Humans, Animals, and the Human Animal. .
Menashi, Steven
MATTHEW SCULLY. Dominion: The Power of Man, the Suffering of
Animals, and the Call to Mercy. ST. MARTIN'S PRESS. 464 PAGES.
$27.95
TYPICALLY, animal rights activists are hard to take Seriously.
Shortly after the September 2001 terrorist attacks, for example, one
Karen Davis, president of an outfit called United Poultry Concerns, took
to the pages of Vegan Voice to opine, "I think it is speciesist to
think that the September 1 x attack on the World Trade Center was a
greater tragedy than what millions of chickens endured that day and what
they endure every day because they cannot defend themselves against the
concerted human appetites arrayed against them." Indeed, "For
35 million chickens in the United States alone, every single night is a
terrorist attack." Lurking behind such comments one perceives a
perverse hostility to human dignity, and the attitude expressed is so
inhuman that the only appropriate response is contempt.
So it is understandable that sensible people often take some
satisfaction in expressions of callousness toward animals. "Calves
are adorable," writes Slate columnist David Plotz. "But veal
is delicious." Food critic Digby Anderson, writing in the Daily
Telegraph, maintains, "In a civilized society rabbits are shot (or
snared or ferreted) and eaten. They are not shot grudgingly, as vermin,
and eaten grudgingly, to use up what had to be shot. They are to be
eaten enthusiastically with mustard sauce." Given the animal
lobby's own unconscionableness ("Six million Jews died in
concentration camps," PETA founder Ingrid Newkirk once told the
Washington Post, "but six billion broiler chickens will die this
year in slaughterhouses"), these seem like measured ripostes, and
many otherwise animal-loving people relish the angst that such comments
doubtless produce among the zoolatrous.
And who, really, can blame them? The animal rights crowd is, by and
large, a contemptible bunch--people who belittle human life not only in
their rhetoric, but also increasingly through arson and physical
attacks. (The FBI counts the Earth Liberation Front among the
nation's largest terrorist groups.) And then there's animal
liberation scholar Peter Singer, the Ira W. DeCamp professor of
bioethics in the University Center for Human Values at Princeton
University, who--though he is really a more serious thinker than his
critics are willing to admit--is still one who champions such practices
as infanticide and bestiality.
Into this mix steps Mathew Scully, a former speechwriter for George
W. Bush and National Review editor, with Dominion: The Power of Man, the
Suffering of Animals, and the Call to Mercy. To a general audience,
Scully appears as our of place among the PETA crowd as Nixon did in
China--and it seems he has opened some doors as well. The Weekly
Standard's Fred Barnes gave Dominion, and its cause, a glowing
review in the Wall Street Journal. And Dominion appeared on the cover of
the American Conservative, and in National Review, and in the Weekly
Standard, and received praise from the likes of G. Gordon Liddy and
Joseph Sobran. Suddenly, animal rights is an important topic among
conservatives, which was Scully's intent. His primary audience is
conservatives, and especially religious conservatives: "More than
anything else, I hope with this book to speak to those people."
In Dominion, Scully introduces us to folks just as objectionable as
the animal activists. He visits Safari Club International, where he
finds people who hunt sheep by helicopter, or practice "canned
hunting" (shooting exotic wildlife while they're trapped and
helpless), or watch videos like DoubleBarreled Zambezi Adventure
("You're right there to see four dramatic brain shots!").
Most shocking is Scully's look at a modern factory farm, where pigs
are kept immobile in tiny cages, never to step outdoors, and subjected
to treatment so brutal even to watch that all 5,000 farm employees
quit--and need to be replaced--every year.
What distinguishes Dominion, however, is Scully's
determination to distance himself from the more intemperate animal
liberation advocates, who deny any essential difference between people
and animals and insist on the legal enforcement of animal rights. Scully
isn't interested, he says, in elaborating a formal doctrine of
animal rights, finding that "the rights cause with its more
extravagant claims has become a convenient foil, a pretext for
disregarding the subject of animal welfare altogether." Nor does he
deny the singular dignity of the human being. Rather, Scully wants to
make the case for animals based on an older, and more readily agreeable,
concept--mercy. As he writes in the book's introduction,
"Animals are more than ever a test of our character, of
mankind's capacity for empathy and for decent, honorable conduct
and faithful stewardship. We are called to treat them with kindness, not
because they have rights or power or some claim to equality, but in a
sense because they don't; because they all st and unequal and
powerless before us."
The vision is appealing, and probably captures the mainstream
thinking about animal welfare. We are often horrified not by an actual
wrong done to animals--after all, animals harm each other all the time,
and we don't find that behavior problematic--but by the sort of
person who would intentionally torture an innocent sentient being. When
we act out of what Scully calls "a spirit of kindness and
clemency" toward our fellow creatures, we exhibit the best elements
of human character. "There are moments," says Scully,
"when life demands some basic response of fellow-feeling and mercy
and love." When we make jokes about veal calves or otherwise
display indifference to suffering, it turns out that we've lost
touch with some salutary impulse in our nature. Laws prohibiting cruelty
to animals, by this logic, would rank with laws against other
practices--dueling, for example--that don't really involve a victim
but are too gruesome to occur in a decent society.
Scully has received much praise for rescuing the cause of animal
welfare from the extremism of the animal rights movement and for
sounding a call to mercy rather than to litigation. The problem,
however, is that he doesn't actually do that. In the end, Scully
comes around to the animal rights position. "If a man beats,
neglects, starves, or abandons a dog, and the dog belongs to him, there
are no grounds to punish that man except by recognizing some independent
moral claim of the dog," he argues. Scully claims that by enacting
laws against animal cruelty, we have already conceded that animals have
rights, and the only question left is how far those rights extend.
"Once it is granted that humans can act wrongfully in our power
over animals," Scully asks rhetorically, "what grounds are
left for denying that animals have a right not to be treated wrongfully
at our hands?"
This is simply mistaken. We also have laws against damaging
historical buildings and landmarks, or forests and streams, even when
they are privately owned, but that doesn't mean we invest houses
and trees with any legal rights.
Throughout Dominion, Scully oscillates between an appeal to mercy
and forbearance for the animals and an invocation of animal rights.
(Ultimately, in his recommendations for public policy and legal reform,
he sides with the animal rights approach: people "can worry about
their own souls.") There is a similar tension when Scully berates
Peter Singer for his "attack on the sanctity of human life"
and then also criticizes science writer Stephen Budiansky for working
"to kill any sense of kinship we feel even with primates."
Surveying scientific and anecdotal data regarding animal intelligence,
Scully concludes that we share "thought and feeling" with
nonhuman animals, having an advantage only in our possession of verbal
language and more highly developed "abstract concepts." The
difference between humans and animals, then, appears to be one of degree
rather than kind. Compared to human consciousness, animal consciousness
is "a humbler version of the same thing," as Scully puts
it--which is precisely Singer's position.
IT TURNS OUT that there are really two Matthew Scullys in Dominion,
with two divergent attitudes toward animals. On the one hand, there is
the humanist Scully, who acknowledges human superiority but encourages
mercy for inferior creation. In this account, humans are marked by a
"spiritual grandeur" that animals lack, a vision that
accommodates the Christian view that humans, created in the image of
God, possess a special dignity. Humans stand above and apart from the
animal world, which "we enter as lords of the earth bearing strange
powers of terror and mercy alike." In short, humans are God to the
animals. Scully makes this analogy explicit in commenting on a British
law to ban fur:
I find the language of the bill very touching, the full majesty of
the law here reaching down even to those afflicted creatures huddled in
their cages, just as the merciful judgment that every human being will
need must come in a way and from a place as far from our understanding
as the halls of Westminster are to them.
Such a relationship leaves no room for animal rights, it would
seem. "Only before one another do we ourselves even have a right to
life," Scully admits. "Before our Maker we are rightless, our
very existence an act of divine generosity." If humans really are
as gods to the animals, claims on behalf of animals can't constrain
people in the way Scully intends. The animals' fates would test
with human generosity--which is not, it turns out, reliable enough.
On the other hand, there is a second, naturalist Scully, for whom
animals are our "fellow creatures," sharing thought and
emotion as well as instinct and appetite:
It is easy to look down upon the animals as utterly alien to us,
driven on by need and instinct in their grubbier, less rational way,
slavering for food and attention like our pets, jostling at the trough
on our farms, battling one another in the wild over mates and territory
and status in the group. But the person who thinks himself entirely
above and apart from this world need only take a closer look at his or
her own daily existence, at the struggles and hurts and yearnings of
body that still mark each and every human life. We do our share of
grubbing and jostling and competing for mates, too, and for good reason
do we say of people hurt or humiliated that they are "licking their
wounds." There is a kinship in this, for all our loftier
capacities, a fellowship with the creatures.
For Scully the naturalist, man stands within rather than outside
nature, and humans and animals are subject to the same God.
Scully invokes each vision according to the needs of his argument,
deploying the humanist conception when he wants to urge us to rise above
the law of the jungle (by, say, abstaining from meat in favor of
soybeans) and the naturalist account when he wants to deflate human
arrogance.
Our most arrogant presumptions center on the concept of Dominion,
the authority God gives man over the animals in Genesis, which Scully
finds invoked time and again by rather unsavory people to justify rather
unsavory practices. Today, Dominion is taken to be justification for the
humanist view, for our godlike powers over the animals. But that's
not at all what the Bible says. After all, at the same moment God gives
man Dominion over the creatures, He also instructs man to eat plants
rather than animals (Gen. 1:29).
And there's more: Animals, along with man, are given the
Sabbath as a day of rest (Ex. 23:12, 20:10). God establishes a covenant
not only with man, but with "every living creature of all
flesh" (Gen. 9:15). And the Bible includes a host of animal cruelty
statutes--only a few of which Scully mentions--that require humane
conduct, such as the prohibition on muzzling an ox while it threshes
(Deut. 2. 5:4). It's not until after the Flood that man is
permitted to eat meat, and even then the practice is surrounded by
regulations that provide for humane treatment and the least painful
slaughter practicable.
It turns out that the Old Testament, despite its granting of
Dominion, takes a rather grim view of hunting. The only people who are
identified as hunters--Nimrod and Esau--are depicted as evil. And Scully
observes that it is Moses's kindness toward a lamb that qualifies
him as a leader: "You who have compassion for a lamb shall now be
the shepherd of My people Israel." The New Testament's
recurrent metaphor of Jesus as the Good Shepherd also points toward the
biblical vision of leadership. The role of the shepherd seems to be what
the God of Genesis has in mind for humankind when He gives us Dominion:
We are to be caretakers and stewards, not ruthless pillagers of nature.
Such a conception does not evade the explicit language of Genesis,
but merely recognizes that our understanding of Dominion in the Bible
has been clouded by more modern ideas. And this is not an understanding
of Dominion that is alien to our experience. Indeed, as others have
noted, the queen of England is said to have "dominion" over
her subjects, but she neither ears them nor hunts them down in game
parks.
Scully, a Christian, expresses some dismay that the New Testament
doesn't have much to say about our duties to animals. "I have
often wished [Jesus] had been more explicit on this score," he
writes, "somewhere along the way encountering a four-footed
equivalent of the woman about to be stoned, fleeing its persecutors,
finding refuge beside him, prompting some saying for the ages about
laying hands off the innocent creature and dealing mercifully with them
all." One notes, however that Scully has left out some inconvenient
verses in scripture, such as Peter's vision in Acts, when he is
shown a procession of animals and hears a heavenly voice exclaim,
"Get up, Peter; kill and ear." It's not exactly the
saying for the ages that Scully hoped for.
Nevertheless, Scully appeals to a solid Christian tradition of
mercy toward animals, which includes Saint Francis of Assisi and C.S.
Lewis, among others. And it is true that if you take seriously the
symbolism of the lamb as the A gnus Dei, you must endure a tremendous
amount of cognitive dissonance in order to tolerate the treatment of
lambs under modern factory farming techniques.
IN A REVIEW of Dominion in the Atlantic Monthly, Christopher
Hitchens charges that the justifications for commercial hunting and
factory farming Scully hears are "the disconcerting sounds of his
own politics being played back to him." But Scully does not agree.
"I find nothing in the conservative moral tradition remotely
resembling this sacrifice of every creature in sight before the almighty
dollar. It is a different spirit entirely," he writes. "It
isn't rooted in conservatism, or Christianity, or Judaism, or
classic capitalism, or any other tradition of honorable origin. It is
much closer to what, in conservative big-think circles, they call
'the modern spirit.'
The animal rights agenda has lately been associated with left-wing
politics, and some conservatives will be inclined to dismiss
Scully's talk about a sense of kinship with the animals as the
sentimental mush of political correctness. Interestingly, however, the
kinship Scully commends leads him naturally to a conservative view of
politics: Scully's ultimate appeal is to the tradition of natural
law." "Every being has a nature, and that nature defines the
ends and ultimate good for which it exists," he writes.
"Suddenly all is not arbitrary and we have a fixed point of
reference, an intelligent basis for calling one thing good and another
bad."
It's the modern left that believes people stand outside and
above nature, peering down on the rest of creation with a godlike power
to manipulate it for our own purposes. Feminists and gender theorists
argue that institutions like marriage and the family--and, indeed,
gender itself--are "social constructs" that can be uprooted
and rearranged through education and social engineering. Karl Marx
advanced a materialist theory of history that ruled out a fixed human
nature; "the human essence is no abstraction inherent in each
single individual," he wrote, "it is the ensemble of the
social relations." And Marx's descendants have gone about the
project of manipulating human nature according to some rational plan for
social harmony.
Throughout these adventures, conservatives have counterpoised a
belief in the permanent truths of human nature to the liberal faith in
the perfectibility of man. Traditionally, this critique was made out of
a religious understanding of man's fallen nature or a philosophic
insight into human character. Increasingly, however, conservatives are
appealing to modern science. In her The War Against Boys: How Misguided
Feminism Is Harming Our Young Men (Simon & Schuste; 2000), Christina
Hoff Sommers appealed to advances in evolutionary biology neuroscience,
and endocrinology to establish, against the gender theorists, that
gender really is hardwired into our biological selves. James Q. Wilson has identified a "natural moral sense" that leads, among other
things, to marriage being a universal characteristic of all human
societies.
Francis Fukuyama explains the failure of Marxism by reference to a
universal human nature: "Marx argued that man is a species-being,
that is, that human beings have altruistic feelings toward the human
species as a whole. The policies and institutions of real-world
communist states--like the abolition of private property, the
subordination of the family to the party-state, and commitment to
universal worker solidarity--were all predicated on this belief."
As we learn from modern kin selection theory, however, Marx's
premise is simply untrue; altruism emerges from the need of individuals
to pass on their genes. And as we know even from common experience, any
political system that denies such moral inclinations as parental care or
familial bonding stands against human nature. Perhaps such a view
explains the relative lack of success of socialist dictatorships
compared to liberal democracy--and economist Paul Rubin, in his
Darwinian Politics: The Evolutionary Origin of Freedom (Rutgers
University Press, 200 2), makes just that claim.
But the idea of human malleability is nowhere more vividly refuted
than in the descriptions of kinship between man and animal contained in
Dominion. Animals form hierarchical social relationships and observe
norms of reciprocity and taboos against incest. Some, like wolves and
quail, form pair bonds (like marriages) that last a lifetime. And
animals, like humans, form special bonds with their kin that involve
special obligations of care. Scully observes that elephant hunters
cannot kill just one member of a herd; "you have to kill them
all," as one hunter put it. This is because of family relationships
within the herd. Orphaned elephant calves, for example, become violent,
asocial juveniles. It doesn't take a great mental leap for humans
to identify with these creatures.
The study of animals, in fact, has had important implications for
understanding human nature. It sounds silly today, but a half-century
ago psychologists discouraged affection between parents and children;
overt displays of love, they argued, could damage a child's
character, making him self-centered and needy. As journalist Deborah
Blum records in her recent Love at Goon Park: Harry Harlow and the
Science of Affection (Perseus, 2002), it was studies of neglected
primates that led to the recognition of what is today conventional
wisdom: Early love and affection improve the child's future health,
social relationships, and even intelligence. Those who insist on an
unbridgeable gap between humanity and nature actually miss something
important about ourselves. "If any person thinks the examination of
the rest of the animal kingdom an unworthy task," Aristotle wrote,
"he must hold in disesteem the study of man."
Aristotle, of course, didn't regard humans and animals as
moral or intellectual equals. For him, humans were political animals,
capable of speech and social activity that nonhuman animals cannot
approach. But he recognized a kinship with them, even if humans are
ultimately a different sort of animal destined for a higher purpose. It
is a more recent thinker, Rene Descartes, whom Scully charges with
callous indifference to the animals. Descartes regarded animals as
unthinking machines and their cries of pain when suffering as nothing
more than the sounds of "broken machinery." Man alone was
capable of consciousness, thought, and self-creation.
Scully wonders why people find it so threatening to human dignity
to regard animals as our fellow creatures, with a dignity (albeit a
lesser one) of their own. But this is not such a mystery.
Descartes's project was for people, through science, to
"render ourselves the masters and possessors of nature." To
acknowledge our ties to animals would be to recognize some power that
constrains human endeavor: nature, or nature's God. That's a
distinctly conservative vision, of course. To be sure, it's not the
only conservative vision (libertarians, for example, have little use for
human nature). But Scully is mostly right when he chastises
conservatives who instinctively write off animal welfare--they are
guilty of the same inconsistent attitudes toward nature that Scully
himself reveals in Dominion.
YET HERE, too, is a cautionary note for the left. Those Marxists
who advocate animal liberation, after all, exhibit the same
inconsistencies. You can't argue that there is no moral difference
between humans and animals and then claim that humans possess a unique
capacity to escape and change their nature - that is quite a moral
difference.
Peter Singer, who has combined liberal politics with animal
advocacy, concedes that his "is a sharply deflated vision of the
Left, its utopian ideas replaced by a coolly realistic view of what can
be achieved." In his A Darwinian Left (Yale University Press,
1999), Singer argues that the left needs to accept that some facts about
human society--gender differences, social hierarchy, attachment to
kin--are rooted in human nature and cannot be altered through the right
social policies. (Strangely, he abandons this principle when, say, he
advocates putting aside our natural parental affection in the case of
infanticide.) Singer writes that the left needs to give up on the
possibility of ending conflict between human beings and must concede
that not all inequalities are the result of discrimination or social
conditioning. A deflated left indeed.
Ultimately, our kinship with animals presents a serious challenge
to egalitarianism. Once it is conceded that there is a hierarchy of
rights or of moral worth in the animal kingdom--a schema of higher and
lesser beings in accordance with their natural capacities--equality
within the human species appears at risk. Egalitarians who advocate
animal rights (save the most radical "pig is a dog is a man is a
boy" types) need to think through the implications of establishing
a biological hierarchy as the basis of our legal rights.
Fukuyama, who identifies nature as the basis of political rights in
his Our Posthuman Future (Farrar, Straus & Giroux, 2002), tries to
square the circle by imbuing each human individual with a mysterious
"Factor x" that is the source of his unique dignity compared
to the rest of the animal kingdom. Fukuyama acknowledges that animals
have rights, based on their more limited capacities, but cautions
against excessive precision in establishing a rights hierarchy. Fukuyama
urges us to focus on "species-typical" behavior, and, barring
the appearance of the Missing Link, this seems both sensible and
practicable--especially as the advance of science and technology
continues to imperil the idea of human equality.
Of course, the best and most distinctive behavior we exhibit is the
political deliberation that led us to egalitarianism in the first place.
Liberal democracy doesn't just work; people actually believe in it.
In a relatively short period--insignificant in evolutionary
time--humanity has traded in despotism for a world in which global
politics is conducted in the language of human rights and equality. We
may exhibit instinctual behavior in our communities and families, but
when we sit down to make our laws no one seriously proposes feudalism or
aristocracy. These ideas have been discredited. We consider ourselves
equal and want to treat others equally. Humans are capable of a
reflection that distinguishes us from the animals, whether it's a
difference in kind or of a very large degree. When we extend our
political concern to animals, we act out of our most honorable instincts
and even form a healthier society. But animals don't demand such
treatment, and wouldn't give it to us if they could.
Steven Menashi is a public affairs fellow at the Hoover Institution
and associate editor of Policy Review.