted,
(A2) [C.sub.t] [not equal to] [C.sup.ND.sub.t] + [C.sup.S.sub.t] -
[C.sup.F.sub.t] - [C.sup.H.sub.t] - [C.sup.M.sub.t] - [C.sup.E.sub.t] -
[C.sup.B.sub.t]
[C.sup.T.sub.t] [not equal to] [C.sup.All.sub.t] - [C.sup.M.sub.t]
- [C.sup.E.sub.t] - [C.sup.B.sub.t].
For t = 1996, that is, any date in 1996, we construct [C.sub.t] and
[C.sup.T.sub.t] by addition. For t > 1996, I generate the series for
real flow consumption by iterating forward through time on
(A3) [MATHEMATICAL EXPRESSION NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII]
and for t < 1996, I generate this series by iterating backward
through time on
(A4) [MATHEMATICAL EXPRESSION NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII]
The construction of real consumption expenditure follows the same
logic. For t > 1996, I generate the series for real consumption
expenditure by iterating forward through time on
(A5) [MATHEMATICAL EXPRESSION NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII]
and for t < 1996, I generate this series by iterating backward
through time on
(A6) [MATHEMATICAL EXPRESSION NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII]
I divide the resulting series by the U.S. population to arrive at
consumption per capita. Population data are three-month averages of
monthly data from the Census data from DRI. The series drops by very
close to 2 million in the first month of 1983 and rises by very close to
2 million after the end of 1985. I adjust the series upward by 2 million
over the period 1983:1 to 1985:4 to avoid the otherwise implied large
swings in consumption per capita. The resulting population growth over
the break periods is similar to the growth rates in nearby months.
Returns on stocks and the risk-free rate are extracted from the
Center for Research on Securities Prices (CRSP) data. The stock market
index used is the quarterly CRSP index for the New York Stock Exchange
and the American Stock Exchange. The risk-free rate is constructed using
three-month averages of the monthly Fama risk-free rate (available in
the CRSP data). The Fama risk-free rate is converted from continuous
time to a quarterly rate. The return subscripted by t + 1 represents the
return during period t + 1 so that
(A7) [r.sub.t,t+1] = ln (1 + [P.sub.t+1] + [d.sub.t+1]/[P.sub.t] -
[i.sup.f.sub.t,t+1])
where [P.sub.t] is the price of the basket of equities at the end
of period t, [d.sub.t] are dividends paid during period t, and
[i.sup.f.sub.t,t+1] is the gross nominal risk-free rate. The
dividend-price ratio corresponding to period t is [d.sub.t]/[P.sub.t-1].
Conditional Estimation and the Vector Autoregression
The VAR confidence intervals are constructed by Monte Carlo
integration under the assumption that the innovations are Gaussian. The
procedure for this paper follows that described in RATS version 5,
section 13.4. The VAR includes a complete set of quarter dummies in
addition to the predetermined variables. The impulse responses for the
entire system are given in figures A1 and A2.
[FIGURES A1-A2 OMITTED]
To construct predicted returns, a regression consisting of the
first row of the VAR system is run for the period from 1959 to 1974, and
the fitted values from this regression are expected returns. From 1975
on, a rolling regression is used in which only information up to t - 1
is used to predict returns at t. For simplicity and consistency, this is
done for a sample of data with timing structured as in the CEX so that
the regression uses three-month lags and predicts three-month returns
but does this at a monthly frequency. Thus the same predicted returns
series is used for the aggregate and the CEX analyses. Month dummies are
included rather than quarter dummies. The aggregate results are almost
identical if only quarterly data are used.
The Consumer Expenditure Survey
Survey data are available only from 1980, so that the earliest
consumption observation covers October to December 1979. In 1998 and
beyond, the survey significantly altered the categories into which
consumption expenditures are grouped, in order to match the extensive
restructuring of the consumer price index (CPI) at that time. The 1997
files include data on household expenditure for all three-month
interview periods starting in 1997, so that the data used cover a period
up to and including February 1998. I use both the raw data files and SAS files available from Lorna Greening at
ftp://elsa.berkeley.edu/pub/ices/.
Flow consumption is defined as purchases of food, alcoholic
beverages, apparel and apparel services, gasoline and motor oil used in
transportation, public transportation, entertainment, personal care, and
reading. As in the aggregate data, this definition omits expenditure on
health care, housing, education, and financial services. Unlike in the
aggregate data, footware is included. I omit tobacco, because it is
addictive; household operations, because it includes repairs of
furniture, appliances, and computers, as well as day care expenses,
including tuition; and utilities, because, apart from telephone service,
these are to a large extent determined by one's housing choice.
Total expenditure omits spending on health care, charitable
contributions, and education. Both series further differ from NIPA data
in excluding spending by nonprofit organizations.
Flow consumption is converted to real terms using the CPI for each
category of consumption for the census region in which the household
resides. The CPI categories match the CEX categories and provide a
reasonable approximation to the optimal chain-weighted index, although
each subcategory of the CPI is likely to overstate inflation. Total
expenditure is deflated by the CPI for all items less medical care.
Similar results obtain if one instead uses the NIPA chain-weighted
deflator for total consumption. Consumption per effective householder is
calculated by dividing by the number of heads (one or two) plus 0.4
times the number of children.
Because of some implausibly low reports of consumption, I drop the
bottom 1 percent of households in the distribution of real flow
consumption per effective householder at each date. Rural households are
dropped, as are households living in student housing and observations in
which family size changes are greater than 3. Finally, the top and
bottom 5 percent of the distribution of growth rates of flow consumption
are dropped in each period. This trimming occurs at log growth rates of
between 50 and 60 percent. Although trimming should not alter inferences
if markets are complete among stockholders, trimming could understate the risk of equity, but in fact it does not. Experimenting with no
trimming and with trimming 1 percent instead of 5 percent tails gave
similar estimates for stockholders, although with slightly greater
standard errors and smaller differences between stockholders and all CEX
households correctly aggregated.
Consumption series are constructed as average consumption growth
for all households and for only those households that report positive
holdings of stocks, private bonds, or mutual funds immediately before
the first observation on consumption. The data are seasonally adjusted by regressing them on dummies for each month, and the residuals are used
in the analysis. Households that have pension wealth but do not directly
hold equity are likely to report that they hold no stocks. Thus the
series on the consumption of stockholders consists primarily of
households that hold stock directly. Households with top-coded amounts
in the final interview are deemed stockholders. Errors in processing the
survey assigned balances of $1 to a significant number of households
that actually have balances well in excess of this amount. To be
conservative in labeling households as stockholders, these balances are
treated as if the household indeed had wealth in these types of assets
of $1. There are an average of 115 valid consumption growth rates per
period for stockholders, and 908 average consumption growth rates per
period for all households (both after trimming the tails of the
distribution).
Because of survey changes, there are eleven missing observations on
consumption growth during the sample, so that ultimately valid data on
consumption growth are available for 205 partly overlapping three-month
periods. Because of decennial survey changes, one cannot construct
consumption growth for any households across the last three months of
1985 to the first three months of 1986, and similarly for 1995 to 1996.
Further, because of changes in the survey methodology, the three
observations on consumption growth ending in December 1987 and January
and February 1988 exhibit large changes in the mean and variance of
consumption growth and are dropped. Similar survey changes lead to
dropping the same three months across 1995 to 1996 and across 1981 to
1982. Thus, from a possible 216 observations on consumption growth, 205
valid observations are available. Because the missing data occur in the
middle of the sample, it could significantly reduce the power of our
tests. To mitigate this effect, consumption growth rates are imputed to
these dates that have the same covariance structure with lagged returns
as the remainder of the data, and the standard errors are adjusted to
account for the fact that some data are imputed.
Comments and Discussion
N. Gregory Mankiw: About twenty years ago, the consumption-based
capital asset pricing model took center stage in discussions of asset
pricing and economic fluctuations. Since then many economists have
puzzled about the economy's most important risk premium, the spread
between the equity return and the risk-free return. According to the
model, the right measure of risk is consumption risk, but the measured
consumption risk associated with the stock market seems too small to
explain an equity premium of 6 percentage points, unless consumers are
extraordinarily risk averse.
Fortunately, we have made progress toward explaining the equity
premium, and this paper by Jonathan Parker makes a significant
contribution to that effort. The resolution to the puzzle rests, at
least in part, on two facts that several studies have now documented.
The first fact is that the risk of equities measure using
consumption by stockholders alone is greater than the risk measured
using aggregate consumption. Stephen Zeldes and I first documented this
using data on food consumption from the Michigan Panel Study of Income
Dynamics. (1) This finding has been confirmed in other, arguably better
data sets by Annette Vissing-Jorgensen and by Parker in this paper. (2)
Of course, this fact does not explain why so many people do not
hold stock, and this can be viewed as a puzzle in its own right. Part of
the answer is that many people live hand to mouth and own hardly any
assets at all. But that is not the whole story. Zeldes and I documented
that many people with sizable liquid assets hold no stock. The most
plausible answer for these people is information costs: many people just
do not understand stocks and bonds and do not feel comfortable buying
them. Imagine how the typical economist would feel if advised to invest
his or her retirement funds in rare stamps or seventeenth-century
artwork. Most of us probably know nothing about these markets, but we
know to stay away from things we do not understand.
The second fact that helps explain the equity premium is that
consumption risk is higher when measured using medium-term changes in
consumption than when using only the contemporaneous co-movement of
consumption with stock market returns. This fact is documented both here
and in a parallel paper by Xavier Gabaix and David Laibson. (3) Parker
estimates (in the first column of his table 1) that lengthening the time
horizon raises the measured consumption risk of equities by a factor of
ten.
With the benefit of hindsight, it seems that both of these facts
should have been obvious. Regarding the fact of limited stock market
participation, it is hardly a shock that many people do not hold
equities and that those who do hold them face more equity risk than
those who do not. Regarding the time horizon, the stock market is widely
viewed as a leading indicator of economic activity, two-thirds of which
is consumer spending. Thus, it is no surprise that increasing the time
horizon raises the measured covariance.
The literature on consumption-based asset pricing neglected this
observation until recently because, according to standard theory as set
forth in Robert Hall's seminal 1978 paper, consumption should
follow a random walk. (4) In particular, the stock market should not be
correlated with future consumption changes, so the contemporaneous risk
and the medium-term risk (as measured in Parker's table 1) should
be the same. Yet this theoretical prediction has never been fully
confirmed by the data. In that same 1978 paper, Hall tested the theory
and found that the random-walk hypothesis worked well, with a single
exception: the stock market predicted future consumption growth. He
hypothesized that some part of consumption takes time to respond to
changes in wealth. This conjecture foreshadowed by two decades this
paper by Parker and the parallel one by Gabaix and Laibson.
Although Hall initially proposed this delayed-adjustment
hypothesis, he never took it very seriously, and for good reason. If you
add adjustment costs to the standard permanent income model, you are
likely to get strong positive autocorrelation in consumption growth,
because people will slowly respond to news about permanent income. By
contrast, as Hall showed, the actual univariate process for consumption
is close to a random walk, which means that consumption growth is close
to white noise. Gabaix and Laibson salvage the model from this critique
by assuming that, although there is lagged adjustment to stock market
news, consumers respond immediately to all other news, such as news
about labor income. Thus delayed adjustment is important for explaining
the equity premium, but all other fluctuations influence consumption as
in the Hall random-walk model. This set of assumptions makes the model
work, but it seems like a deus ex machina, descending out of the sky to
save us when we need it and assuming itself back to heaven when it would
prove inconvenient. Parker avoids such criticism by skirting the
question of why the short-run and the medium-run dynamics are so
different. This is an important topic for future work.
One place where I part company with Parker is over the magnitude of
this time horizon effect. I think the paper overstates the case because
it emphasizes the difference between medium-term risk and
contemporaneous risk measured using quarterly data. Much, although not
all, of the previous literature, including my paper with Zeldes, has
used annual data. Parker's figures 1 and 2 show that most of the
gain in,this exercise comes in the first few quarters. Had he started
with data at an annual frequency, he would have seen a much smaller
improvement from going beyond the contemporaneous consumption risk.
Despite this complaint, I am convinced by the more fundamental
point: Consumption risk measured over the medium term exceeds that
measured contemporaneously. I do not believe that this observation
changes the estimates by a factor of ten, but it could well be a factor
of two or three.
In addition to limited participation and time horizon, Parker
suggests a third piece to the equity premium puzzle: aggregation. He
claims that moving from National Income and Product Accounts data to a
correctly aggregated consumption series from the Consumer Expenditure
Survey increases measured consumption risk substantially. This
inconsistency between the NIPA and the CEX data is interesting and
potentially important, but the explanation for it is left as a bit of a
puzzle in its own right. If the NIPA data are artificially smoother than
they should be, this fact would have major ramifications for the
literature on consumption and asset pricing. But it is also possible
that the CEX data are flawed in some way. The paper shows that the two
data sets lead to different results, but it does not make a compelling
case for preferring one data set over the other. The CEX data may simply
be noisy: the large standard errors in Parker's table 6 certainly
suggest this possibility.
Besides the explanations for the equity premium that this paper
explores, another deserves to be on the table: sheer luck. Parker
emphasizes that it would be a mistake to judge the equity premium using
data from the 1980s and 1990s alone, because those decades saw
extraordinarily high returns, a fact that someone at the beginning of
the period could not have foreseen. I agree with that logic. But the
same argument could be made for the entire twentieth century. From the
standpoint of humankind's longer history, the economic progress of
the past hundred years has been exceptional. Naturally, those who held
an equity stake in this progress were well rewarded. Yet this outcome
was probably not what most people living at the beginning of the
twentieth century expected. In other words, the ex ante equity premium
may have been much smaller than the ex post equity premium of 6 percent.
One person who did envisage this remarkable growth was John Maynard
Keynes. In a famous essay, "Economic Possibilities for Our
Grandchildren," (5) Keynes suggested that humankind was embarking
on an economic miracle of a sort that previous generations could not
have imagined. It is worth taking a moment to reflect on Keynes's
prognostications and their implications for the equity premium. Keynes
predicted that, a century after he was writing, incomes would be four to
eight times higher than they were in 1930. This translates into growth
in real income per capita between 1.4 and 2.1 percent a year, which has
turned out to be remarkably accurate. Keynes then went on to suggest
that if this growth occurred, "the economic problem may be
solved." In other words, humankind would become satiated. The
marginal utility of consumption would hit zero.
If Keynes's view on the latter point were right, buying
equities at the beginning of the twentieth century would not have been a
good investment. If the economy experienced the growth that Keynes
forecast, as it has, equities would pay off, as they have. But so what?
If we are all going to be satiated, the higher return of stocks is of no
value, and therefore there is no point in taking the risk. If the
marginal utility of consumption is heading rapidly toward zero, people
will exhibit very high risk aversion and will require a very large extra
return to take on the risks of holding equities.
With the benefit of hindsight, we can see that Keynes was right
about the growth, but wrong about the satiation. Although the twentieth
century did generate a high return on equities, it also generated a
surprising increase in the number of ways for investors to spend their
marginal wealth. Perhaps this is why today we look back and view the
equity premium as such a puzzle.
Jonathan Parker has moved us closer to resolving the puzzle. I am
convinced that he is getting at a large part of the truth. Limited
participation in the stock market and a longer time horizon can surely
help explain the large observed equity premium. And the discrepancy between the NIPA and the CEX data is an issue that deserves a closer
look. But part of the explanation for the equity premium may also lie in
the fact that few people expected the rapid growth and high returns that
we have experienced over the past hundred years, and some of those who
did thought we would end up sated as a result. In other words, what we
take for granted at the beginning of the twenty-first century was not at
all obvious a century ago.
(1.) Mankiw and Zeldes (1991).
(2.) Vissing-Jorgensen (1998).
(3.) Gabaix and Laibson (forthcoming).
(4.) Hall (1978).
(5.) Keynes (1931).
Paul Willen: In this paper Jonathan Parker calculates the risk
aversion of consumers who invest in the stock market. He exploits the
first-order conditions of the individual utility maximization problem,
which relate expected asset returns and the covariance of marginal
utility of consumption with asset returns. Parker innovates on the
existing literature by measuring that covariance as the covariance of
consumption with lagged asset returns, rather than with contemporaneous
asset returns as previous researchers have done. He finds that consumers
who invest nonzero amounts in the stock market have risk aversion
coefficients in the range that most researchers would consider
reasonable. Thus one might be tempted to argue that the equity premium
puzzle has been solved.
But has it been? Strictly speaking, no. Although Parker shows that
the equity premium is consistent with reasonable values of risk aversion
for those holding stocks, the puzzle remains why so many consumers hold
no stocks. One natural explanation of Parker's finding is that some
consumers do not participate because they are highly risk averse. If we
average together the participants, with their reasonable risk aversion
coefficients, and the nonparticipants, with their extremely high
coefficients, we get a very high average level of risk aversion (and a
puzzlingly large amount of dispersion in risk aversion). Thus the equity
premium puzzle is alive and well.
Alternatively, suppose we assume that there is some reason other
than high risk aversion why people fail to participate in equity
markets. Then we can conjecture that these nonparticipants' risk
aversion is comparable to that of participants and claim a solution to
the equity premium puzzle. Thus Parker's analysis solves one
puzzle, the equity premium, by invoking another, the participation
puzzle: if nonparticipants have reasonable risk aversion coefficients,
why don't they own equity?
Recall two basic stylized facts about equity ownership: (1)
--Most people own little or no equity, even when equity ownership
is defined very broadly to include equity held in defined-contribution
pension plans and similar vehicles.
--Even many people with significant liquid financial assets own no
equity, again even when equity ownership is broadly defined.
Why do these facts puzzle economists? Consider the individual
investment decision: all potential investors face roughly the same
opportunity to invest in risky assets--a better-than-fair bet. Theory
tells us that no matter how risk averse you are, you should invest a
strictly positive amount in such a bet. In the real world, indeed,
equity is not just a better-than-fair bet, but a much, much better than
fair bet.
But in the real world certain circumstances still might lead to
nonparticipation. Three of these are trading costs, borrowing
constraints, and labor income risk. In reviewing these, one should keep
in mind that a plausible explanation must generate the nonparticipation
of a large fraction of the population and predict positive equity
holdings for the consumers that Parker focuses on. In other words, if
something reduces demand for equity for everyone, it might explain the
equity premium but will not explain the participation puzzle.
Trading costs. If investors can borrow unlimited amounts at the
risk-free interest rate, standard models predict that they will take
enormous positions in equity, by borrowing against future labor income.
For example, Steven Davis and I show that a plumber aged thirty will
invest more than $700,000 in risky assets. (2) Such investments allow
for dramatically higher lifetime consumption. And as a result, no
reasonable trading cost can dissuade investors from participating in
risky asset markets.
Borrowing constraints. Under borrowing constraints, consumers
cannot take leveraged positions. But reasonably calibrated examples show
that they will still invest all (or almost all) their liquid wealth in
risky assets. Life-cycle models with borrowing constraints predict low
levels of liquid wealth until age forty. (3) Thus, even if a younger
consumer invests all his or her wealth in the stock market, the
consumption and utility benefits of equity ownership are small.
Relatively small trading costs could then explain nonparticipation among
these younger consumers. So borrowing constraints, coupled with
reasonable trading costs, could in principle explain the first stylized fact cited above, but they cannot explain the second: that of
nonparticipation among consumers with considerable liquid wealth.
Labor income risk. Can the presence of risk to labor income reduce
the benefits of stock ownership? Yes, in principle. First, if labor
income is positively correlated with stock returns, then labor income
acts as an implicit holding of equity and reduces the benefits of
additional equity ownership. (4) However, empirical evidence shows that
the correlation of equity and labor income is highest for men with the
most education and for the self-employed, (5) two groups that are highly
likely to own stock; the correlation is negative for least educated men,
the group least likely to own stock. Second, even if labor income risk
is uncorrelated with equity, it can depress demand for equity by making
consumers more averse to all risks. Simulation evidence suggests that
labor income risk uncorrelated with equity does not have a significant
effect on portfolio choice. (6) Gregory Mankiw argues that if the
variance of labor income shocks is negatively correlated with return
shocks, demand for equity will fall. (7) Simulation evidence on the
Mankiw effect is mixed. (8) Empirical evidence suggests that the effects
of uncorrelated labor income risk are present but small. (9)
Other researchers have argued that habit formation and other
modifications to preferences can explain why consumers are much more
averse to holding equity than standard measures suggest they should be.
Although such explanations could, in principle, explain the equity
premium puzzle, they cannot explain the cross section of portfolio
holding. It is not clear, for example, why habit formation would affect
one part of the population and not another.
Widespread nonparticipation is, in many ways, an even more puzzling
phenomenon for equilibrium theory than it is for optimization theory.
General-equilibrium models with incomplete markets predict that
marketable risks will be shared across individuals. (10) Equity risk is
marketable, yet we see that only a small fraction of the population owns
equity. If frictions such as borrowing constraints account for the poor
distribution of equity across the population, then the puzzle is why
society has not created institutions to share equity risk more broadly.
In conclusion, the failure of large sections of the population to
hold stock is a puzzle for economic theory. Although many things could
explain this nonparticipation, researchers have yet to find a reasonable
model that matches the observed distribution of participation. But if
Parker has not solved the participation puzzle, he has at least shown
that a solution to the participation puzzle will take us a long way
toward solving the equity premium puzzle.
(1.) See Poterba and Samwick (1995) for details.
(2.) Davis and Willen (2000a).
(3.) Coco, Gomes, and Maenhout (2001); Constantinides, Donaldson,
and Mehra (forthcoming).
(4.) See Davis and Willen (2000b) for an explanation.
(5.) For evidence on the first group see Davis and Willen (2000a);
for evidence on the self-employed see Heaton and Lucas (2000). See also
Bertaut and Haliassos (1995).
(6.) Heaton and Lucas (1997); Coco, Gomes, and Maenhout (2001).
(7.) Mankiw (1986).
(8.) Heaton and Lucas (1996, 1997) find small effects;
Storesletten, Telmer, and Yaron (2001) find larger effects.
(9.) Vissing-Jorgensen (2000).
(10.) See Willen (2001), for example.
General discussion: Robert Gordon commented on the fact that the
CES data that Parker uses are more volatile than the NIPA consumption
data. He noted that for many reasons--sample survey error, imperfect recall of purchases, and lumping together of large purchases that are
strung out over time--the CES survey data might exhibit a lot of
spurious volatility. This could give the impression of greater
variability in the marginal utility of consumption, and hence of greater
risk, than actually exists. Gregory Mankiw noted, however, that spurious
volatility per se is not the problem, but rather spurious volatility
that is correlated with stock market returns, so that it is not clear
that these errors bias Parker's results.
William Nordhaus observed that the paper assumes agents know the
parameters of the distribution of stock market returns estimated from
the entire sample period. He wondered whether estimates of risk aversion
would be noticeably different if they were based only on past
observations at each point in time. Elaborating on this point, Gordon
compared the extraordinarily high returns from 1982 to 2000 with the low
returns from 1965 to 1982 and cautioned against taking the last twenty
years of stock market data as a representative sample of returns. He
viewed the higher stock prices of the last twenty years as the result of
a series of positive supply shocks that unwound the earlier adverse
supply shocks that had depressed prices. Gordon suggested that it would
be imprudent for investors today to draw conclusions based on either
series alone. However, he thought that the risk of the stock market
might be substantially less now than it had been perceived to be earlier
in the twentieth century. Stabilization policy in the postwar period has
reduced the exposure of individual investors to the greater part of the
risk actually experienced, in both the stock market and consumption, in
the period before 1950. In addition, mutual funds now protect more
people from the risk associated with holding individual stocks. He
concluded that there are substantial reasons why the perceived risk of
stocks, as opposed to their return, may have fallen significantly.
Although the expected return has probably gone up, the risk has probably
gone down.
The discussion turned to the paper's implications for Social
Security. Alberto Alesina questioned the relevance of the model to
anyone with a paternalistic view of Social Security. Because
Parker's is a model in which investors are rational, any constraint
imposed by the Social Security system would appear to decrease utility.
Peter Orszag noted the importance of distinguishing between a policy of
investing Social Security funds in the stock market and a policy that
increases saving, either by prefunding the existing plan or by
increasing compulsory saving. He argued that although the paper supports
proposals to diversify the Social Security trust fund, it does not
provide evidence in favor of increased saving. He noted that a footnote in the paper suggests that the increase in estimated risk from
lengthening the horizon is actually greater for bonds than for stocks,
which would increase the desired portfolio share in stocks. Elaborating
on this point, William Nordhaus noted that, for liquidity-constrained
households, forced increases in saving could be utility decreasing, even
if equities are extremely attractive relative to risk-free investments.
A household that finds itself borrowing on its credit card at 16 percent
interest will not find it advantageous to borrow more to invest in
stocks. He noted further that if a parentalistic view with respect to
Social Security reflects the belief that consumers are not well informed
with respect to either financial investing or calculating future
savings, it may be undesirable to give individuals choice over the
portfolio allocation of their Social Security savings.
William Brainard suggested it would be interesting to examine
whether characteristics of households that vary over the life cycle are
useful in explaining risk taking or the response of consumption to
unexpected gains or losses. Even for a given measured wealth-income
ratio, young households have a great deal more human wealth relative to
financial wealth than do old households; unexpected returns on stocks
should therefore have a smaller percentage effect on the consumption of
younger households. Similarly, it would be interesting to compare
homeowners with renters, the college educated with the less educated,
and households whose earned income has a high correlation with market
returns with those for whom the correlation is low--stockbrokers and
college professors, for example.
Table 1. Consumption Risk of Equity and Implied Risk Aversion,
1959-2000 (a)
Flow consumption
Horizon Unconditional Implied risk
(quarters) covariance (b) aversion (c)
0 0.00017 379.3
(0.00016) (342.0)
1 0.00080 83.0
(0.00031) (32.5)
2 0.00104 63.7
(0.00043) (26.1)
3 0.00112 59.2
(0.00051) (27.0)
4 0.00155 42.7
(0.00064) (17.6)
5 0.00170 39.1
(0.00070) (16.2)
6 0.00186 35.6
(0.00074) (14.0)
7 0.00198 33.4
(0.00084) (14.1)
8 0.00163 40.6
(0.00096) (23.9)
9 0.00129 51.5
(0.00103) (41.4)
10 0.00167 39.7
(0.00125) (29.7)
11 0.00175 37.8
(0.00145) (31.4)
Total consumption expenditure
Horizon Unconditional Implied risk
(quarters) covariance (b) aversion (c)
0 0.00001 12,067.0
(0.00021) (453,259.3)
1 0.00088 75.4
(0.00037) (31.7)
2 0.00151 44.0
(0.00053) (15.5)
3 0.00161 41.2
(0.00064) (16.3)
4 0.00207 32.0
(0.00075) (11.6)
5 0.00210 31.5
(0.00082) (12.3)
6 0.00212 31.2
(0.00086) (12.7)
7 0.00215 30.8
(0.00099) (14.2)
8 0.00188 35.3
(0.00114) (21.5)
9 0.00159 41.6
(0.00124) (32.2)
10 0.00194 34.1
(0.00147) (25.7)
11 0.00171 38.8
(0.00170) (38.6)
Source: Author's calculations. See appendix for data sources.
(a.) Standard errors are reported in parentheses: for covariance
estimates they are calculated using the Newey-West procedure, and
for risk aversion estimates they do not reflect uncertainty in the
numerator and are calculated by the delta method.
(b.) Covariance of the logarithm of excess returns of stocks over
the risk-free interest rate during time t + 1 and the logarithm of
consumption growth from time t to t + 1 + S, where S is the
horizon.
(c.) Calculated as the sum of the mean log excess return and
one-half its variance, divided by their covariance.
Table 2. Consumption Risk of Equity and Implied Risk Aversion
Estimated from a Vector Autoregression, 1959-2000 (a)
Flow consumption
Horizon Conditional Implied risk
(quarters) covariance (b) aversion (c)
0 0.00021 323.1
(0.00014) (224.1)
1 0.00084 78.9
(0.00022) (20.8)
2 0.00117 56.6
(0.00030) (14.3)
3 0.00128 51.6
(0.00038) (15.2)
4 0.00171 38.9
(0.00046) (10.5)
5 0.00186 35.7
(0.00052) (9.9)
6 0.00195 34.0
(0.00057) (9.9)
7 0.00210 31.5
(0.00062) (9.3)
8 0.00220 30.1
(0.00068) (9.2)
9 0.00228 29.1
(0.00073) (9.3)
10 0.00237 27.9
(0.00078) (9.2)
11 0.00244 27.1
(0.00084) (9.3)
Total consumption
expenditure
Horizon Conditional Implied risk
(quarters) covariance (b) aversion (c)
0 0.00009 757.9
(0.00017) (1,498.5)
1 0.00101 65.8
(0.00026) (16.6)
2 0.00175 37.9
(0.00034) (7.4)
3 0.00189 35.1
(0.00045) (8.3)
4 0.00240 27.6
(0.00055) (6.3)
5 0.00258 25.7
(0.00062) (6.2)
6 0.00270 24.6
(0.00069) (6.3)
7 0.00287 23.1
(0.00076) (6.1)
8 0.00299 22.2
(0.00083) (6.2)
9 0.00309 21.5
(0.00090) (6.2)
10 0.00318 20.9
(0.00097) (6.4)
11 0.00324 20.5
(0.00104) (6.6)
Source: Author's calculations. See appendix for data sources.
(a.) Based on impulse responses from a VAR (see text and appendix
for details). Standard errors are reported in parentheses; for
covariance estimates they are bootstrapped from the estimated VAR
coefficients, and for risk aversion estimates they do not reflect
uncertainty in the numerator and are calculated by the delta
method.
(b.) Estimated as the impulse response of log consumption at
horizon S times the standard deviation of returns at an annual
rate.
(c.) Calculated as the sum of the mean log excess return and
one-half its variance, divided by their covariance.
Table 3. Conditional Consumption Risk of Equity and Implied Risk
Aversion, 1959-2000 (a)
Flow consumption
Horizon Conditional Implied risk
(quarters) covariance (b) aversion (c)
0 0.00020 329.4
(0.00015) (238.5)
1 0.00089 74.5
(0.00030) (25.4)
2 0.00114 58.3
(0.00040) (20.5)
3 0.00113 58.5
(0.00051) (26.5)
4 0.00147 45.0
(0.00066) (20.0)
5 0.00153 43.3
(0.00079) (22.3)
6 0.00166 39.9
(0.00097) (23.3)
7 0.00173 38.3
(0.00110) (24.4)
8 0.00136 48.6
(0.00130) (46.4)
9 0.00077 85.6
(0.00143) (157.5)
10 0.00127 52.4
(0.00171) (70.7)
11 0.00139 47.5
(0.00196) (66.9)
Total consumption
expenditure
Horizon Conditional Implied risk
(quarters) covariance (b) aversion (c)
0 0.00005 1,249.0
(0.00020) (4,715.7)
1 0.00090 73.7
(0.00037) (30.5)
2 0.00155 42.7
(0.00050) (13.7)
3 0.00149 44.5
(0.00063) (18.7)
4 0.00184 36.1
(0.00075) (14.8)
5 0.00175 38.0
(0.00092) (20.0)
6 0.00171 38.8
(0.00113) (25.5)
7 0.00167 39.7
(0.00131) (31.1)
8 0.00135 49.0
(0.00153) (55.6)
9 0.00081 81.9
(0.00164) (166.2)
10 0.00135 48.9
(0.00196) (71.0)
11 0.00121 54.8
(0.00227) (102.9)
Source: Author's calculations. See appendix for data sources.
(a.) Standard errors are reported in parentheses; for covariance
estimates they are calculated using the Newey-West procedure,
and for risk aversion estimates they do not reflect uncertainty
in the numerator and are calculated by the delta method.
(b.) Covariance of the logarithm of excess returns of stocks over
the risk-free interest rate during time t + 1 and the logarithm
of consumption growth from time t to t + 1 + S, where S is the
horizon.
(c.) Calculated as the sum of the mean log excess return and
one-half its variance, divided by their covariance.
Table 4. Consumption Risk of Equity and Implied Risk Aversion,
Using NIPA Flow Consumption Data, 1979-98 (a)
Unconditional estimates
Ratio of
Implied implied risk
level aversion to
Horizon of risk estimate for
(quarters) Covariance (b) aversion (c) 1959-2000 (d)
0 -0.00002 n.a. n.a.
(0.00023) n.a.
1 0.00031 210.9 2.5
(0.00047) (318.0)
2 0.00058 114.5 1.8
(0.00065) (128.6)
3 0.00045 147.3 2.5
(0.00083) (272.4)
4 0.00088 75.7 1.8
(0.00100) (86.8)
5 0.00091 72.8 1.9
(0.00108) (86.5)
6 0.00073 91.2 2.6
(0.00106) (132.7)
7 0.00077 85.9 2.6
(0.00116) (128.6)
Conditional estimates
Ratio of
Implied implied risk
level aversion to
Horizon of risk estimate for
(quarters) Covariance (b) aversion (c) 1959-2000 (d)
0 0.00009 702.5 2.1
(0.00021) (1,550.4)
1 0.00056 118.0 1.6
(0.00044) (92.2)
2 0.00096 69.0 1.2
(0.00056) (40.4)
3 0.00071 93.6 1.6
(0.00074) (98.2)
4 0.00098 67.4 1.5
(0.00088) (60.1)
5 0.00101 65.6 1.5
(0.00106) (69.0)
6 0.00058 113.6 2.8
(0.00117) (227.6)
7 0.00059 113.1 3.0
(0.00135) (260.8)
Source: Author's calculations. See appendix for data sources.
(a.) Standard errors are reported in parentheses; for covariance
estimates they are calculated using the Newey-West procedure,
and for risk aversion estimates they do not reflect uncertainty
in the numerator and are calculated by the delta method.
(b.) Covariance of the logarithm of excess returns of stocks over
the risk-free interest rate during time t + 1 and the logarithm
of consumption growth from time t to t + 1 + S, where S is the
horizon.
(c.) Calculated as the sum of the mean log excess return and
one-half its variance (both estimated over 1959-2000), divided
by their covariance.
(d.) Ratio of implied risk aversion shown here to that of the
corresponding horizon from table 1 (unconditional covariance)
or table 3 (conditional covariance).
Table 5. Consumption Risk of Equity and Implied Risk Aversion,
Using NIPA Total Consumption Expenditure Data, 1979-98 (a)
Unconditional estimates
Ratio of
Implied implied risk
level aversion to
Horizon of risk estimate for
(quarters) Covariance aversion 1959-2000
0 -0.00031 n.a. n.a.
(0.00030) n.a.
1 0.00045 148.3 2.0
(0.00053) (175.3)
2 0.00110 60.1 1.4
(0.00076) (41.6)
3 0.00107 62.0 1.5
(0.00096) (55.8)
4 0.00120 55.5 1.7
(0.00111) (51.6)
5 0.00117 56.5 1.8
(0.00117) (56.2)
6 0.00085 78.4 2.5
(0.00120) (110.9)
7 0.00086 77.5 2.5
(0.00131) (118.2)
Conditional estimates
Ratio of
Implied implied risk
level aversion to
Horizon of risk estimate for
(quarters) Covariance aversion 1959-2000
0 -0.00020 n.a. n.a.
(0.00028) n.a.
1 0.00058 114.2 1.5
(0.00048) (93.6)
2 0.00138 47.9 1.1
(0.00061) (21.3)
3 0.00113 58.6 1.3
(0.00078) (40.3)
4 0.00108 61.6 1.7
(0.00084) (48.0)
5 0.00102 65.0 1.7
(0.00104) (66.6)
6 0.00038 174.2 4.5
(0.00122) (559.2)
7 0.00036 184.5 4.7
(0.00152) (779.4)
Source: Author's calculations. See appendix for data sources.
(a.) See table 4 for details.
Table 6. Consumption Risk of Equity for Stockholders and Implied
Risk Aversion, Using CEX Flow Consumption Data (a)
Unconditional estimates
Adjusted
Adjusted risk
Horizon Covariance, covariance, aversion,
(quarters) 1979-98 (b) 1959-2000 (c) 1959-2000 (c)
0 0.00072 n.a. n.a.
(0.00064) n.a. n.a.
1 0.00194 0.00493 13.4
(0.00088) (0.00224) (6.1)
2 0.00251 0.00451 14.7
(0.00115) (0.00207) (6.8)
3 0.00133 0.00331 20.0
(0.00127) (0.00316) (19.0)
4 0.00229 0.00406 16.3
(0.00114) (0.00202) (8.1)
5 0.00210 0.00391 16.9
(0.00126) (0.00235) (10.1)
6 0.00223 0.00572 11.6
(0.00145) (0.00372) (7.6)
7 0.00261 0.00670 9.9
(0.00141) (0.00362) (5.3)
Conditional estimates
Adjusted
Adjusted risk
Horizon Covariance, Covariance, aversion,
(quarters) 1979-98 (b) 1979-98 (b) 1959-2000 (c)
0 0.00097 0.00208 31.9
(0.00068) (0.00145) (22.3)
1 0.00244 0.00387 17.1
(0.00082) (0.00130) (5.8)
2 0.00357 0.00422 15.7
(0.00106) (0.00125) (4.7)
3 0.00246 0.00394 16.8
(0.00118) (0.00189) (8.1)
4 0.00373 0.00559 11.9
(0.00123) (0.00184) (3.9)
5 0.00330 0.00500 13.2
(0.00146) (0.00221) (5.8)
6 0.00346 0.00984 6.7
(0.00166) (0.00472) (3.2)
7 0.00412 0.01216 5.4
(0.00163) (0.00481) (2.2)
Source: Author's calculations. See appendix for details.
(a.) Sample periods are 1979:4 through 1998:1 for unadjusted
covariance estimates and 1959:1 through 2000:4 for adjusted
estimates. Standard errors are reported in parentheses; for
covariance estimates they are calculated using the Newey-West
procedure, and for risk aversion estimates they do not reflect
uncertainty in the numerator and are calculated by the delta
method.
(b.) Covariance of the logarithm of excess returns of stocks over
the risk-free interest rate during time t + 1 and the logarithm of
consumption growth from time t to t + 1 + S, where S is the horizon.
(c.) Scaled by the ratio of aggregate covariance in the two
periods.
Table 7. Consumption Risk of Equity for Stockholders and Implied
Risk Aversion, Using CEX Total Consumption Expenditure Data (a)
Unconditional estimates
Adjusted
Adjusted risk
Horizon Covariance, covariance, aversion,
(quarters) 1979-98 1959-2000 1959-2000
0 0.00248 n.a. n.a.
(0.00149) n.a. n.a.
1 0.00335 0.00659 10.1
(0.00151) (0.00297) (4.5)
2 0.00377 0.00515 12.9
(0.00197) (0.00269) (6.7)
3 0.00290 0.00437 15.2
(0.00254) (0.00383) (13.3)
4 0.00451 0.00782 8.5
(0.00226) (0.00392) (4.2)
5 0.00554 0.00993 6.7
(0.00266) (0.00477) (3.2)
6 0.00391 0.00981 6.8
(0.00323) (0.00810) (5.6)
7 0.00316 0.00794 8.3
(0.00285) (0.00716) (7.5)
Conditional estimates
Adjusted
Adjusted risk
Horizon Covariance, covariance, aversion,
(quarters) 1979-98 1959-2000 1959-2000
0 0.00221 n.a. n.a.
(0.00151) n.a. n.a.
1 0.00316 0.00490 13.5
(0.00150) (0.00232) (6.4)
2 0.00443 0.00498 13.3
(0.00197) (0.00221) (5.9)
3 0.00330 0.00435 15.3
(0.00264) (0.00348) (12.2)
4 0.00516 0.00880 7.5
(0.00256) (0.00437) (3.7)
5 0.00591 0.01013 6.5
(0.00295) (0.00505) (3.3)
6 0.00438 0.01968 3.4
(0.00355) (0.01595) (2.7)
7 0.00435 0.02024 3.3
(0.00317) (0.01475) (2.4)
Source: Author's calculations. See appendix for data sources.
(a.) See table 6 for details.
Table 8. Consumption Risk of Equity and Implied Risk Aversion,
Using Pseudo-NIPA Flow Consumption Data (a)
Unconditional estimates
Adjusted
Adjusted risk
Horizon Covariance, covariance, aversion,
(quarters) 1979-98 (b) 1959-2000 (c) 1959-2000 (c)
0 -0.00035 n.a. n.a.
(0.00068) n.a. n.a.
1 0.00182 0.00463 14.3
(0.00078) (0.00198) (6.1)
2 0.00280 0.00503 13.2
(0.00106) (0.00190) (5.0)
3 0.00159 0.00396 16.8
(0.00102) (0.00254) (10.8)
4 0.00184 0.00326 20.4
(0.00129) (0.00228) (14.3)
5 0.00084 0.00157 42.3
(0.00118) (0.00220) (59.1)
6 0.00052 0.00132 50.1
(0.00111) (0.00285) (107.5)
7 0.00064 0.00164 40.5
(0.00108) (0.00277) (68.5)
Conditional estimates
Adjusted
Adjusted risk
Horizon Covariance, covariance, aversion,
(quarters) 1979-98 (b) 1959-2000 (c) 1959-2000 (c)
0 -0.00035 -0.00074 n.a
(0.00068) (0.00145) n.a
1 0.00186 0.00295 22.5
(0.00085) (0.00135) (10.3)
2 0.00259 0.00306 21.6
(0.00106) (0.00125) (8.8)
3 0.00134 0.00214 30.9
(0.00084) (0.00135) (19.4)
4 0.00154 0.00231 28.8
(0.00109) (0.00163) (20.4)
5 0.00073 0.00111 59.5
(0.00098) (0.00149) (79.7)
6 0.00027 0.00076 86.9
(0.00099) (0.00281) (320.8)
7 0.00035 0.00103 64.2
(0.00092) (0.00271) (169.0)
Source: Author's calculations. See appendix for data sources.
(a.) CEX data are used to construct a series consistent with the
NIPA consumption measures (see text and appendix for details).
Sample periods are 1979:4 through 1998:1 for unadjusted covariance
estimates and 1959:1 through 2000:4 for adjusted estimates.
Standard errors are reported in parentheses; for covariance
estimates they are calculated using the Newey-West procedure, and
for risk aversion estimates they do not reflect uncertainty in the
numerator and are calculated by the delta method.
(b.) Covariance of the logarithm of excess returns of stocks over
the risk-free interest rate during time t + 1 and the logarithm of
consumption growth from time t to t + 1 + S, where S is the horizon.
(c.) Scaled by the ratio of aggregate covariance in the two periods.
Table 9. Consumption Risk of Equity and Implied Risk Aversion,
Using Pseudo-NIPA Total Consumption Expenditure Data (a)
Unconditional estimates
Adjusted
Adjusted risk
Horizon Covariance, covariance, aversion,
(quarters) 1979-98 1959-2000 1959-2000
0 0.00047 n.a. n.a.
(0.00071) n.a. n.a.
1 0.00209 0.00411 16.2
(0.00106) (0.00208) (8.2)
2 0.00290 0.00397 16.7
(0.00143) (0.00196) (8.3)
3 0.00242 0.00365 18.1
(0.00147) (0.00221) (11.0)
4 0.00207 0.00359 18.4
(0.00168) (0.00291) (14.9)
5 0.00148 0.00265 25.1
(0.00170) (0.00305) (28.8)
6 0.00091 0.00228 29.1
(0.00167) (0.00419) (53.6)
7 0.00051 0.00128 51.9
(0.00170) (0.00427) (173.3)
Conditional estimates
Adjusted
Adjusted risk
Horizon Covariance, covariance, aversion,
(quarters) 1979-98 1959-2000 1959-2000
0 0.00067 n.a. n.a.
(0.00072) n.a. n.a.
1 0.00211 0.00327 20.3
(0.00110) (0.00170) (10.5)
2 0.00274 0.00308 21.5
(0.00123) (0.00138) (9.6)
3 0.00221 0.00291 22.7
(0.00116) (0.00153) (12.0)
4 0.00152 0.00259 25.5
(0.00126) (0.00215) (21.2)
5 0.00112 0.00192 34.5
(0.00122) (0.00209) (37.4)
6 0.00027 0.00122 54.2
(0.00123) (0.00553) (245.6)
7 -0.00036 n.a. n.a.
(0.00132) n.a. n.a.
Source: Author's calculations. See appendix for data sources.
(a.) See table 8 for details.
Table 10. Consumption Risk of Equity and Implied Risk Aversion, for
Older and Wealthy Households in the CEX (a)
Flow consumption
Unconditional estimates Conditional estimates
Adjusted
risk Adjusted
aversion, risk
Horizon Covariance, 1959- Covariance, aversion,
(quarters) 1979-98 (b) 2000 (c) 1979-98 (b) 1959-2000 (c)
Households headed by persons aged sixty-five and older
0 -0.00057 n.a. -0.00055 n.a.
(0.00077) n.a. (0.00074) n.a.
5 0.00104 34.3 0.00114 38.3
(0.00105) (34.7) (0.00119) (39.8)
6 0.00110 23.4 0.00123 19.0
(0.00078) (16.5) (0.00085) (13.1)
Households holding more than $25,000 in equities (d)
0 0.00055 n.a. 0.00017 180.1
(0.00149) n.a. (0.00152) (1586.4)
5 0.00242 14.7 0.00271 16.1
(0.00288) (17.5) (0.00296) (17.6)
6 0.00180 14.4 0.00210 11.1
(0.00305) (24.4) (0.00319) (16.9)
Total consumption expenditure
Unconditional estimates Conditional estimates
Adjusted
risk Adjusted
aversion, risk
Horizon Covariance, 1959- Covariance, aversion,
(quarters) 1979-98 (b) 2000 (c) 1979-98 (b) 1959-2000 (c)
Households headed by persons aged sixty-five and older
0 0.00171 n.a. 0.00131 n.a.
(0.00093) n.a. (0.00091) n.a.
5 0.00077 48.3 0.00087 44.3
(0.00152) (95.5) (0.00163) (82.4)
6 0.00140 18.9 0.00168 8.8
(0.00153) (20.7) (0.00152) (8.0)
Households holding more than $25,000 in equities (d)
0 0.00265 n.a. 0.00211 n.a.
(0.00262) n.a. (0.00275) n.a.
5 0.00741 5.0 0.00567 6.8
(0.00456) (3.1) (0.00502) (6.0)
6 0.00436 6.1 0.00236 6.2
(0.00493) (6.9) (0.00618) (16.3)
Source: Author's calculations. See appendix for data sources.
(a.) Sample periods are 1979:4 through 1998:1 for unadjusted
covariance estimates and 1959:1 through 2000:4 for adjusted
estimates. Standard errors are reported in parentheses; for
covariance estimates they are calculated using the Newey-West
procedure, and for risk aversion estimates they do not reflect
uncertainty in the numerator and are calculated by the delta
method.
(b.) Covariance of the logarithm of excess returns of stocks over
the risk-free interest rate during time t + 1 and the logarithm of
consumption growth from time t to t + 1 + S, where S is the
horizon.
(c.) Scaled by the ratio of aggregate covariance in the two
periods.
(d.) In 1982-84 dollars.
I thank Pierre-Olivier Gourinchas, Christian Julliard, David
Laibson, Monika Piazzesi, Bruce Preston, Christopher Sims, Nicholas
Souleles, Annette Vissing-Jorgensen, Mark Watson, and Michael Woodford for helpful discussions. I am also grateful to the discussants and
participants in the Brookings Panel for their comments. Motohiro Yogo
and Christian Julliard provided excellent research assistance in the
summers of 2000 and 2001, respectively. Financial support was provided
by National Science Foundation grant SES-0096076 and by a National
Bureau of Economic Research Aging and Health Economics Fellowship
through National Institute on Aging grant number T32 AG00186.
(1.) See Grossman and Shiller (1981), Shiller (1982), and Mehra and
Prescott (1985).
(2.) This view is endorsed in such widely cited books as Glassman
and Hassett (1999).
(3.) This approach is also pursued in contemporaneous work by
Gabaix and Laibson (forthcoming).
(4.) Mankiw and Zeldes (1991).
(5.) The slow adjustment of consumption has a long history starting
with Flavin (1981) and Hall and Mishkin (1982). See the surveys in
Deaton (1992) and Browning and Lusardi (1996). Three recent papers that
explore the consumption response to the stock market more generally are
Parker (1999b), Ludvigson and Steindel (1999), and Dynan and Maki
(2001).
(6.) See Brainard, Nelson, and Shapiro (1991), Cochrane and Hansen
(1992), Daniel and Marshall (1997), and Piazzesi (forthcoming).
(7.) See Vissing-Jorgensen (1998), Attanasio, Banks, and Tanner (1998), and Brav, Constantinides, and Geczy (1999).
(8.) In part this is because the order in which one takes the steps
from one series to the other affects the relative importance of each
difference, and in part it is because, consistent with substantial
statistical uncertainty, the importance of different sources is not
robust to small changes in data construction.
(9.) This finding is closely related to the finding that the risk
of equity for the consumption of luxury goods is sufficient to
rationalize the average premium on equity. See Ait-Sahalia, Parker, and
Yogo (2001).
(10.) Hansen and Singleton (1983).
(11.) The data and calculations in this paragraph are described in
more detail below. The result is standard and is representative of any
reasonable use of the data.
(12.) See, for example, the discussion in Mehra and Prescott (1985)
and the thought experiment in Mankiw and Zeldes (1991, p. 105). Further,
large levels of risk aversion pose other problems for the model, most
notably in matching the observed risk-free real interest rate. See Weil
(1989).
(13.) This literature is not in agreement about the explanation for
this failure, but this literature has the problem of too many models
fitting the time-series data on consumption and risk-free returns rather
than none.
(14.) On the first assumption see Attanasio and Weber (1995) and
Basu and Kimball (2000); on the second see Zeldes (1989), Caballero (1990), Carroll (1997), and Gourinchas and Parker (forthcoming); on the
third see Grossman and Laroque (1990), Caballero (1993), Ogaki and
Reinhart (1998), Attanasio and Weber (1995), and Baxter and Jermann
(1999); on the fourth see Attanasio and Weber (1993) and Wilcox (1992);
and on the fifth see Caballero (1995), Parker (1999a), Souleles
(forthcoming), and Sims (2001).
(15.) I do not discuss these models, because good surveys already
exist--see Campbell (1999) and Kocherlakota (1996)--and because
discussing any one model opens a Pandora's box. That said, perhaps
the leading candidate for a successful model is that based on habit
formation (Constantinides, 1990). Many versions of the habit formation
model now exist, but all have at least one of three major shortcomings.
First, many models (for example, Campbell and Cochrane, 1999) still
require extremely high risk aversion coefficients to match the data.
Second, models constructed to fit some aspects of asset data are
rejected when tested in other contexts (see Dynan, 2000, and Otrok,
Ravikumar, and Whiteman, 2001). Third, these models suggest that the
level of consumption in the medium or the long term is largely
irrelevant for welfare, a difficult assumption to square with results
and successful models in most other areas of economics.
(16.) Factor models that omit asset prices can price assets without
reference to other assets. Although many observed factors that predict
time variation in returns, like those of Lettau and Ludvigson (2001),
Lamont (1998), and Campbell (1987), are based on asset prices, factor
models lack the structure necessary to judge the riskiness of stocks or
the sensibility of implied preferences. Factor models provide clues
about the structure of the correct model but cannot address the question
at hand.
(17.) This derivation and those in the rest of this section are
done for the case of unconditional moments only. However, derivations of
risk aversion in terms of conditional moments are completely analogous.
(18.) Gabaix and Laibson (forthcoming). See also Lynch (1996) and
Marshall and Parekh (1999).
(19.) Wilcox (1992).
(20.) See Ait-Sahalia, Parker, and Yogo (2001).
(21.) I thank Gregory Mankiw for raising this point. See Grossman,
Melino, and Shiller (1987).
(22.) This statement is based upon confidence intervals in similar
VARs in which consumption growth is included in place of the level of
consumption.
(23.) One could also adjust the numerator so that the variance of
returns is reduced by the extent to which they are one-step-ahead
predictable. This is not done for three reasons: first, this adjustment
in practice is small; second, the bias from not making this adjustment
is toward making risk aversion larger; and finally, this makes clear
that differences in risk aversion across horizon and method are due to
differences in the estimated consumption risk of equity.
(24.) Ludvigson and Steindel (1999) estimate a more structural VAR
and find a long-run elasticity of consumption to equity returns of only
5 percent. Parker (1999b) also studies the consumption response to the
stock market using survey data from the Panel Study of Income Dynamics
and finds elasticities of less than 5 percent.
(25.) See Mankiw (1986). An alternative way to cast the puzzle is
to say that the return on equity is too high relative to the covariance
of aggregate wealth and equity returns, for reasonable levels of risk
aversion. See Davis, Nalewaik, and Willen (2000) and the discussion in
sections 4.3 and 4.4 of Campbell (1999).
(26.) This measure is not conservative in that it is possible that
a household included as a stockholder might in fact hold a corporate
bond mutual fund, or corporate bonds directly, and not hold any stock.
However, it seems reasonable that households who hold such assets also
have easy access to stock funds. In this case the Euler equation for
consumption and stock return should hold for these households, and they
belong in the sample of stockholders.
(27.) Using all possible three-month-to-three-month changes uses
more of the information available in the survey than do papers that
collapse the data to a quarterly frequency. This approach increases the
amount of data and so aids inference in the presence of measurement
error.
(28.) Measurement error also motivates the linear approach used
throughout the paper. First, I do not estimate nonlinear Euler
equations, because Vissing-Jorgensen (1998) and Brav, Constantinides,
and Geczy (1999) find problems with measurement error for estimating
nonlinear Euler equations. Second, I do not use Hansen and Jaganathan
bounds because they require that one estimate the variance of
consumption growth rather than its covariance with returns. Given both
mismeasurement and clustering in the survey design, this is an uncertain
exercise.
(29.) Because of the overlapping nature of the data, sampling
generates correlation across measurement error in different periods.
However, this mismeasurement should still be uncorrelated with returns.
Further, since any given household is in the survey for at most three
consecutive consumption growth rate observations, correlation across
observations is short-lived, and inference with the Newey-West standard
errors should provide accurate measures of statistical uncertainty.
(30.) This result also follows directly from the result that
uncertainty in a stochastic discount factor that is uncorrelated with
returns does not affect the price of the asset. This result, in turn, is
the reverse of the well-known result that uncertainty in returns that is
uncorrelated with consumption does not affect the price of the asset.
(31.) See in particular Vissing-Jorgensen (forthcoming). My own
experience is that grouped linear estimators perform quite similarly as
one reduces the sample size until the average group size falls below
seventy-five. Of course, this may differ from application to
application.
(32.) Data for these calculations are quarterly Flow of Funds data
from the Federal Reserve.
(33.) This factor also measures any differences in the estimates of
the covariance due to different small-sample properties of the
covariance measure between the longer and the shorter samples.
(34.) Vissing-Jorgensen (1998); Bray, Constantinides, and Geczy
(1999). Vissing-Jorgensen (forthcoming) does not include estimates of
risk aversion from this method since the contemporaneous covariances are
not large enough to ensure reasonably tight confidence intervals around
the risk aversion estimates. Standard errors using the delta method
(used here) are sensitive to the value of the covariance.
(35.) Dynan and Maki (2001) use the CEX to study the consumption
response of stockholders to the stock market, conditional on
household-level income movements and the mean return in each year.
Although this formulation is not theoretically correct for the current
exercise, they find levels of medium-term risk much greater than the
contemporaneous risk, their point estimates would imply even higher
covariances and lower (more plausible) estimates of risk aversion than
found here.
(36.) Calculations per effective householder are also done at the
household level rather than simply making the data per person.
(37.) See Attanasio and Weber (1993).
(38.) It is also worth noting that, partly as a result of
statistical uncertainty, and unlike the results up to this point, the
magnitudes of the comparisons in this section depend to some extent upon
relatively minor (although correct) decisions concerning the
construction of the data.
(39.) See, for example, Constantinides and Duffie (1996),
Constantinides, Donaldson, and Mehra (forthcoming), and Heaton and Lucas
(1996). Parker (1998) shows that consumption and liquid wealth are
closely related at low levels of liquid wealth, implying that an
investment in equity could significantly raise consumption volatility
for households with low liquid wealth.
(40.) The risk-return trade-off for long-term bonds lies between
those of short-term bonds and the stock market, and so is also a puzzle.
It seems reasonable to assume that households that hold corporate bonds
have easy access to corporate equity, and therefore that limited
participation has no role in explaining the risk-return trade-off
between these two assets. For this model to work, therefore, it must be
that the increase in measured risk that one observes in moving from a
contemporaneous measure to a medium-term measure is greater for bonds
than for equity, which, if true, is another interesting clue for
modeling consumption behavior.
(41.) Another important caveat is that the canonical models do not
always predict that opening a previously closed market gives welfare
gains at all. For discussion of the issues, see the analyses of Allen
and Gale (1994), Willen (2001), and Abel (2001).
(42.) See, for example, the discussions in Vissing-Jorgensen (1998)
and Heaton and Lucas (2000).
(43.) Some early real data are available only in chained 1992
dollars. The early portion of the series in 1992 dollars is converted to
1996 chain-weighted dollars by rescaling to make the series averages
match in the first four common quarters, which are the four quarters of
1967.
References
Ait-Sahalia, Yacine, Jonathan A. Parker, and Motohiro Yogo. 2001.
"Luxury Goods and the Equity Premium." Working Paper 8417.
Cambridge, Mass.: National Bureau of Economic Research (August).
Allen, Franklin, and Douglas Gale. 1994. "Limited Market
Participation and Volatility of Asset Prices." American Economic
Review 84(4): 933-55.
Attanasio, Orazio, James Banks, and Sarah Tanner. 1998. "Asset
Holding and Consumption Volatility." Working Paper 6567. Cambridge.
Mass.: National Bureau of Economic Research (May).
Attanasio, Orazio P., and Guglielmo Weber. 1993. "Consumption
Growth, the Interest Rate and Aggregation." Review of Economic
Studies 60 (3): 631-49.
--. 1995. "Is Consumption Growth Consistent with Intertemporal
Optimization? Evidence from the Consumer Expenditure Survey."
Journal of Political Economy 103(6): 1121-57.
Basu, Susanto, and Miles S. Kimball. 2000. "Long-Run Labor
Supply and the Elasticity of Intertemporal Substitution for
Consumption." Unpublished paper. University of Michigan (December).
Baxter, Marianne, and Urban J. Jermann. 1999. "Household
Production and the Excess Sensitivity of Consumption to Current
Income." American Economic Review 89(4): 902-20.
Bertaut, Carol C., and Michael Haliassos. 1995. "Why Do So Few
Hold Stocks?" Economic Journal 105(432): 1110-29.
Brainard, William C., William R. Nelson, and Matthew D. Shapiro.
1991. "The Consumption Beta Explains Expected Returns at Long
Horizons." Unpublished paper. Yale University (June).
Brav, Alon, George M. Constantinides, and Christopher C. Geczy.
1999. "Asset Pricing with Heterogeneous Consumers and Limited
Participation: Empirical Evidence." Working Paper 7406. Cambridge,
Mass.: National Bureau of Economic Research (October).
Browning, Martin, and Annamaria Lusardi. 1996. "Household
Saving: Micro The-ories and Micro Facts." Journal of Economic
Literature 34(4): 1797-1855.
Caballero, Ricardo J. 1990. "Consumption Puzzles and
Precautionary Savings." Journal of Monetary Economics 25(1):
113-36.
--. 1993. "Durable Goods: An Explanation for Their Slow
Adjustment." Journal of Political Economy 101(2): 351-84.
--. 1995. "Near-Rationality, Heterogeneity, and Aggregate
Consumption." Journal of Money, Credit, and Banking 27(1): 29-48.
Campbell, John Y. 1987. "Stock Returns and the Term
Structure." Journal of Financial Economics 18(2): 373-99.
--. 1999. "Asset Prices, Consumption, and the Business
Cycle." In Handbook of Macroeconomics, volume 1C, edited by John B.
Taylor and Michael Woodford. Elsevier Press.
Campbell, John Y., and John H. Cochrane. 1999. "By Force of
Habit: A Consumption-Based Explanation of Aggregate Stock Market
Behavior." Journal of Political Economy 107(2): 205-51.
Carroll, Christopher D. 1997. "Buffer-Stock Saving and the
Life Cycle/Permanent Income Hypothesis." Quarterly Journal of
Economics 112(1): 1-55.
Cochrane, John H., and Lars Peter Hansen. 1992. "Asset Pricing
Explorations for Macroeconomics." In NBER Macroeconomics Annual,
edited by Olivier Blanchard and Stanley Fischer. MIT Press.
Coco, Joao F., Francisco J. Gomes, and Pascal J. Maenhout. 2001.
"Consumption and Portfolio Choice over the Life-Cycle."
Working paper. London Business School (May).
Constantinides, George M. 1990. "Habit Formation: A Resolution
of the Equity Premium Puzzle." Journal of Political Economy 98(3):
519-43.
Constantinides, George M., John B. Donaldson, and Rajnish Mehra.
Forthcoming. "Junior Can't Borrow: A New Perspective on the
Equity Premium Puzzle." Quarterly Journal of Economics.
Constantinides, George M., and Darrell Duffie. 1996. "Asset
Pricing with Heterogeneous Consumers." Journal of Political Economy
104(2): 219-40.
Daniel, Kent D., and David Marshall. 1997. "The Equity Premium
Puzzle and the Risk-Free Rate Puzzle at Long Horizons."
Macroeconomic Dynamics 1 (2): 452-84.
Davis, Steven J., Jeremy Nalewaik, and Paul Willen. 2000. "On
the Gains to International Trade in Risky Financial Assets."
Working Paper 7796. Cambridge, Mass.: National Bureau of Economic
Research (July).
Davis, Steven J., and Paul Willen. 2000a. "Using Financial
Assets to Hedge Labor Income Risks: Estimating the Benefits."
Unpublished paper. University of Chicago Graduate School of Business (March).
--. 2000b. "Occupation-Level Income Shocks and Asset Returns:
Their Covariance and Implications for Portfolio Choice." Working
Paper 7905. Cambridge, Mass.: National Bureau of Economic Research
(September).
Deaton, Angus. 1992. Understanding Consumption. Oxford, England:
Clarendon Press.
Dynan, Karen E. 2000. "Habit Formation in Consumer
Preferences: Evidence from Panel Data." American Economic Review
90(3): 391-406.
Dynan, Karen E., and Dean M. Maki. 2001. "Does the Stock
Market Matter for Consumption?" Finance and Economics Discussion
Working Paper 2001-23. Washington: Federal Reserve Board (May).
Flavin, Marjorie A. 1981. "The Adjustment of Consumption to
Changing Expectations about Future Income." Journal of Political
Economy 89(5): 974-1009.
Gabaix, Xavier, and David Laibson. Forthcoming. "The 6D Bias
and the Equity Premium Puzzle." In NBER Macroeconomics Annual,
edited by Ben S. Bernanke and Kenneth Rogoff. MIT Press.
Glassman, James K., and Kevin A. Hassett. 1999. Dow 36,000: The New
Strategy for Profiting from the Coming Rise in the Stock Market. New
York: Three Rivers Press.
Gourinchas, Pierre-Olivier, and Jonathan A. Parker. Forthcoming.
"Consumption Over the Life Cycle." Econometrica.
Grossman, Sanford J., and Guy Laroque. 1990 "Asset Pricing and
Optimal Portfolio Choice in the Presence of Illiquid Durable Consumption
Goods." Econometrica 58(1): 25-51.
Grossman, Sanford J., Angelo Melino, and Robert J. Shiller. 1987.
"Estimating the Continuous-Time Consumption-Based Asset-Pricing
Model." Journal of Business and Economic Statistics 5(3): 315-27.
Grossman, Sanford J., and Robert J. Shiller. 1981. "The
Determinants of the Variability of Stock Market Prices." American
Economic Review Papers and Proceedings 71 (2): 222-27.
Hall, Robert E. 1978. "Stochastic Implications of the Life
Cycle-Permanent Income Hypothesis: Theory and Evidence." Journal of
Political Economy 86(6): 971-87.
Hall, Robert E., and Frederic S. Mishkin. 1982. "The
Sensitivity of Consumption to Transitory Income: Estimates from Panel
Data on Households." Econometrica 50(2): 461-81.
Hansen, Lars Peter, and Kenneth J. Singleton. 1983.
"Stochastic Consumption, Risk Aversion, and the Temporal Behavior
of Asset Returns." Journal of Political Economy 91 (2): 249-65.
Heaton, John, and Deborah Lucas. 1996. "Evaluating the Effects
of Incomplete Markets on Risk Sharing and Asset Pricing." Journal
of Political Economy 104(3): 443-87.
--. 1997. "Market Frictions, Savings Behavior, and Portfolio
Choice." Macroeconomic Dynamics 1 (1): 76-101.
--. 1999. "Stock Prices and Fundamentals." In NBER
Macroeconomics Annual, edited by Ben S. Bernanke and Julio J. Rotemberg.
MIT Press.
---. 2000. "Portfolio Choice and Asset Prices: The Importance
of Entrepreneurial Risk." Journal of Finance 55(3): 1163-98.
Keynes, John Maynard. 1931. "Economic Possibilities for Our
Grandchildren." In Essays in Persuasion. London: Macmillan.
Kocherlakota, Narayana R. 1996. "The Equity Premium: It's
Still a Puzzle." Journal of Economic Literature 34(1): 42-71.
Lamont, Owen. 1998. "Earnings and Expected Returns."
Journal of Finance 53(5): 1563-87.
Lettau, Martin, and Sydney Ludvigson. 2001. "Consumption,
Aggregate Wealth, and Expected Stock Returns." Journal of Finance
56(3): 815-49.
Ludvigson, Sydney, and Charles Steindel. 1999. "How Important
is the Stock Market Effect on Consumption?" Federal Reserve Bank of
New York Economic Policy Review 5(2): 29-51.
Lynch, Anthony W. 1996. "Decision Frequency and
Synchronization across Agents: Implications for Aggregate Consumption
and Equity Return." Journal of Finance 51 (4): 1479-97.
Mankiw, N. Gregory. 1986. "The Equity Premium and the
Concentration of Aggregate Shocks." Journal of Financial Economics
17(1): 211-19.
Mankiw, N. Gregory, and Stephen Zeldes. 1991. "The Consumption
of Stockholders and Nonstockholders." Journal of Financial
Economics 29(1): 97-112.
Marshall, David A., and Nayan G. Parekh. 1999. "Can Costs of
Consumption Adjustment Explain Asset Pricing Puzzles?" Journal of
Finance 54(2): 623-54.
Mehra, Rajnish, and Edward C. Prescott. 1985. "The Equity
Premium: A Puzzle." Journal of Monetary Economics 15(2): 145-61.
Ogaki, Masao, and Carmen M. Reinhart. 1998. "Measuring
Intertemporal Substitution: The Role of Durable Goods." Journal of
Political Economy 106(5): 1078-98.
Otrok, Christopher, B. Ravikumar, and Charles H. Whiteman. 2001.
"Habit Formation: A Resolution of the Equity Premium Puzzle."
University of Iowa Working Paper 98-04 (May).
Parker, Jonathan A. 1998. "The Consumption Function
Re-Estimated." Unpublished paper. University of Wisconsin
(December).
--. 1999a. "The Reaction of Household Consumption to
Predictable Changes in Social Security Taxes." American Economic;
Review 89(4): 959-73.
--. 1999b. "Spendthrift in America? On Two Decades of Decline
in the U.S. Saving Rate." In NBER Macroeconomics Annual, edited by
Ben S. Bernanke and Julio J. Rotemberg. MIT Press.
Piazzesi, Monika. Forthcoming. "Comment on Gabaix and Laibson,
`The 6D Bias and the Equity Premium Puzzle.'" In NBER
Macroeconomics Annual, edited by Ben S. Bernanke and Kenneth Rogoff. MIT
Press.
Poterba, James, and Andrew Samwick. 1995. "Stock Ownership
Patterns, Stock Market Fluctuations and Consumption." BPEA, 2:1995,
295-372.
Shiller, Robert J. 1982. "Consumption, Asset Markets, and
Macroeconomic Fluctuations." Carnegie Rochester Conference Series
on Public Policy 17: 203-38.
Sims, Christopher A. 2001. "Implications of Rational
Inattention." Unpublished paper. Princeton University (June).
Souleles, Nicholas S. Forthcoming. "Consumer Sentiment: Its
Rationality and Usefulness in Forecasting Expenditure--Evidence from the
Michigan Micro Data." Journal of Money, Credit, and Banking.
Storesletten, Kjetil, Chris I. Telmer, and Amir Yaron. 2001.
"Asset Pricing with Idiosyncratic Risk and Overlapping
Generations." Working paper. Carnegie Mellon University (May).
Vissing-Jorgensen, Annette. 1998. "Limited Stock Market
Participation." Unpublished paper. Massachusetts Institute of
Technology (May).
--. 2000. "Towards an Explanation of Household Portfolio
Choice Heterogeneity: Nonfinancial Income and Participation Cost
Structures." Working paper. University of Chicago (September).
--. Forthcoming. "Limited Asset Market Participation and the
Elasticity of Intertemporal Substitution." Journal of Political
Economy.
Weil, Phillipe. 1989. "The Equity Premium Puzzle and the
Risk-Free Rate Puzzle." Journal of Monetary Economics 24(3):
401-21.
Wilcox, David W. 1992. "The Construction of U.S. Consumption
Data: Some Facts and Their Implications for Empirical Work."
American Economic Review 82(4): 922-41.
Willen, Paul. 2001. "New Financial Markets: Who Gains and Who
Loses." Unpublished paper. University of Chicago (September).
Zeldes, Stephen P. 1989. "Consumption and Liquidity
Constraints: An Empirical Investigation." Journal of Political
Economy 97(2): 305-46.
JONATHAN A. PARKER
Princeton University