Theology and Difference: The Wound of Reason.
Cunningham, David S.
By Walter Lowe. Indiana Series in the Philosophy of Religion.
Bloomington: Indiana University, 1993. Pp. xiii + 181. $29.95.
Commentators lament the failure of theology to engage the work of
Derrida. While deconstruction has affected biblical studies, its
theological appropriation has been largely limited to those intent upon
proclaiming the "death of God" or otherwise dismantling
religious belief. We have needed an exposition of deconstruction as a
tool which could be adapted for use by traditional systematic
theologians.
Such an exposition has now been written, and it is a tour de force.
Lowe, professor of systematics at Emory University, believes
Derrida's work can operate in the service of Christian theology.
But he knows that few would be convinced if he spoke only the
insider's argot and ignored traditional concerns; instead, he
focuses on Derrida's affinities with perhaps the most important
modern philosopher (Kant) and theologian (Barth). Theologians who have
put off engagement with Derrida because "he's just too
different" no longer have an excuse.
L. argues that the Enlightenment metaphysic ignored human
limitations and sought to provide a complete, coherent, definitive
metanarrative of origin, separation, and restoration. This metanarrative
fails because it does not adequately account for the reality of human
suffering, especially the violence that is the hallmark of our century.
The alternative is a "radical hermeneutics" that admits the
limits and brokenness of the human condition. Deconstruction provides an
appropriate method, because it testifies, "directly or indirectly,
to the reality of human brokenness" (xi). Deconstruction recognizes
the reality of evil and sin.
Consequently, suffering is a focus of the book. Following J. B.
Metz, L. argues that suffering provides us with a critical standard
against which experience can be tested, as well as a common vision of
the human condition and an awareness of our need for redemption. But
unlike Metz, who focuses mainly on praxis, L. is concerned with
theoretical reason as well: "that crucial, broken but perceptive
thinking represented by the memory of suffering" (11). L.'s
subtitle takes full advantage of its ambiguous genitive: reason may
indeed inflict wounds, but it also bears a wound. "A reason aware
of its own brokenness might prove, in the end, a better guide than one
committed a priori to healthy-mindedness" (11).
L. begins with a fine discussion of Barth's Romerbrief,
arguing that its emphasis upon the "qualitative difference"
between God and humanity is not so much a minimization of human striving
(as a Nietzschean critic might suppose), but a leveling of the playing
field. In asserting the significant difference between God and humanity,
Barth cautions us against attributing an inflated importance to the less
significant (but always impinging) differences within the created order.
Derrida is brought into the conversation, along with Freud and Husserl,
in order to develop a splendid critique of traditional hermeneutics.
L. now returns to Kant, whose early work on theodicy echoes
Barth's emphasis on the qualitative difference between God and
humanity. This is nicely contrasted with Enlightenment optimism; and
here readers, fearing a lengthy account of Leibnizian theodicy, are
surprised by a delightful account of Alexander Pope's "An
Essay on Man" instead. The contrast could not be greater, and it
demonstrates the rhetorical appeal of linking humanity to God via
"the great chain of being." By contrast, Kant appears almost
Barthian: "On the terms which Kant has explicitly prepared, to
speak of fundamental difference is to speak of one difference and one
difference only, namely the difference between that which is finite,
however grand, and that which is infinite" (90). Kant's
metaphysics, rationalistic though they may be, nevertheless operate
coram Deo; and this view continues, though implicitly, into the critical
writings and especially the Second Critique. Consequently, the
categorical imperative appears increasingly relevant for Christian
ethics. And this is an important claim, for the ethical implications of
deconstruction have not been adequately explored in the contemporary
theological engagement with Derrida. Hence L. concludes with an incisive
critique of the work of Mark C. Taylor, and reiterates the claim that
genuine thought is broken thought, and that a genuine human life is a
suffering life.
My only significant complaint is that L.'s account of
brokenness and suffering is fairly abstract. His occasional nods toward
a passion-centered Christology and a fleeting reference to The Brothers
Karamazov suggest that L. has the resources to offer a more concrete
account of this "wound of reason." A more Christological focus
would also have made his concluding reflections on ethics more
persuasive. Finally, suffering here is primarily a white, Western, male
enterprise (the favorite example is of a platoon leader). Yet L. is
generally sensitive about matters of inclusivity, and his larger claims
need not be as limited as his examples.
L. sees his work as offering a possible alternative to the
method(s) of correlation currently popular among theologians. For this
alone, he deserves commendation. Moreover, he has produced a fine work
of philosophical theology, inviting systematic theologians with
traditional concerns to learn more about deconstruction and employ it in
the service of the gospel. That the book will likely be attacked by
deconstructionist "insiders," who will resent L.'s
unwillingness to play their game and make sacrifices to their gods, only
makes it all the more inviting.