The limits of bioethics.
Satel, Sally
ON VALETINE's DAY two years ago, Paul Wagner, a 40-year-old
Philadelphia purchasing manager, gave Gail Tomas, a total stranger, his
left kidney. Wagner met Tomas, a 65-year-old former opera singer, on the
internet, at MatchingDonors.com. Her daughter had posted an ad asking
some magnificent stranger to save her mother. "It was there that I
read about a lady in my city, Philadelphia, who was desperate for
help," Wagner said. "It has been one of the best decisions I
have ever made." This story had a happy ending. Yet it unfolded
amid controversy over whether ethical norms were violated.
Exasperated by the efforts of sick and needy patients to find
donors for themselves, Dr. Douglas Hanto, a transplant surgeon at the
Beth Israel Deaconess Hospital in Boston, complained "it will
undermine trust in the whole system.' By "system," Hanto
was referring to the national transplant list. Today, there are over
83,000 people in line for a kidney in the United States, In places such
as New York and California, the wait can be up to eight years. Unless a
friend or a relative offers a kidney, people such as Tomas languish on
dialysis, awaiting an organ from a deceased donor. They die at the rate
of I3 per day because an organ did not arrive in time--hence the frantic
plea of Tomas's daughter to anyone who would consider donating to
her mother.
A few years ago, Hanto, a former head of the ethics committee of
the American Society of Transplant Surgeons, had his hospital turn away
a fragile patient named Lisa Cunningham, a 40-year-old former social
worker with a young son, whose prospective donor read about her plight
in a local newspaper. Arthur Caplan, a prominent bioethicist at the
University of Pennsylvania, condemned donor solicitation online as
"an outbreak of impatience combined with a me-first attitude,"
he a reporter.
Me first? Cunningham was not snatching a kidney away from someone
else. Except for the story about her, there would have been no offer in
the first place Moreover, every so-called Good Samaritan donor who gives
to someone like Cunningham or Tomas removes them from the queue, and so
others move up a slot. No one is. harmed while someone is saved.
Caplan is a bioethicist; his titles imply an expertise in ethics.
Hanto served as the chair of the Ethics Committee at the American
Society of Transplant Surgeons. Yet what are we to make of their
willingness to issue life-and-death pronouncements involving other
people? Well, we know a few things about them. First, that they share an
absolutist approach to egalitarianism: If all cannot benefit, then none
should benefit. Second, as ethicists they presume to know how despairing
patients should conduct their private affairs. And third, they appear to
have few qualms about conveying to desperately ill people a message of
hopelessness: Be passive, dying patients--wait your turn and take no
initiative to save your own life.
Does being a bioethicist entitle one to any such moral authority,
edifying the rest of us about right and wrong? Is this what society
should expect of its "ethics experts"?
The proper relationship between experts and citizens is a question
of longstanding interest to sociologists and social critics. In the case
of bioethicists, the nature of the subject about which they claim
authority is up for debate traditionally, they have focused on the
controversies surrounding biomedical technology, such as cloning, sex
selection, in vitro fertilization, nanotechnology, research ethics,
organ allocation, and so on. Now experts are calling for involvement in
policy. Renee Fox and Judith P. Swazey, senior scholars who have studied
the sociology and history of bioethic, urge a focus on
"inequalities in health and in access to health care in
America." The field is too "narrowly American-ocentric,"
they write in their 2008 book Observing Bioethics; it should become
"more centrally and deeply involved with [global] suffering and
issues of social justice." In his new book The Future of Bioethics,
Howard Brody, a physician and philosopher at the University of Texas
Medical Branch, instructs bioethicists to gauge success by asking
themselves if they are "speaking truth to power." These
prescriptions presume a moral authority that bioethicists cannot
properly claim.
Origins
WHERE DID BIOETHICISTS come from? Ethical conundrums in medicine
long predated the creation of the field now known as bioethics. In his
respected book The Birth of Bioethics, Albert R. Jonsen, a moral
theologian and bioethicist, dates the origin of bioethics as a distinct
discipline to 1947, the year that 23 physicians were convicted of war
crimes during the Nuremberg tribunal. Others believe the field grew out
of postwar technological capabilities that intensified the already
vexing dilemmas about human control over life and death. Medical
controversies over care for the terminally ill, reproductive technology,
genetic manipulation, and organ transplantation drew the attention of
Catholic theologians and other religious scholars in the 1950s and
1960s. In concert with philosophically inclined physicians and
scientists, they began to apply moral theory to modern medical
controversies. The exploration of these issues soon became more
secularized as historians, philosophers, anthropologists, legal
scholars, and others joined in.
At the same time it became clear that as technology enhanced
physicians' therapeutic powers, it increased the range of
interventions that patients could undergo and the vulnerability that
came from not understanding the risks of those interventions. This
recognition brought questions about docks' duty to inform patients
about the treatments prescribed, the alternates available, the
patient's prognosis, and the right to refuse care. A back-lash
against medical paternalism that was already underway in the 1960s began
to attract academics who were engaged in the civil rights and antiwar
movements and harbored a keen distrust
of institutions; they trained their sights on resetting the balance
of power between physicians and patients.
As ethical quandaries multiplied and demanded attention, it was
perhaps inevitable that a specialized group of professionals--the
bioethicists--would emerge to meet the task. In an impressive burst of
institution-building that was funded by both the federal government and
private philanthropies, three bioethics think tanks sprang up between
1969 and 1971: the Hastings center, in upstate New York; the now defunct
Society for Health id Human Values, in Philadelphia; and the Kennedy
Institute of Ethics at Georgetown University, a Jesuit institute, in
Washington. Populated by Physicians, legal scholars, philosophers,
historians, and humanists, their agendas coalesced around cutting-edge
issues such as genetic testing, organ transplants, in vitro
fertilization, neonatal intensive care units, euthanasia, and other
conundrums surrounding death and dying. And when, in the 1970s, research
scandals at Willowbrook and Tuskegee erupted, research ethics and
regulatory oversight were added to the bioethics portfolio.
Inhabitants of the ivory tower were eager to make themselves
relevant by applying theory to real-world problems. According to Daniel
Callahan, one of the founders of the Hastings Center, he and his
colleagues wanted to give philosophy "some social bite, some
'relevance.'" In 1982, in an article called "How
Medicine Saved the Life of Ethics," the philosopher and historian
Stephen Toulmin argued that the imperatives of medicine enabled moral
philosophy to avoid the academic sidelines. And there is no question
that, in some cases, physicians themselves turned to theologians and
moral philosophers for help.
Today, bioethics has an impressive institutional footprint. Major
universities house bioethics centers that offer a plethora of programs:
intensive immersion courses, certificate programs, master's and
doctoral degree programs. The field has several peer-reviewed journals
and a major professional organization. Bioethicists teach medical
students and undergraduates; they serve on hospital ethics committees
and on research review boards. In many hospitals bioethicists are
"on call" to offer guidance on issues such as the mental
competence of patients and whether certain life-prolonging treatments
should be initiated or withdrawn. Some are regularly sought out by the
media, others consult for pharmaceutical companies, and a few even serve
as expert witnesses in courts of law. In the public policy arena,
bioethicists are appointed to presidential commissions and state and
federal task forces that formulate guidelines and advise politicians.
Since 1970, the year in which the term "bioethics" was
coined by Sargent Shriver, the institutional base of bioethics has
flourished. The swift rate of growth alone makes the field itself
perhaps as interesting as the problems it addresses. As the bioethicist
Carl Elliot has pointed out, every sector of society has its moral
dimensions, "yet in no other sphere of our lives [but medicine] has
ethics been so thoroughly professionalized ... it is worth stepping back
and noting just how unusual this really is." No wonder bioethics
has become a subject of study in its own right.
A wide-open field
BIOETHICS TODAY IS a today is a field with widely divergent
understanding of itself. In meetings of the American Society for
Bioethics and Humanities (ASBH), which is the major professional
organization for bioethicists, and in journal symposia, participants try
to come to terms with the question of what kind of enterprise bioethics
is. Is it a field of scholarly inquiry, a learned profession, a
consultancy, a form of policy-making or activism, an oversight apparatus
that monitors researchers and physicians, a discourse, a project, or a
collection of questions or issues? What training should a bioethicist
receive? Should the field take stands on mainstream political issues,
such as the war in Iraq, the crisis in Darfur, Abu Ghraib? Are
bioethicists excessively beholden to the institutions that they serve?
when I spoke in 2006 at the annual meeting of the ASBH on the
assigned topic of whether the organization should take political
positions--I said no--the reception I received was chilly indeed. This
was a question that the society itself had been debating for years.
During the q and a, almost all the bioethicists who asked questions
contested my view that professional groups Linage their credibility when
they pronounce on issues outside of their expertise. Au contraire, they
said; as experts in ethical matters, who better than to opine? I
remember feeling sympathy for the leadership of the ASBH, which has to
accommodate these competing views, and I admired the officers for
inviting me in the first place and for airing the society's
internal disagreements openly.
Is it politically desirable for society to credit a designated
group called "bioethicists" with expertise in resolving the
most difficult moral questions? If so, what is it that gives ethicists a
more legitimate claim applied to wisdom about right and wrong than the
rest of us? The matter of ethical expertise--what it looks like, who can
claim it--a profound one. The place of bioethics in the academy, in the
clinical aim, and in society turns on it. For most of us, the very idea
of the "right" answer to a complex moral dilemma seems absurd
on its face. After all, its derivation depends upon which moral theory
one favors: deontological, consequentialist, natural law, situational,
and so on.
By no means does this negate the possibility, let alone the
importance, of serious moral reflection, but such analyses may be too
lost in the foundational questions to be of much everyday use. And, of
course, many bioethicists rely on their own philosophical biases. So,
for example, when bioethicists condemn organ donor solicitation with the
argument that it gives unfair advantage to some or violates human
dignity, we must ask what makes them sufficiently sure of their view to
impose it on others? Finding the "right" moral
answer--assuming for a moment one exists--is not the business of applied
ethics. So what can bioethics offer? What is its technical expertise?
The answer comes into focus when we think of applied ethics as a
deliberative process, one that concerns itself with how to determine
what ought to done rather than to make a concrete determination per se.
For example, hen an expert in bioethics approaches a problem, such as an
end-of-life vision, he brings a deep knowledge of the cultural history
of that controversy, including the conceptual schemes that have been
used to resolve it and relevant legal decisions. This allows him to draw
analogies to current situations. While hovering above the fray the
bioethicist objectively delineates value conflicts, lays out the
assumptions behind different positions, evaluates the soundness of
arguments according to standard rules of logic, and reflects upon the
potential consequences of various courses of action. Mostly, he imparts
this analysis to the doctors or administrators who enlisted his advice.
However, when working directly with patients, the task is typically one
of helping them or their loved ones reach consensus about end-of-life
decisions or course of treatment.
Ultimately, the bioethicist presents his analysis to the designated
decision-maker--typically a physician or an administrator--who is
accountable to his patients and his employer. Bioethicists should not
advocate for patients or physicians or hospitals; they should advocate
for disinterested moral deliberation. Nor should they mistake consensus,
which is required in order to take action, for the discovery of moral
truth. The role of the bioethicist, then, should be to illuminate
debates, not to settle them. In the parlance of medicine, they do not
have prescribing privileges.
Though many bioethicists disavow the mantle of moral authority that
the professionalization of ethics implies, many others, alas, do not.
Ask almost any hospital physician about this and you will get, in
reliable sequence, an eye roll, a sigh, and then an earful of anecdotes
about swaggering bioethicists posing as arbiters of right and wrong
("Wizards of Oughts," as the critic Giles Scofield put it). In
the media, the coverage of almost any biomedical controversy is sure to
contain a quotation from a bioethicist with oracular pretensions. The
message is clear: Anyone who disagrees with me is thoughtless or
unethical.
Such arrogance discomfits ethical bioethicists as well. Erik Parens
of the Hastings Center, located just outside of New York City, regrets
the popular view of ethicist as "priggish or foolish enough to lay
claim to how other people should lead their lives." Fed up with
Homo bioethicus, Carl Elliott of the University of Minnesota has
remarked that "Many people working in and around bioethics wince if
someone called them a 'bioethicist' ... Some resist the aura
of professionalism and moral expertise that the term bioethics seems to
imply. Others are just embarrassed by the incivility and glibness of our
public spokespeople. Others just don't want to be viewed as the
ethics police.
Bioethics and social justice
BIOETHICISTS LIKE RUTH MACKLIN of the Albert Einstein College of
Medicine would have bioethics adopt an aggressive pursuit of social
justice. "As a liberal, humanitarian bioethicist," she told
interviewers, "I acknowledge that my chief concern is in striving
for greater social justice within and among societies, and reducing
disparities in health, wealth, and other resources among populations in
the world." Howard Brody opines that the future agenda of bioethics
"ought to be concerned with power disparities." These may be
noble aspirations, but one must ask what particular authority or skill
bioethicists possess that qualifies them to solve global health
problems, let alone economic ones. Achieving social justice in health is
a complex task that requires the forging of a meaningful universal
agreement on what health care should be like and what kind of scheme
should dictate the national and transnational allocation of medical
resources. Lest Americans be accused of bioethical imperialism, they
will need to be part of a consensus involving countries whose
fundamental views of justice, fairness, and basic human rights may
differ dramatically from our own and from one another.
It is unclear what the field of bioethics can add in the way of
unique scholarship, practical wisdom, or ethical reflection that is not
already being applied today, for better or worse, by experts in
international development, global health economics, and political
theory. Granted, there might be a role for the dispassionate
articulation of moral options, but as Fox and Swazey portray them,
bioethicists who seek a global stage sound more like activists intent on
changing the world. Moreover, so many of the world's tragic
circumstances do not need subtle moral clarification. They result from
unjust institutions and corrupt leaders, and they require state and
international action in the political and in some cases even the
military realms. Displacing oppressive regimes and establishing the rule
of law are no jobs for a bioethicist. The question for bioethics, then,
is whether such a moral crusade is an appropriate mission for the field.
Or, as the philosopher and bioethicist Jonathan Moreno has rightly
asked, "Can a scholarly field retain its intellectual legitimacy,
both internally and in the eyes of the public, when some of its core
topics seem to be matters of ideology, rather than, or at least as much
as, expertise?"
The origin of the current crisis of purpose, identity, and
expertise in bioethics stems in large part from its being a derivative
enterprise. During the 1960s and early 1970s, bioethics was less a
distinct field than a collegial network of scholars and learned
professionals who shared a mutual interest in applying moral theory to
medical quandaries. These physicians, legal theorists, philosophers,
historians, anthropologists, and sociologists were members of
established academic disciplines with distinct bodies of knowledge, with
time-honored theories and methods of inquiry. They brought those
intellectual traditions to bear on questions of value-conflict within
medicine. But when the zone of intersecting interests promoted itself
into a primary, semi-autonomous field of its own, in much the same way
that women's studies or black studies did, it became more and more
estranged from the rigorous scholarly disciplines that spawned it. Now
many students aspire to become "bioethicists" without any
other disciplinary background.
"Conservative" bioethics
THOUGH PROFESSIONAL BIOETHICISTS may not agree, they tend to close
ranks when outsiders presume to make ethical claims. Fox and Swazey
describe how mainstream bioethics--which they consider to be
"essentially synonymous [with] liberal bioethics"--reacted
with tribal animus to the ascendancy of conservative bioethics during
the Bush administration.
A defining moment of the bioethics culture wars was August 9, 2001.
On that day President Bush announced federal funding, with restrictions,
for human embryonic stem cell research and named Leon Kass, a vocal
critic of embryonic stem cell cloning, as director of a new
President's Council on Bioethics.
During its tenure, which ended in June 2009, the Council elicited
full-throated denunciations by many in the academy. Among the most vocal
was Alta Charo, a legal scholar and bioethicist from the University of
Wisconsin (recently named by the Obama Administration to serve as a
senior advisor at the Food and Drug Administration) who has referred to
Kass's reign as "the Endarkenment." More dramatically,
when Kass presented the keynote at the ASBH in 2004, the atmosphere in
the lecture room crackled with hostility and some in the audience stood
with their backs to him as he spoke.
The implication is clear: The conservative agenda is essentially
inhospitable to scientific progress and, by extension, to the patients
who could benefit from its fruits. Recall when Dolly, the cloned
Scottish ewe, stepped daintily into the public square in 1997. For the
most part, mainstream bioethicists were exhilarated by the therapeutic
promise she represented, whereas their right-leaning colleagues saw
Dolly's creation as a threat to the sanctity of life and the
beginning of a program that could well end in cloning designer children.
The right and the left have a profoundly different understanding of what
is at stake; and the rift between them, it is safe to say, is
unbridgeable.
So deft are some conservative bioethicists at conjuring apocalyptic
visions of a post-human future that the journalist Will Saletan has
characterized them as "standing athwart history, sighing
'Oy.'" He has a point. To be sure, they sigh with
erudition and with eloquence. Should conservative bioethicists--or any
bioethicist, for that matter--counsel us on reasons for vigilance? Yes,
but too often they warn us not to make any progress at all. There is an
irony here. For all the deference that conservative bioethics pays to
the implicit wisdom of the ages, it rarely mines the recent past for
lessons. Instead of concentrating on the ancients, why not also study
the history of in vitro fertilization, paid egg donation, and surrogate
motherhood to learn about cultural resistance and adaptation to such
practices?
Even better, why not consider earlier practices that were deemed
repugnant in their day but are now unexceptionable? The list of these
moral apocalypses that never were is a distinguished one: vaccination,
anesthesia, blood transfusions, life insurance, artificial insemination.
Perhaps the systematic analysis of these practices holds little interest
for conservative bioethicists because most of society now regards them
as nonissues. Or more likely, they regard an objective assessment as
irrelevant given their convictions that certain practices pose such an
affront to human dignity that they should not be pursued at all, no
matter how much good can come of them.
And what about politics? To be fair, mainstream bioethicists are
correct when they say that conservative bioethicists often have a
political agenda. But so do they, making their assertion that President
Bush's Council on Bioethics was too partisan and
homogeneous--"a council of clones," as Arthur Caplan
remarked--amusing indeed. Having attended several council meetings
myself, I can attest to its diversity of views and its careful
deliberation. In the end, yes, the "Oys" had it but, no
surprise, other bioethics commissions have displayed their own slant.
They were "chaired by liberals, staffed by liberals, [with]
overwhelmingly liberal members," according to Daniel Callahan of
the Hastings Center. Yet, as Callahan says, "they received hardly
any criticism at all." When bioethicists swim in the same
ideological waters as the administrations they serve, their likeminded
colleagues find little to complain about--but a bias may still lurk.
The human subject
NO DISCUSSION OF bioethics is complete without a discussion of
human subject research. It is through the regulatory reach of ethics
oversight that we see how deeply institutionalized bioethics has
penetrated medicine. In 1974, in response to the revelations surrounding
the Tuskegee Syphilis Study, Congress passed the National Research Act.
It mandated the creation of institutional review boards, or IRBS, to
ensure that the benefits of research outweighed the risks and that
individuals know those risks before consenting to become a subject. All
human subject research conducted in medical schools, universities, and
federal agencies must be approved by IRBS.
Today many IRBS are hidebound bureaucracies. The informed consent
documents that subjects must read and sign can run to dozens of pages.
To spare themselves suffocation by red tape, researchers sometimes
abandon studies altogether. Changing a single word in a consent form at
the request of an IRB can entail a months-long wait for approval after
resubmission. Out of zealous concern for subjects' privacy, some
IRBS require that raw data, including tapes and transcripts, be
destroyed a few years after collection. For investigators who wish to
replicate or to extend the original work, this is an irretrievable loss
of information. Amid burdensome paperwork requirements and nitpicky
objections to even the most innocuous interventions, projects are often
held up for months. This costs medical schools considerable amounts of
money and, as in the case of cancer drug trials, it surely costs actual
lives.
Efforts to assure informed consent and subject autonomy often veer
into smothering paternalism. Consider the complaints of mental health
researchers in the wake of September II. Their timely access to victims
was thwarted by IRBS concerned that subjects would be
"re-traumatized" by filling out a questionnaire or undergoing
an interview. Along these lines, many IRBS spend hours deliberating over
whether subjects will be "coerced" into participating in a
study if offered a token gratuity of, say, $25. More serious cases have
involved the refusal to allow parents to enroll their terminally ill
children in studies. In the pioneering days of liver transplants, for
example, some bioethicists said that parents of dying infants should not
be allowed to give them a life-saving segment of their own liver. The
reason? No parent would refuse the opportunity to save his own
child's life--thus, he would effectively be "coerced"
into doing so--and so the option should not exist at all.
Based on this dubious logic, the power of decision would have been
taken from the parents. Someone else knew better. What's more, as
doctors have long observed, some parents do indeed refuse, especially if
they have other children for whom they must remain healthy and not risk
major surgery. The scenario echoes the time in the mid-1990s when
ethicists urged physicians to withhold genetic test results from women
with a high risk of breast cancer. The knowledge, they believed, was
just too dangerous for the women to handle.
And yet, the field of bioethics considers the institutionalization of research ethics to be among its greatest accomplishments. Having
attended anniversary conferences commemorating the Belmont Report, a
document that in 1979 set forth the basic principles of human research,
Fox and Swazey portray themselves as bemused to hear bioethicists
praising Belmont as "near-canonical," having "changed the
world," and having been "consecrated" by its impact. To
be sure, nobody denies the need for research oversight. But at many
institutions the pendulum surely has swung too far in the direction of
vigilance. Relentless scrutiny and seemingly capricious restriction have
fostered mutual distrust between reviewers and researchers, making
legitimate regulation more difficult and encouraging gaming by
investigators.
Priorities for bioethicists
WHEN BIOETHICISTS SPEAK, who listens? When geologists weigh in on
global warming, attention must be paid. After all, they are experts in
climate science. When bioethicists put a full-page ad in the New York
Times urging the passage of universal health care, as they did in 1994,
what kind of expertise do they bring to bear? Citizens interested in the
debate are sufficiently versed in its moral dimensions;
"experts" are not required to tell them what is and is not
ethical. Nor does the repudiation of Matchingdonors.com hold sway with
vulnerable patients, the people who love them, or most of the doctors
who want to save them. They embrace their own moral imperative: to
minimize suffering through the unparalleled kindness of strangers.
At their best, bioethicists are scholars who study the intellectual
and social history of value controversies in medicine and biotechnology.
They can teach us about the technical and cultural antecedents of modern
debates and show us how to engage in disciplined moral inquiry. They are
skilled at drawing conceptual maps of the dilemma at hand while
enumerating various ways to resolve it. In these ways, bioethicists have
much to offer. But beyond this, their value is mainly cosmetic or
bureaucratic. When called upon by politicians, their main task is to
neutralize explosive issues or to provide ethical cover for decisions
that have already been made. When physicians summon them, it is mostly
to mediate disputes between patients, staff, and family members
regarding end-of-life decisions. The media tap bioethicists for
high-minded sound bites. In hospitals and in governmental agencies, they
man the regulatory ramparts.
It is hard to gauge how much impact organized bioethics has had on
society. If the activist wing closed up shop and the pundits went home,
it is doubtful they would be missed. But one hopes that at least its
scholarly and didactic entities will live on. With our growing technical
capacity to manipulate our biology and thus our destiny, biomedical
dilemmas will certainly increase in number and in difficulty, and they
will require as much thoughtful attention as they can get. But social
justice should be left to others--to the rest of us. The more bioethics
promotes an agenda of social or economic reform, the more it betrays
itself to be politics by other means.
Sally Satel, a practicing psychiatrist, is a resident scholar at
the American Enterprise Institute. She is the editor, most recently, of
When Altruism Isn't Enough: The Case for Compensating Kidney Donors
(AEI Press, 2009).