The Case for Supermajority Rules.
McGinnis, John O. ; Rappaport, Michael B.
THIS CENTURY ENDS, as it began, with extraordinary ferment about
the soundness of our constitutional structures. In a series of recent
decisions, the Supreme Court has appeared to revive doctrines of
federalism and carve out spheres of autonomy for the states. In
Congress, each house gave majority support to serious constitutional
amendments setting term limits, requiring balanced budgets, and limiting
tax increases. In fact, the Balanced Budget Amendment came within one
vote of being sent to the states for ratification. Congress has also
passed rules to restructure the federal legislative process. In an
attempt to promote accountability and protect the autonomy of the
states, both houses have required separate votes on unfunded mandates.
The House of Representatives has passed a rule requiring a three-fifths
majority to raise income tax rates.
Whatever they may signify individually, all these initiatives
reflect a dissatisfaction with the continuing growth of the federal
government. For despite President Clinton's declaration that the
era of big government is over, the national government is as imperial
and imperious as at any time in the nation's history. It spends 17
times the percentage of the nation's income as it did in 1910, and
it takes a greater percentage of citizens' income in taxes than it
has in peacetime ever before. The nature of federal spending has been
transformed as well. Whereas in the early part of this century the
budget focused on public goods, like national defense and
infrastructure, that benefited everyone, today it is largely composed of
transfer payments that enrich some citizens at the expense of the
others. As the federal government has become ever more a dynamo for the
satisfaction of private interests, a government designed for the
energetic pursuit of the public purpose has been transformed into the
special interest state.
Recently, some scholars and other observers have come to believe
that excessive government spending is no longer a problem, because we
now enjoy a surplus. Yet today's favorable fiscal situation, we
submit, is adventitious and temporary. The government surplus is the
result of a vibrant economy, peace, and the full employment of the baby
boom generation, none of which will last forever. Indeed, as the baby
boomers retire during the next 20 years, government spending obligations
will grow tremendously. The most realistic projections (not the
pessimistic ones) predict that by 2020, the cost of Social Security and
government health care programs for the elderly alone will require
payroll taxes approaching 30 percent. This bill coming due makes it all
the more imperative that we focus on our fiscal Constitution right now.
Today is when we should be reconstituting the government to avoid the
upcoming crisis -- not tomorrow, with the crisis already upon us.
Today's bloated federal government is a legacy of
yesterday's enthusiasm for collectivist solutions to social
problems. While the United States suffered less than many other nations
in this century from this worldwide delusion, the fervor for intrusive
social reform -- one directed not only from the left, but also from the
political center -- has left a mark on our original charter. In the
course of the Progressive Era and the New Deal, federalism and the
separation of powers were so effectively weakened that the federal
government came to possess plenary powers of spending and regulation. As
the failures of such federal intervention have become more apparent,
political attention, particularly but not only on the right, has
naturally shifted to recreating an architecture for government that will
discourage such excesses in the future. What we need are constitutive structures that make it easier to apply what we have learned in this
century: to employ market-based and community solutions to social
problems wherever possible and to deploy the heavy hand of the central
authority only as a last resort.
It is our belief that the single best prospect of reconsecrating
the Constitution to individual liberty and the public good would be the
adoption of fiscal supermajority rules. Essentially, what such rules
represent is an attempt to constrain government by requiring more than a
simple majority of legislators to enact a particular category of
legislation. Fiscal supermajority rules, for instance, are already at
the heart of the Balanced Budget Amendment and the tax limitation
proposals: the former requires a three-fifths majority of both the House
and Senate to run a deficit or issue debt, and the latter requires a
two-thirds majority to raise taxes.
The benefits of such a change in the way laws are made are
potentially very large. Supermajority rules for fiscal matters would
increase economic growth by decreasing the burdens the federal
government imposes on citizens. They would help restore civic virtue by
focusing the government on public interest projects rather than on
inherently divisive transfer payments among citizens, thus allowing us
together to address real social problems more energetically and
effectively. Finally, by restraining the reach of the federal
government, they would revive federalism more effectively than will
piecemeal legislation or judicial decisions.
The institutional strength of supermajority rules lies in their
recognition of the limitations of both legislatures and judges. As
history shows, legislatures working under majority rule have
systematically become captive of special interests and thus tax and
spend more than the public interest requires. Judges, on the other hand,
have tended to aggrandize themselves by their willful misreading of text
and precedent. Supermajority rules are an idea for an age skeptical of
all rulers, because they restrain special interests that flourish under
legislative majority rule without providing expansive authority to
judges. They thus provide a better method of creating a framework for a
flourishing polity than a structure that relies either exclusively on
majority rule (as many conservatives, for example, would have us do), or
largely on individual rights (as many libertarians urge).
Some advocates seek to achieve these same goals through other
constitutive reforms, like term limits or campaign finance reform. We
believe that fiscal supermajority rules, however, are more effective at
restraining special interests, because they attack the root cause of
their power -- a government that is inherently inclined to excessive
spending. The very popularity of term limits and campaign finance
reform, however, shows that the burdens of our special interest state
have become so large as to create a wave of popular discontent -- one
that supermajority rules may be able ride to success.
The special interest state
BOTH THEORY AND PRACTICE suggest that the best type of government
is a limited one that provides only those goods and services that cannot
be adequately supplied by the private sector -- that is to say, public
interest goods such as national defense, police, and infrastructure.
Government of this sort both respects individual freedom and
energetically promotes the welfare of the populace.
The hard task is making sure that a limited government remains
limited. A government sufficiently powerful to supply public interest
goods also has enough power to expropriate the property of its citizens.
In the American political tradition, the first mechanism for limiting
the power of government is what the Founders called republicanism and
what we now call democracy: If the people can oust their leaders, this
will restrain the government from abusing its powers.
Yet the American political tradition also demonstrates that
democratic checks, while important, are not sufficient to protect the
people from a distant central government. The Framers of the
Constitution were worried about the power of a majority to abuse even a
democratic government by opting for noxious laws. For their part, the
Antifederalists -- who opposed the Constitution but were responsible for
pressing for the Bill of Rights -- were concerned about the ability of
powerful minorities to secure the passage of injurious legislation. They
feared that a group of wealthy individuals would use the national
government to usurp power and exploit the people.
Today, the greatest danger in our democratic political system
derives from special interests -- groups who wield disproportionate
political power that they can use to obtain private interest benefits
from the government. Special interest groups tend to have certain
characteristics that enable them to succeed in the political process. In
the most common type of special interest group -- think of big business
or big labor -- each member receives a large benefit from the
government. Special interests are therefore willing to incur substantial
costs to operate an organization that will monitor and lobby the
government. Frequently, the members of these groups can also organize on
the cheap, either because they have few members or because they are
already organized (such as the workers in a labor union). By contrast,
most citizens on most issues find it difficult to organize and therefore
exercise little political influence. For example, a consumer spends
relatively little on a typical product and thus does not have incentive
to lobby to prevent the government from raising its price through
tariffs.
One of the strongest special interest groups today, the elderly,
has some of the same features as the most common type of special
interest, but not others. Like big business and big labor, the elderly
receive large amounts of money from the government through Social
Security and Medicare. Although they constitute a large group, and thus
are hard to organize, they make up for their lack of organization with
voting strength. They vote in large numbers, and they tend to vote on
the basis of a candidate's position on Social Security and
Medicare. The power of the elderly helps to explain why Social Security
and Medicare are the third rails of American politics and how they have
grown to encompass so much of the federal budget.
Special interests of all kinds often use their influence to support
government spending increases. Indeed, when special interests act, they
almost always support additional spending rather than less spending and
therefore exert continuing pressure to expand government. Special
interests behave this way by their very nature. While members of special
interests can receive large benefits from spending programs tailored
toward their interests, they benefit much less from opposing spending
than does the average citizen. Spending programs are usually financed by
general tax increases or by government borrowing. If the special
interest successfully opposes spending for another group that is
financed through a general tax increase, it will benefit only by the
small amount of the tax increase that it would have paid. Most of the
benefit will go to the rest of the taxpayers. Similarly, if the special
interest successfully opposes spending that would have been financed by
borrowing, most of the benefit will not go to the special interest, but
to future taxpayers who would have to repay the debt. Rather than
incurring costs opposing spending programs, special interests are better
off attempting to secure programs that specifically benefit them. Mancur
Olson described this phenomenon in his 1965 book, The Logic of
Collective Action.
Unfortunately, from the point of view of the greater good, special
interest groups have increased in strength throughout American history.
When the country was formed, the polity was divided largely between
farmers and merchants. Today, of course, it is vastly more diverse,
consisting of corporate executives, clerical workers, government
bureaucrats, academics, and journalists, to name just a few. As the
number of occupations with distinct interests increases, the number of
interest groups that have incentive to lobby the government for
subsidies grows. Moreover, a stable society like ours inevitably
accumulates special interest organizations. Such organizations may be
hard to form, but once created have staying power. The growing power of
special interests helps explain why total government spending and the
amount of such spending devoted to private interest goods have both
significantly increased. Unless mechanisms can be developed to limit
special interests, they will continue to use their power to grow the
state, enriching themselves at the public's expense and weakening
the government's ability to pursue public purposes.
Undoing constitutional constraints
THE FOUNDERS' GENERATION recognized the need to limit the
powers of government in order to keep it focused on the public good,
rather than on the private interests of either the majority or the
minority. In the original Constitution, the principal means of
restraining government was the system of federalism. Under this system,
the Framers gave the national government only limited powers that were
devoted mainly to national defense and to promoting free trade. The
states, by contrast, were largely free to legislate, but were checked by
competition. If one state passed harmful legislation, it would lose
capital and population to the other states. Moreover, not only the
Supreme Court, but also senators selected by the state legislators
themselves, maintained the limits of the federal government. In the
Senate, the states had a powerful means of constraining both the
Congress and Supreme Court justices (whom the state-controlled Senate
confirmed). Initially, this mechanism worked well on fiscal issues.
After 125 years under the Constitution, the federal government's
spending in 1910 was still only 2 percent of gdp and domestic spending
was only 1 percent. This was quite an accomplishment, since it continued
many decades after the Civil War and the centralization of power
necessary to end slavery and reconstruct the Confederacy.
But the limits on the national government soon began to give way.
The constraints of federalism, in particular, were weakened in two
different ways. First, in 1913, the nation passed two constitutional
amendments that significantly expanded the federal government's
powers. The Sixteenth Amendment eliminated restrictions on
Congress's ability to impose income taxes, thus allowing the
federal government to raise funds without limits. The Seventeenth
Amendment transferred the power of selecting senators from the state
legislatures to the voters; in ratifying this amendment, states removed
the most powerful check they had on the passage of federal legislation.
Second, during the New Deal, the Supreme Court reinterpreted the
Constitution to allow Congress to exercise far broader powers than the
Framers had conferred. Under the new interpretation, Congress had
virtually unlimited authority to pass regulatory and spending programs.
These changes have tremendously increased both the powers of the
federal government and the amount of federal spending. With the
roadblocks from the original Constitution withdrawn and special
interests in the engine room of government, the nation has been moving
steadily along the track of federal spending growth. Nor has our recent
economic prosperity changed all that. Indeed, the percentage of GDP
devoted to domestic spending continues to grow significantly, while the
main reductions in spending have come from defense -- one of the few
areas of federal spending devoted to a public interest good.
We have been fortunate because the baby boomers are still working,
there is peace, and the nation is enjoying the benefits of the computer
and telecommunications revolutions. But this is the calm before the
storm. Unless substantial changes are made, first Medicare and then
Social Security will run out of money, forcing the government to pass
huge tax increases or to run enormous deficits. It is a sign of the
power of those interests, however, that the nation is not even taking
moderate measures to deal with these problems. Consider only what our
recent fiscal politics shows -- that the government finds it difficult
to cut taxes, even though the country is now paying a greater percentage
of national income in taxes than at any time since World War II.
Proposals to save Medicare from bankruptcy have failed miserably, while
the administration's plan to expand the program to people in their
50s receives attention.
The clearest indication of special interest power has been the
Congress's sad inability to live within the statutory limits it has
set for discretionary spending -- the money the government spends
outside the area of entitlements like Social Security and Medicare. Here
Congress continues to behave like an alcoholic who swears that the drink
he is about to have will be his last. Congress regularly enacts spending
limits, then chooses to violate these limits as it enacts a new spending
cap that it pledges to follow in the future. In the 1980s, Congress
sought to restrain spending and deficits through the Gramm- Rudman law.
In 1990, Congress violated this limit, but made sure to pass a new
spending restraint that it claimed would be more effective in the
future. In 1997, however, Congress transgressed this limit, but not
without once again solemnly pledging to respect new spending caps.
In the past few years, Congress has accelerated its pattern of
spending breaches, playing fast and loose with the limits each year. In
1998, it was able to avoid enacting new spending caps, but only by
exploiting a loophole for emergency spending, intended for unexpected
occurrences. Congress cynically treated the y2k computer problem as an
unpredictable emergency, although it had certainly been aware of the
issue when it enacted the caps the previous year. This year the
legislature appears to be outdoing itself. It has contemplated using the
emergency spending exception to fund, of all things, the 2000 census --
an event so unpredictable that the Constitution just happens to mention
it! Congress has also considered placing other items, such as airport
funding, off budget, as if an accounting device could erase the true
costs of government spending. Finally, even with such spending gimmicks
both the speaker and the Senate majority leader have announced that they
intend to exceed the statutory spending caps yet again.
The Republican Congress, however, looks like a model of fiscal
restraint when compared to the spending programs advocated by the
Democratic presidential candidates. Vice President Gore and Sen. Bradley
are trying to outdo each other with expensive ideas for spending the
taxpayers' money. Even the New York Times has recently estimated
that their proposals, if enacted, would not only exceed the budget caps,
but wipe out the entire Social Security surplus.
Supermajority rules and how they work
THE FIRST VIRTUE of fiscal supermajority rules can be simply
stated: By increasing the percentage of legislators needed to pass
additional spending, debt, or taxes, supermajority rules reduce the
amount of such legislation. The second virtue is also important: By
requiring a larger majority to pass laws, fiscal supermajority rules
help to filter out inefficient programs. This filtering effect follows
from the intuitive idea that good legislation is generally able to get
more votes than bad, so that supermajority rules will block the
enactment of a higher percentage of bad laws than of good laws. Our own
Constitution makes such an assumption: If legislation passing with a
supermajority is no better on average than legislation passing with a
mere majority, there would have been no reason to require a
supermajority of Congress and the states to amend the Constitution.
Thus, a well-designed supermajority rule should create a government
that is both smaller and more focused on the public interest. Consider
as an example perhaps the simplest of all supermajority rules -- one
that requires a supermajority (say two-thirds) for any new spending.
This rule certainly would have the advantageous effect of reducing the
amount of government spending. Even if it reduced both good and bad
spending equally, the rule would still be beneficial if most federal
government spending is currently ill-conceived -- a plausible enough
assumption to anyone familiar with the waste in our government programs.
Yet a supermajority rule would also filter out bad spending, while
preserving the good. Voters evaluate spending bills in some measure by
whether bills provide them with net benefits. A bill with more net
benefits is, on average, more popular than a bill with lower net
benefits or negative benefits. For instance, the spending required to
defend the United States from invasion offers huge net benefits and
would be easily passed under any supermajority rule. In contrast, a bill
that transferred money to a small group would have fewer supporters.
Thus, a supermajority rule that filters could improve government
spending on balance, even if the time comes when most federal spending
is well-conceived.
In fact, such a supermajority rule may mimic the workings of
majority rule in an idealized version of democracy -- one with majority
rule and with no special interests. As we have noted, special interests
systematically favor spending and have substantial leverage over
legislators. Thus, in the real world, the legislature operates as if
special interests control pocket boroughs and additional votes in the
legislature. By creating a higher hurdle for spending, the legislature
will pass only spending favored by an actual majority of voters. In our
imperfect world such spending programs would generally obtain
supermajorities of legislators, consisting both of the majority
sustained by regular voters and the pocket boroughs of special
interests.
A fiscal supermajority rule creates a third structure of governance
-- one that combines the advantages of majority rule and absolute
limitations on government, such as the Bill of Rights and the
protections of federalism. Like majority rule, supermajority rule
ultimately permits government decisions to be made by popular consensus.
If a spending program is truly popular, the judiciary cannot stop it.
Moreover, because Congress ultimately passes on the wisdom of
legislation, judges are not subject to societal pressure to abrogate supermajority rules in times of crisis, as they did to many
constitutional limitations during the New Deal. The supermajority
limitations bend in the face of popular passions so that they do not
break.
On the other hand, supermajority rules are like absolute
limitations that shape the political process to prevent its distortion
by special interests. Thus, like federalism or individual rights,
supermajority rules can help protect our basic liberties -- in this case
our right to keep what we earn free from the overreaching of government.
As a result, supermajority rules encourage economic growth and
discourage wasteful and divisive attempts by private interests to use
government to obtain transfer payments for themselves.
The comparison of supermajority rules with absolute limitations
shows that supermajority rules are wholly consistent with the tenets of
American democracy. The existence of constitutional provisions
protecting individual rights and federalism show that throughout
American history popular majorities have always perfected democracy by
placing constraints on national legislative majorities. Indeed,
supermajority rules thwart majority decisionmaking far less than
absolute limitations like individual rights because supermajority rules
ultimately entrust government decisions to the representatives of the
people, not to judges.
How to draft the best rules
WE NEED TO DRAFT supermajority rules carefully to get the optimal
benefits of restraining the legislature while minimizing the complexity
of the function they assign to the judiciary. This will necessarily
involve tradeoffs between these two objectives. Because all rules must
be enforced by fallible institutions, any sensible constitutional
provision seeks to reduce the combined costs of institutional failure of
both the legislatures and the courts, not just one or the other.
For instance, the rule with which we illustrated the benefits of
supermajority rules -- a two-thirds requirement for any spending bill -
- has the virtue of simplicity. Spending is a relatively easy concept to
define: Under cost accounting, a government expenditure is the amount
that is actually transferred from the government to a party outside the
government. Applying this simple rule to all spending circumscribes
judicial discretion, because little room for dispute exists in its
application.
Unfortunately, this simple rule permits strategic behavior by
legislators and interest groups. By holding out against passage of an
important spending bill, like one that funds the treasury or justice
system, legislators who want more spending can threaten a government
shutdown. As we witnessed in 1995, President Clinton used the threat of
government shutdown to obtain increased spending from the Republican
Congress.
The power of holdouts can be reduced by establishing two kinds of
supermajority rules. First, a supermajority could be required to pass
any spending bill that constituted a new entitlement. Since citizens do
not count on receiving an entitlement that has not yet been enacted, the
creation of novel benefits is much less vulnerable to holdouts. On the
other hand, because existing entitlements run on automatic pilot, they
create a very substantial risk of excessive spending, as Social Security
and Medicare show. It is therefore imperative that a decision that can
so dramatically affect the economic future not only of the living but of
those yet unborn have the support of a very broad social consensus.
Second, the total amount of so-called discretionary spending -- the
kind that keeps the government running -- should also be made subject to
a slightly more complicated supermajority rule. If Congress were to
spend more than a certain percentage, say 90 percent, of what it spent
in the previous year, it should have to enact this overall total
spending level by a two-thirds vote. Holdouts would have less leverage
under this rule, because if they threaten to shut down the government, a
majority could prevent its closure by authorizing 90 percent of the
previous year's expenditures.
To restrain the legislature more effectively, these supermajority
rules introduce slightly more complicated concepts for the judiciary to
interpret. For instance, the judiciary has to decide whether spending is
an entitlement. Yet this is a manageable determination, since
"entitlements" can be defined as all spending not subject to
the yearly appropriations process. Certainly, this is a less open-ended
kind of judgment than that routinely made by the judiciary in deciding
what constitutes "equal protection of the law" or "the
freedom of speech." The judiciary would also have to decide what
constitutes 90 percent of last year's spending. But there is little
chance that this question will be decided mistakenly or improperly,
because the amount of expenditures is so clearly defined and because
Congress will almost always spend more than the 90 percent of what it
spent the previous year, thereby avoiding the need for the court to make
a close calculation. Another way of reducing judicial power over this
fiscal calculation would be to make the president the initial monitor of
congressional compliance by giving him the responsibility of
sequestering funds spent in violation of the rule.
Focusing on supermajority rules as a way of optimizing restraints
on both the legislature and the judiciary helps us evaluate the Balanced
Budget Amendment and the Tax Limitation Amendment -- the principal
supermajority rules that Congress has actually proposed. First, these
amendments would constrain legislative spending far more effectively if
they were passed together. If only one of these methods for funding
special interest spending were restrained, then we would expect Congress
to circumvent that restraint simply by using the other method.
Second, even if supermajority rules were applied to both taxes and
debt, these particular sorts of rules would contain more complex
concepts than would supermajority rules on spending. Debt is harder to
define than spending, as corporate finance shows. State experience with
balanced budget provisions also indicates that judges sometimes
manipulate the concept to permit legislatures to borrow money.
Tax increases are also not as easy to define, at least in a way
that encourages the government to choose the optimal kind of tax. For
instance, there are problems with applying a supermajority rule to all
laws that increase revenues. Certainly supermajority rules should cover
increases in tax rates because they can be diffused over the general
public and thus are the perfect support for special interest spending.
But there are laws that increase revenues, such as eliminating tax
preferences, that should not be discouraged by supermajority rules,
because special interests devise tax preferences to get additional
resources for themselves.
One major advantage of applying supermajority rules to taxes and
debt cannot be ignored. Such a constitutional amendment would probably
be easier to enact than one applied to spending. Citizens simply resent
increased taxes and debt more than they do excessive spending, because
spending, unlike taxes or debt, can be more easily presented as a
benefit to someone. Of course, it is an easy step to show that excessive
spending requires either excessive taxes or excessive debt or both, but
in politics even a two-step argument is often one step too many for
success.
No matter what supermajority rule is chosen, special interests will
not disappear. They can be expected to try to circumvent the
supermajority rule by finding other kinds of legislation that will
benefit them. For instance, legislation that would require, say,
supermarkets to give special low rates to the elderly would benefit a
group of individuals at the expense of the public, but would not be
subject to a supermajority rule on spending, debt, or taxes.
Nevertheless, we would expect such substitution to be imperfect. The
success of special interests lies in their ability to diffuse the costs
of their program on the public through general taxes. Regulatory
legislation, by contrast, often imposes costs on concentrated groups
that can be expected to organize effective lobbies against it. Thus, in
our imagined example, supermarkets could be expected to battle the
regulatory transfer.
Since special interests could not easily substitute bad regulations
for excessive spending, taxes, or debt, supermajority rules applied to
these fiscal matters would reduce the overall level of special interest
extractions from the federal government. Of course, we recognize that
over time special interests may find ways to weaken the restraints of
fiscal supermajority rules as well. But no constitutional settlement can
ever be permanent. Even if supermajority rules restrain government
spending for only 50 years -- a third of the time in which the
Constitution's original structure of enumerated powers held sway --
fully two generations once again will enjoy the benefits of a government
more focused on the public interest.
Rules for compassionate conservatism
FISCAL SUPERMAJORITY RULES are multipurpose tools. Besides leading
to more efficient spending, these rules also advance important social
objectives. Fiscal supermajority rules can create a less divided polity
and help to focus citizens on common goals. They can also promote
private charitable organizations, individual freedom, and federalism.
At present, special interests regularly use the state to acquire
private interest goods for themselves at public expense. Farmers secure
agricultural subsidies, the elderly obtain generous government pensions,
and large businesses get corporate welfare. In this political world, it
is natural for each citizen to regard his fellow citizens as either
sources of wealth he can seize or as threats to commandeer his property.
Our political regime thus generates suspicion and division as citizens
are pitted against one another in a litany of spending decisions that
benefit some at the expense of others.
Fiscal supermajority rules, by contrast, would help change
people's sentiments about politics. Supermajority rules make it
harder to pass laws that simply transfer funds from one group to
another. Such laws generate opposition, and obtaining the requisite
numbers for passage would become more difficult. Instead, supermajority
rules tend to favor laws that appeal to a wide range of interests and
therefore are popular enough to secure passage. As a result, citizens
will feel more secure that their wealth is not being seized for private
purposes and that the government is attempting to promote the interests
of all. Supermajority rules will also give politicians and citizens an
incentive to consider the goals and interests their fellow citizens have
in common, because only this strategy will allow them to formulate a
legislative agenda that can pass.
Besides making politics focus more on the common goals of citizens,
fiscal supermajority rules would also promote the development of private
associations devoted to benefiting other citizens. Writing in the early
part of the nineteenth century when government was small, Alexis de
Tocqueville observed that America was a nation of individuals who formed
charities, churches, and societies for all sorts of collective goods.
Unfortunately, the large government produced by the modern special
interest state has tended to crowd out many of these private
associations. Because citizens now see government as the primary vehicle
to address social issues, they are less motivated to organize privately
to tackle them. Moreover, the higher taxes needed to fund big government
deprive citizens of resources that could be used to create and sustain
civic associations. In contrast, by establishing a civic world in which
private citizens have more responsibility and more resources for solving
social problems, supermajority rules have the potential to reinvigorate private associations and thereby create a social fabric richer in mutual
aid and trust. If "compassionate conservatism" aims to refocus government on public purposes and to unleash the forces of beneficence for the poor and afflicted, supermajority rules should be seen as its
signature constitutional structure.
Thus, we completely reject any contention of liberal Democrats that
fiscal supermajority rules would injure the poor. Supermajority rules
restrain special interests, but the poor are unlikely to form into an
effective special interest group. The poor are a diffuse group and have
few resources to spend becoming organized. Moreover, they can offer only
their votes and not campaign contributions or other material resources
useful to politicians. Therefore it should not be surprising that
excessive public spending does not flow to the poor. Instead, we observe
that the federal transfer programs that comprise much of the federal
budget are aimed at the aging middle class. The taxes that support such
entitlements in fact harm the poor significantly because the poor are
more likely than the average citizen to have used the money paid in
taxes for the necessities of life.
Fiscal supermajority rules also foster individual freedom. The
excessive government spending under existing legislative rules deprives
people of resources to spend on enterprises and projects of their
choosing. Additional government spending also produces a larger and more
powerful bureaucratic state, which has more opportunity arbitrarily to
infringe on freedom. Supermajority rules would reduce the size and
intrusiveness of government, allowing individuals a greater measure of
autonomy.
Finally, fiscal supermajority rules would promote federalism. By
making it more difficult for Congress to pass legislation, these rules
would limit the federal government and help preserve the authority of
the states to take actions without congressional interference. Moreover,
because supermajority rules filter out bad legislation, they would tend
disproportionately to block federal laws in areas where the states
legislate well but to allow federal laws in areas where national
legislation is needed. Thus, supermajority rules would obstruct federal
spending on agricultural subsidies, while not interfering with necessary
spending on national defense. Supermajority rules are also superior to
the traditional system of enumerated powers in promoting federalism,
because supermajority rules do not rely primarily on judicial
enforcement.
Thus, supermajority rules -- even ones devoted to fiscal matters --
are not simply about economics. Fiscal supermajority rules would promote
social harmony, civic associations, freedom, and local decisionmaking -
- important social and moral objectives that help sustain a rich civic
life in a well-functioning polity.
A new charter of liberty
IN OUR OPINION, supermajority rules can command widespread support
in the coming years. As noted, the supermajority rules in the Balanced
Budget Amendment and the Tax Limitation Amendment gained many votes in
Congress. Even more telling is the almost universal desire to achieve a
principal goal of fiscal supermajority rules -- the reduction of the
power of special interests. The popularity of term limits and campaign
finance reform, for instance, largely derives from the promise of these
proposals to take government away from the special interests and give it
back to the people.
Fiscal supermajority rules, however, accomplish this objective
better than campaign finance reform or term limits. Supermajority rules
attack the chief cause of the special interest state -- the dissolution
of limitations on government spending authority. In contrast, term
limitation or campaign finance reform each curtails only one means by
which special interests exercise disproportionate influence -- either
through peculiar influence with entrenched legislators or through
greater campaign contributions.
It might be thought that a supermajority rule cannot be enacted,
because special interests will use their power to oppose it in an effort
to protect their subsidies. Although special interests would certainly
oppose reductions in their benefits under existing fiscal arrangements,
supermajority rules have the advantage of disarming all special
interests simultaneously. They thus offer a promising solution to the
prisoners' dilemma that afflicts our politics: Although we would
all be better off with a smaller government, it would be irrational for
the members of any special interest to surrender their benefits unless
they can be sure that other groups will too. Under a fiscal
supermajority rule applying to all spending, the benefits to a special
interest group from less spending on other special interests might be
larger than the reduction in its subsidies.
Edmund Burke defended the Glorious Revolution on grounds that even
revolution can be necessary to "preserve . . . that ancient
Constitution of government which is our only security for law and
liberty." He cautioned that the resulting reformation should
proceed "upon the principle of reference to antiquity" and
thus be "carefully formed upon analogical precedent, authority, and
example" of prior law.
Fiscal supermajority rules are the kind of innovation Burke
celebrated. We now need them to perform a task analogous to that
undertaken by structures of the original Constitution that have fallen
into disrepair. Like the original system of enumerated powers,
constitutional supermajority rules would inhibit the government from
producing private interest goods and instead concentrate its energies on
the public good. They would accomplish this goal without giving
excessive power to judges or other nondemocratic institutions. They
would thus help achieve what Madison defined as the principal goal of a
constitution: "To secure the public good, and private rights,
against the danger of . . . faction, and at the same time preserve the
spirit and form of popular government." Supermajority rules can
provide, in short, a new charter of freedom for those who would rule
themselves.