Toward a realist ethics of intervention.
Wesley, Michael
Most considerations of the ethics of intervention in international
relations attempt to reconcile within a common moral framework claims of
humanitarian obligation, sovereign rights, international order, and the
just use of coercive force. (1) The obvious normative intent of much of
this writing is to contribute to the establishment of a compelling case
for the provision of assistance, often in the face of physical
resistance and legal objections, to humans who are suffering. Yet a
survey of the incidence and progress of force-backed interventions over
the past decade would suggest that the efforts of these scholars and
jurists have had little traction either within most foreign ministries
or on the ground among populations subject to humanitarian concern.
Convincing moral cases for a general obligation to intervene have had
little effect on the rising tide of postintervention peace-building
fatigue that has resulted from ongoing obligations to ensure stability
after various interventions. Regimes in Pyongyang, Moscow, Beijing,
Tehran, and Harare have likewise been unmoved by powerful moral-legal
arguments about sovereignty being conditional on a government's
respect for the well-being of its citizens (2)--as has the UN Security
Council. And as postconflict peacekeepers in Bosnia, Kosovo,
Afghanistan, and Iraq remain powerless to resolve deep communal hatreds,
gratitude for the initial interventions among local populations has
begun to ebb away. Despite the euphoric claims made about the new moral
framework for humanitarian intervention after NATO's Operation
Allied Force in Kosovo, considerations of interest, viability, and
partiality continue to drive the pattern of interventions.
If ethical inquiry about intervention is to have practical impact,
it must range further than purely conceptual discussions of obligations,
rights, order, and just war. It must, in short, learn from realism,
taking into account considerations that resonate within foreign
ministries and on the ground in societies in distress. My intention in
this article is to approach the ethics of humanitarian intervention from
a more empirical standpoint by presenting a history of humanitarian
intervention as a process of evolution through successive stages
featuring different dominant rationales and forms. I argue that
humanitarian intervention should be discussed in a broader and different
historical context than is typical. This context is the rise of
developed states' concerns about the domestic institutions and
practices of developing states after the 1970s. This "new"
interventionism--different from traditional interventionism that was
based primarily on considerations of strategic advantage (3)--raised to
new prominence in international relations a set of ethical issues
concerning political community and obligation. (4) The forces driving
the evolution of humanitarian intervention through successive dominant
forms have been the internal normative contradictions of each stage and
the persistence of concerns about the internal workings of postcolonial,
and, later, post-communist states.
My empirical-historical approach to the ethics of humanitarian
intervention leads to a conviction that a different set of moral issues,
informed by realist considerations, needs to be addressed in creating an
effective normative framework for intervention. After outlining this
alternative set of moral issues in the next section, I use the following
four sections to demonstrate that each "phase" of humanitarian
intervention--which I term economic, political, human rights, and
governance interventionism--has suffered from an inability to reconcile
these normative issues in a way that directly impacts on
interventions' effectiveness. In the conclusion I suggest that the
current phase of concern with transnational security, if powerful enough
to drive a general realignment of conceptions of interests and
obligations, presents us with the best chance to construct a common
normative framework under-girding humanitarian interventions.
REALIST ETHICS AND INTERVENTION
Many understand realism to be either amoral or immoral, the favored
position of those wishing to deny the relevance of normative frameworks.
This popular conception relies on a caricature, which at times has been
used by realists themselves for dramatic effect. Realism's approach
to ethics derives from a philosophical tradition that has long discussed
the relationship between ethical frameworks and effective political
action and association. Thomas Hobbes and David Hume sought to
demonstrate why rational individuals living in political society had an
interest in acting in accordance with moral rules. (5) In arguing that
effective political action often requires acting outside of the
conventions of common morality, Niccolo Machiavelli nevertheless
affirmed the existence and importance of shared systems of motivation
and justification--whether "moral" or
"political"--between peoples and those ruling them. (6) More
recently, participants in the debate over what Michael Walzer termed
"the problem of dirty hands" have argued that even politically
justified but morally dubious actions carry a "moral residue"
demanding that their authors feel guilt and atone for these acts. (7)
Realism takes from this tradition of inquiry an acknowledgment that
effective political action is best pursued within a common moral
community. In the absence of such a common moral community, the utility
of force rises and that of ethical appeal declines, while what can be
achieved by politics alone becomes much more limited. (8) The tradition
of Carl Schmitt, transmitted through Hans Morgenthau, saw the existence
of bounded moral communities among which competition reigned as the
essence of the realm of the political. (9) It is a consequence of the
division of humanity into bounded moral communities that they will
contend for necessarily limited and rival goods. The essence of realist
ethics is that political leaders have an overriding moral obligation to
advance the interests of their own, bounded moral communities against
the interests of other moral communities. And, of course, this moral
obligation is reinforced by the logic of political representation within
states. So the basic component of any realist ethics must be the
consideration of the motivation for political action, based on a
government's obligations to protect and advance the interests of
its own constituents.
For realists, to propose that a government should act in accord
with general moral interests rather than state interests is to propose
an absurdity, a diplomatic counterpart to Prince Myshkin in
Dostoyevsky's The Idiot. Even states that proclaim an
"ethical" foreign policy rarely stray far from the dictates of
self-interest. But this is not to endorse the caricature of realism:
that extreme immorality brings the greatest rewards in international
relations. Careful realists have always recognized that the
"id" of state self-interest must conform to a
"superego" of general normative principles of state behavior
in order for the state to function effectively and avoid destruction.
(10) Particularly in the postwar era, states have become increasingly
sensitive to perceptions of the legitimacy of their actions, (11) and
commentators have attempted to demonstrate the folly of state actions
that pay little attention to international perceptions. (12) Foreign
policy actions that are rhetorically justified according to a structure
of normative principles shared by all those affected by the action will
be less costly and more enduring. So a second component of a realist
ethical framework must be the consideration of the justification for an
action, or whether it is seen to be legitimate to all those affected by
it.
In addition to considerations of interest and legitimacy, states
are also highly attentive to the principles of international order.
Proposals and principles deemed too corrosive to the ongoing viability
of a stable international society have generally remained just
that--proposals and principles. (13) It is in relation to this
consideration that many of the inquiries into the ethics of intervention
have occurred. (14) For realists, the principles of international order
serve as an overarching normative structure that is vital to both the
motivation and justification for foreign policy actions. (15)
International order principles function as the framework within which
state actions occur, and are added to and reinforced by state actions.
Realists see the principles of international order as necessarily
evolving and as generally compatible with viable and effective political
outcomes, while independently valid of particular exigencies. So the
third component of a realist ethical framework must be its validity in
terms of the general principles of international order.
A realist system of ethics determines that just actions in
international relations must align these three principles: motivation
according to states' interests, justification in terms of
principles of legitimate action, and validity by reference to the
principles of international order. The 1991 Gulf War is often hailed as
such an occasion. (16) Humanitarian interventions, because they seek a
lasting transformation of the domestic practices of other societies,
need to be especially attentive to aligning these realist ethical
principles. Interventions motivated by general moral justifications or
conceptual appeals to the validity of international order will either
fail to occur or will succumb to halfhearted commitments (as the cases
of Rwanda and Somalia showed). Interventions based on self-interested
motivation alone (as some argued was the case with the 2003 invasion of
Iraq), will strike resistance on the ground and incur great costs in
morale, materiel, and diplomatic capital.
I define "humanitarian" intervention as the provision of
prescriptive advice about, or the direct manipulation of, a state's
domestic processes and institutions of government, backed by the threat
or use of coercive measures or conditions on assistance, by external
states or international agencies. This distinguishes broadly
"humanitarian" interventions--those professing concern for the
people of the state in question from earlier forms of great-power
interventions concerned with the adjustment or tending of spheres of
influence or balances of power. Humanitarian intervention, because it
seeks to accomplish a lasting change in another jurisdiction, relies
implicitly on a common normative framework simultaneously reconciling
the motivations of the intervening states, the justifications provided
to the society subject to intervention, and general understandings of
international order and acceptable state conduct. The following sections
demonstrate that the four phases of humanitarian intervention since the
1970s have lacked such a framework, which contributed directly to their
poor rates of success.
ECONOMIC INTERVENTIONISM
The rise of humanitarian interventionism in the 1970s needs to be
seen against the historical context of decolonization and postcolonial
politics in international relations. As colonies graduated to statehood,
the metropolitan powers accepted that the new states would be
constituted on the basis of what Robert Jackson calls "negative
sovereignty"--that is, the international assurance of their
juridical existence and status. The exclusive focus on the international
form of these new states led the former colonial powers to ignore
questions of "positive sovereignty"--that is, whether new
states possessed sufficient internal control and resources to form
viable states. (17) Negative sovereignty, postcolonial sensitivities,
and Cold War geopolitics coincided to produce a disinclination on the
part of Western states to criticize or even examine too closely the
domestic affairs of postcolonial states. (18) Between the developed and
the developing worlds, the ambit of moral evaluation and judgment
narrowed significantly, as the remit of tolerance, agnosticism, and
negative comity widened. (19) Where established and new states were
compared explicitly was over broad disparities in economic development,
and to a lesser extent in political maturity. Developing states were
able to tie their underdevelopment to colonialism and the unfair
structure of the global economy in a way that conferred an obligation on
the developed world to provide them with development assistance.
Meanwhile, in developed nations, particularly the United States, the
ascendancy of "modernization theory" assumed that the progress
of economic development and political maturity in the developing world
were inevitable given the requisite aid and advice, and would unfold
along predictable, well-trodden trajectories.
While developed states generally accepted the obligation to assist
postcolonial states economically through aid and advice, it was an
obligation never taken particularly seriously. Levels of aid provided by
most states have never even approached the 0.7 percent of GNP suggested
as a basic level of obligation, while many wealthy countries have
manipulated their aid transfers to secure benefits for national
economies and producers. (20) The providers of economic assistance were,
in the early postwar decades, wary of intervening too closely in
determining how developing states would use the aid payments. A
comparison that is rarely made in this context is with U.S. Marshall
Plan in Europe, which saw large aid transfers accompanied by extensive
involvement by the U.S. government and civil society organizations in
the restructuring and rebuilding of war-torn European societies. The
presumption of the Marshall Plan was that economic development required
deep and ongoing commitment on the part of donors to the domestic
governance of the recipient states. (21) In the case of development aid
to the developing world, the provision of technical advice was left
largely to the UN, the World Bank, and the regional development banks.
(22)
Two issues arose in the early 1980s to unsettle the West's
relative neglect: the "Third World" debt crisis and the aid
paradox. Many developing countries' spiraling indebtedness and
worsening economic performance despite decades of aid and assistance
focused attention on their domestic economic structures. The aid paradox
both raised the concern of developed state governments about the use of
aid money and tempered feelings of sympathy for developing countries.
The focus of blame for underdevelopment shifted from disadvantages
arising from the unfair structure of the global economy--for example,
the harms of colonization and underdevelopment imposed by economic
"dependency"--to inadequacies in economic management.
Following the postwar ascendancy of state-led development strategies,
which had emphasized the problem of market failures that needed to be
corrected through state interventions, (23) developing states'
internal economic policies and institutions came under close scrutiny.
The lack of development in many states, despite decades of aid payments,
led to mounting concern about developing states' economic
management capacities, particularly concentrating on state intervention
in the economy, corruption, and distributional inefficiencies. The
rising tide of neoliberal economic doctrine was soon applied to
development economics as the development banks, the IMF, and individual
states began advocating a mixture of macrostability, liberalization, and
privatization for the domestic economic policy of developing states.
(24)
The neoliberal economic interventionism that arose in the 1980s was
enforced mainly through conditionality: the practice of attaching
conditions of policy behavior to economic assistance from the major
development banks. But the arm's-length nature of this new economic
interventionism betrayed the weakness of developed states'
motivations to address effectively underdevelopment in the developing
world. Developing states that had become reliant on external financial
assistance often had little option but to accept the conditionality of
the new aid. Neoliberal economic doctrine was also injected into
developing countries through the dispatch of advisors from the
development banks and through the training of economists from developing
countries in Western universities, where many economics departments had
succumbed to the neoliberal economic revolution.
A recent study has revealed a very mixed rate of success for the
958 "structural adjustment programs" that were implemented in
developing countries between 1980 and 1998 by the Bretton Woods institutions. (25) Francis Fukuyama has recently observed that
neoliberal interventions in many countries had an adverse impact on
their capacity to develop the economic and other attributes of positive
sovereignty, writing:
The relative emphasis in this period lay very
heavily on the reduction of state activity, which
could often be confused or deliberately misconstrued
as an effort to cut back state capacity
across the board.... The result was that liberalizing
economic reform failed to deliver on its
promise in many countries. In some countries,
indeed, absence of a proper institutional framework
left them worse off after liberalization than
they would have been in its absence. (26)
Developed countries' general concern with economic governance
was an insufficient motivation to drive their comprehensive engagement
with the diverse problems of underdevelopment in the developing world,
leading to low rates of success for economic interventionism.
Despite such damning critiques, the urgency of economic
interventionism increased in the late 1990s. New reasons arose for
attention to economic governance, which were related to concerns about
the transnational effects of economic weakness. The Asian financial
crisis caused many, such as former IMF managing director Michel
Camdessus, to see developing countries' domestic economic policies
and institutions as dangerous to regional and global financial
stability:
Crises can now become systemic through contagion.
Domestic economic policy must take
into account its potential worldwide impact; a
duty of universal responsibility is incumbent,
making each country responsible for the stability
and quality of world growth. (27)
Many commentators argue that the IMF and the development banks have
made marginal modifications to their economic intervention strategies,
while continuing to push the neoliberal "Washington consen
sus" agenda on developing countries. (28) Economic interventionism
failed to allay nagging concerns in the developed world about shortfalls
in developing states' positive sovereignty. By the beginning of the
1990s, this led to the rise of a new form of interventionism, complete
with its own motivations, justifications, and validity claims, but
ultimately, also, flawed.
POLITICAL INTERVENTIONISM
For most of the postwar period, Western states have been little
concerned about the domestic political makeup of postcolonial states, in
terms of the presence or absence of functioning democracies.
Interventions occurred when, irrespective of the presence or absence of
democracy, it appeared that a state was changing its foreign policy, and
drifting from one Cold War bloc to another. (29) Indeed, Western states
intervened on several occasions in the developing world when it appeared
that a democratically elected government was adopting a more independent
or pro-Soviet stance. (30) During the Cold War, the presence or absence
of democracy was thought to be irrelevant in determining how developing
states should be dealt with. The Reagan administration's ambassador
to the UN, Jeane Kirkpatrick, had argued that there was no dilemma for
the United States in befriending dictators in noncommunist countries
because they were more likely eventually to become democracies. (31)
This lack of concern with regime type began to change by the
mid-1980s, as the Reagan administration faced the prospect of losing the
United States' strategic bases in the Philippines to the
"people power" protests shaking the Marcos dictatorship.
Washington's sudden withdrawal of support for Ferdinand Marcos and
backing of Corazon Aquino saw the rise of a powerful conservative
constituency convinced that democratization should be a central plank in
U.S. foreign policy. (32) From that point, elements on both the Left and
Right of politics in the United States provided strong adherence to what
Walter Russell Mead calls the "Wilsonian" tradition of foreign
policy, which seeks to export democracy to undemocratic states. (33) The
strategic case for democratization had long been made by
"democratic peace" scholars, who argued that democratic states
were less likely to fight each other and more likely to subscribe to international norms. (34) The end of the Cold War provided further
impetus to the democratization lobby, by demonstrating that some
authoritarian regimes were vulnerable to popular demands for political
freedoms and democratic rights. The use of American symbols of democracy
by the Tiananmen protesters in China showed that the U.S. democratic
example was a powerful motivating force. And when Iraq invaded Kuwait in
August 1990, Saddam Hussein was immediately portrayed as an aggressive
Hitler-style dictator, with the implication that authoritarian regimes
were by their very nature a threat to international peace and security.
Democratization advocates had found a new rationale for
intervention: that a government's clearly enunciated support for
democracy and anti-authoritarianism would lead to long-term strategic
advantages. The appeal to the political liberties of subject peoples
provided ample justification, though not to authoritarian governments
and their supporters. The problem occurred when there were overriding
short-term strategic interests in favoring the status quo in various
authoritarian states.
Commentators began making the case that democratization should
become the focus of U.S. foreign policy after the end of the Cold War
had deprived it of a central driving focus. (35) Fukuyama's widely
read "end of history" thesis made the case that the progress
of liberal democracy was inevitable; thus, in advocating
democratization, it was argued that American foreign policy would be
pushing at an opening door. (36) By September 1993, Anthony Lake, the
national security adviser in the first Clinton administration, had given
U.S. government endorsement to the focus on democratization:
Throughout the Cold War we contained a
global threat to market democracies; now we
should seek to enlarge their reach, particularly
in places of special significance to us ... we
should help foster and consolidate new democracies
... especially in states of special significance. (37)
Democratization was seen not only as being in the interests of
those who lived in autocracies, but also as a positive development for
global stability, because it promised to reduce the number of dictators,
who were seen as less trustworthy international partners and less
inclined to respect international norms. In this, European states had a
longer democratization tradition than the United States in their
insistence that only democracies would be eligible for membership in the
European Community.
This democratic political interventionism relied on certain
assumptions about human aspirations and motivations. Democratization
advocates assume that all humans possess a common drive toward free
expression and entrepreneurialism, and that it is pathologies that arise
within the domestic politics or societies of states that prevent these
human qualities from flourishing. (38) This gives rise to further
assumptions about the desirability, inevitability, and linearity of
democratization, once these state-imposed impediments and pathologies
are removed. (39) As Charles Call and Susan Cook have argued,
"Despite protests to the contrary, democratization theory suffers
from some of the flaws of modernization theory, including its tendency
to view the West's experience as both a normative yardstick and an
empirical expectation." (40)
The mechanisms of political intervention have been varied, and they
are tied to diagnoses of what causes dictatorships to survive or
collapse. An initial model was that embodied in the European
Community's body of law, the acquis communautaire, which by clearly
stating that only stable democracies will be considered for membership
provides a considerable carrot to regional countries to institute human
rights and democracy. More recently, the EU has applied this criterion
to out-of-area involvements--for example, by refusing to take part in
discussions to which undemocratic Burma is an invited party. After 1991,
Iraq was subjected to sanctions and international opprobrium while
opposition groups were actively supported, including by being provided
with safe areas enforced by no-fly zones. North Korea and Zimbabwe were
isolated and delegitimized also. In these cases, the strategy of
intervention was premised on the assumed inherent fragility of
dictatorships and the inherent appeal of democratization; yet in each of
these countries, the autocrats proved highly skilled and ruthless in
maintaining power. A significant part of the case for the invasion of
Iraq in 2003 stemmed from assessments that Saddam Hussein had proved
more than a match for more indirect methods of political intervention to
overthrow his regime. (41) More recently, Western governments and NGOs
have concentrated on providing direct advice and assistance to
opposition parties in quasi-democratic states, such as Georgia, Ukraine,
and Kyrgyzstan.
There is strong evidence that democratic political interventionism
has as mixed a record of success as its neoliberal economic counterpart.
Of the wave of democratization that has occurred since the end of the
Cold War, very little can credibly be attributed to the direct
intervention of outside actors. And in the above-listed cases of direct
political pressure in favor of democratization, as well as situations in
which UN missions have undertaken the task of democratic peace-building
in postconflict societies, the record of success in constructing durable
democracies is very poor. (42) For realists, the problems with political
interventionism occurred at the levels of motivations and
justifications. The overriding strategic importance of a Hosni Mubarak
or a Pervez Musharraf regime inspires caution in the face of claims of
long-term strategic gains. This leads to a partial implementation of the
policy and thus a denial of the formal justice requirement to
"treat like cases alike," opening its justifications up to
accusations of cynicism and self-interest.
HUMAN RIGHTS INTERVENTIONISM
Between 1945 and the early 1990s, there was considerable reluctance
on the part of Western states to critique the human rights performance
of postcolonial states. During the colonial period, and particularly in
the context of battling decolonization movements, all of the colonial
powers had engaged in serious human rights abuses. Furthermore, the key
human rights issue in the West in the 1950s and 1960s, racial equality,
closely echoed anticolonial rhetoric, making Western leaders and
commentators largely inattentive to humanitarian breaches in
non-white-ruled countries.
The circumstances and conditions of decolonization made many
postcolonial states reliant on repressive methods to control ethnically
divided societies. In the context of decolonization, national
self-determination referred only to a "negative right" not to
be ruled by members of a different race. (43) Whichever ethnic group
assumed power in the new state was entitled to expect the political
allegiance of all ethnic groups that had been enclosed within the former
colony's boundaries, and quite often assumed the right to repress rival ethnic groups in the name of state building. As a result, ethnic
conflict has been endemic in many postcolonial and postcommunist states,
and even democratic governments have resorted to widespread and
systematic human rights abuses to safeguard the integrity of their
states and the tenure of their regimes.
Human rights began to gain prominence as an issue in international
relations in the context of the Cold War, particularly after the passing
of the Final Act of the Helsinki Conference on Security and Cooperation
in Europe in 1975. (44) The inclusion of a declaration on common
humanitarian principles in a document legitimating Cold War frontiers
directed attention to the abuses of human rights carried out against not
only high-level dissenters, such as Alexander Solzhenitsyn, but also the
mass of ordinary people in the Soviet bloc. (45) It was not until after
the Cold War, in the early 1990s, however, that humanitarian
catastrophes surged to prominence as issues demanding direct preventive
and corrective intervention by the international community. More than
any other event, it was the conflict in the Balkans and the emergence of
the practice of "ethnic cleansing," which recalled the Nazi
Holocaust, that placed human rights intervention on the international
agenda. (46) The agony of Bosnia was closely followed by a failed
international intervention in Somalia to alleviate widespread starvation
occurring as a consequence of an ongoing civil war, and then the failure
of the UN to take timely action to prevent large-scale genocide in
Rwanda. After the NATO alliance's forceful intervention in Serbia
in 1999 to halt abuses against Muslims in Kosovo, an international
commission of legal practitioners and scholars, responding to a
challenge from UN secretary-general Kofi Annan, proposed that the
international community has a "responsibility to protect"
people subject to abuses by their own governments. (47)
The motivation toward human rights interventionism on the part of
Western states came in response to several factors. One was that human
rights outrages appeared incongruous in the light of the predominant
"new world order" liberal internationalist euphoria prevailing
at the end of the Cold War. Western public opinion, provided with
immediate images of human suffering by the media, exerted very real
pressure on governments to "do something" to help alleviate
catastrophes. (48) This was a sentiment that was used by certain
governments to shore up public support against pushing for too big a
post-Cold War "peace dividend": "Humanitarian actions
nurture the ... public's support for our engagement abroad."
(49) But there were almost no states willing to subscribe to the
doctrine proposed by scholars, jurists, and ethicists that a general
duty of humanitarian intervention existed or should exist in
international law. Indeed, every humanitarian intervention that has
occurred since India's invasion of East Pakistan in 1971 has been
justified primarily not by humanitarian concern, but by reference to the
international destabilization caused by the conflict or its humanitarian
impact. The security rationale has been the key to achieving the
acquiescence of skeptical permanent members of the UN Security Council
to humanitarian interventions, and to reassuring the rest of the
international community that human rights interventions will not become
a destabilizing general crusade.
The justifications for human rights intervention were much more
problematic. Once again, humanitarian concern came face-to-face with
strategic realities, as Chinese and Russian atrocities occurred and
reoccurred with little cost--let alone full interventions. Beyond this,
there seemed to be little consensus on how to compare types and
circumstances of human suffering. And then the genocide in Rwanda
occurred, leading to questions about whether the color of the
victims' skin determines concern for human rights. Once again, the
justification for humanitarian intervention suffered from shortfalls in
formal justice. As Mohammed Ayoob has pointed out, the selectivity of
human rights interventionism generates considerable cynicism in the
postcolonial world, among populations to whom it appears that some
humans' rights are more worthy of protection than others.'
(50)
Each mechanism of human rights intervention has proved problematic,
a record that has robbed the movement supporting humanitarian
interventionism of some of its momentum. The mechanisms of rhetorical
pressure, ranging from the U.S. State Department's annual report to
the UN Commission on Human Rights, have had much of the impact of their
shaming strategies negated by political maneuvering and name-calling.
States such as China, regularly the subject of critique, have either
neutralized UN processes or issued their own reports pointing out the
human rights failings of their principal accusers. And the "Asian
values" debate during the 1990s saw postcolonial states mount a
vigorous pluralist defense of their human rights records in the face of
the cosmopolitan-solidarist international human rights agenda. The use
of direct sanctions has been discredited by the case of Iraq in the
1990s, where it became clear that the impact of sanctions was most
directly and catastrophically felt by the weakest members of society. On
the other hand, policies of "constructive engagement" with
such countries as Burma are argued to bolster the power and legitimacy
of brutal governments. And direct military intervention confronts the
still-unresolved moral dilemma of doing harm in order to protect and the
legal dilemma of using force against sovereign states.
The experiences of the 1990s show that in seeking to ensure
adherence to human rights standards, the international community has
been unwilling to contravene the basic principles of negative
sovereignty and the current state system. Even the most ambitious and
extensive human rights interventions, such as that in Kosovo, have not
been willing to alter international territorial boundaries or challenge
the negative sovereignty of states in pursuit of a durable solution.
(51) This means that human rights interventions into ethnic conflicts by
default have the objective of leaving behind functioning multiethnic
states with strong guarantees of minority rights. (52) In practice, it
has meant that human rights interventions often result in open-ended
peacekeeping and peace-building obligations, which over time come to
resemble international mandates. The sheer cost and commitment of too
many open-ended mandates meant that by the end of the 1990s, direct
military intervention in support of human rights had become a much less
discussed and advocated policy by governments and most commentators.
GOVERNANCE INTERVENTIONISM
While economic, political, and human rights interventionism are all
motivated by concern about the consequences of the domestic organization
of postcolonial and postcommunist states, each of these three types of
interventionism has directed its attention to the reform of processes.
Thus, economic interventionism attempts to reorganize the processes of
economic policymaking and regulation along neoliberal lines; political
interventionism seeks to democratize the processes of government; and
human rights interventionism promotes processes guaranteeing basic human
rights to all citizens. The new phase of interventionism, focused on
governance, which gained dominance after the terrorist attacks of
September 11, 2001, is less concerned about processes and more attentive
to achieving an outcome: specifically, making states effective in
controlling what occurs and arises from within their borders. Although
the economic, political, and human rights intervention agendas continue
to operate--and they often also inform the governance agenda--the
single-minded focus on states' capacity to control the people and
territory for which they are responsible has often overridden concern
with democracy or human rights.
International interest with "governance" (53) and
"failing states" had begun to rise in the early 1990s, in
particular with the persistent chaos in Somalia. But until September 11,
2001, this concern had been related primarily to issues of international
order and humanitarianism. After the terrorist attacks on the World
Trade Center and the Pentagon, governance and state failure became
concerns of intense security self-interest to Western governments, such
as the U.K.'s:
[The terrorist attacks] confirmed the emergence
of two linked threats to Britain's and the
world's security: global terrorism and the
dangers from "failed states" where the rule of
law has broken down and chaos prevails. Terror
and state failure had been with us for
many years. But never before had they combined
to such devastating effect. Al Qa'ida
grew strong in a country where legitimate
government had given way to force of arms
and barbarism. (54)
As global security concern turned to transnational threats,
including terrorism, organized crime, drug smuggling, pandemics, and
weapons proliferation, the example of al-Qaeda and Afghanistan focused
attention on failing states and governance. Almost overnight,
international security had shifted its attention from the aggregation of
power to zones of extreme powerlessness. The new security focus quickly
generated its own geopolitics, with Fukuyama writing, "The end of
the Cold War left a band of failed and weak states stretching from the
Balkans through the Caucasus, the Middle East, Central Asia and South
Asia." (55) Other commentators developed a new "domino
theory" of state failure, arguing that the chaos from one failing
state can easily spill over into adjacent states, thereby dragging
neighbors into failure also. (56) The logic of this new geopolitics is
clear: weak states must be strengthened before their internal chaos
affects regional and global security. For the first time in recent
history, the motivation for intervention became more aligned to
traditional realist concerns of self-interest, as interventions were
advocated as a form of forward or anticipatory defense against the
transnational threats that could spill forth from weak states.
According to the new security paradigm, what makes the developed
world so vulnerable to the effects of state weakness in the developing
world is globalization. As Richard Haass describes:
Besides providing tangible "goods," globalization
facilitates the flow of numerous "bads."
The same networks that channel billions of
dollars in investment capital around the world
every day can also transmit financial contagion.
The same structure of global production
that brings opportunity to poor regions can
generate trans-boundary pollution. The same
Internet that links continents can be used to
coordinate criminal enterprises. The same
flow of scientific expertise that enables medical
breakthroughs can put the power to kill
thousands in the hands of terrorists. (57)
Globalization, an unstoppable force, requires close attention to
governance, according to the Australian government: "The quality of
a country's governance is crucial in determining whether it gains
or loses from globalization." (58) And Thomas Barnett argues that
weak systems of governance that are ill equipped to handle the forces of
globalization become the defining security challenge:
In this century, disconnectedness [meaning a
low level of integration into the processes of
globalization] defines danger. Disconnectedness
allows bad actors to flourish by keeping
entire societies detached from the global community
and under their control. Eradicating
disconnectedness, therefore, becomes the
defining security task of our age. (59)
The new concern with internal governance signifies a full-scale
shift back to international concern with the conditions of positive
sovereignty, or a state's possession of sufficient internal control
over its population and territory. Justifications highlighting concern
with the plight of people in failing states resonated with the
humanitarian concerns driving economic, political, and human rights
interventionism. The sense of urgency surrounding the issue of terrorism
has created a new normative environment that has allowed postcolonial
sensitivities to be brushed aside. Australian prime minister John Howard
notes:
There was a time not so long ago when sensitivities
about alleged "neo-colonialism" perhaps
caused Australia to err on the side of
passivity in our approach. Those days are
behind us as we work constructively to address
the challenges faced by our immediate neighbourhood. (60)
And, in preparing the ground for a new phase of interventionism,
negative sovereignty is hedged with a new form of conditionality,
according to Haass:
One of the most significant developments
over the past decades [is] the emerging global
consensus that sovereignty is not a blank
check. Rather, sovereign status is contingent
on the fulfillment by each state of certain
fundamental obligations, both to its own citizens
and the international community.
When a regime fails to live up to these
responsibilities or abuses its prerogatives, it
risks forfeiting its sovereign privileges
including, in extreme cases, its immunity
from armed intervention. (61)
As governance has become "securitized," its meaning has
changed. Originally, governance was understood as "the structures
and processes that enable governmental and nongovernmental actors to
coordinate their interdependent needs and interests through the making
and implementation of policies in the absence of a unifying political
authority." (62) As it has become linked to measures of state
failure, governance has been redefined as the capacity of a state to
provide certain public goods to its people. (63) Primary among these is
security from the types of societal disorder that provide ideal
conditions in which malevolent transnational forces can operate. The
focus on transnational security threats has assuaged the likely
opposition of such states as China and Russia, which would be deeply
suspicious of a governance agenda that was not linked to effectiveness
against transnational threats. (64)
The drive to ensure greater state capacity to eradicate conditions
conducive to transnational threats has led the United States, as well as
global and regional organizations, to pass a raft of resolutions and
measures mandating state action against terrorism (by one count, twelve
counter-terrorism protocols requiring specific state actions had been
passed between 2001 and 2004), terrorist financing (specifically, the
Financial Action Task Force requirements on terrorist financing),
organized crime, documentation fraud, money laundering, drug production,
and transport and trade security requirements. Many of these injunctions
have been accompanied by threats that noncompliant states will face
moratoriums on aid and other international eligibilities. The sheer
number and scale of new internationally mandated governance requirements
and the urgency dictated by the accompanying sanctions has led many
small developing states to worry about their capacity to enact and
enforce so much complex legislation in a short time. (65)
The series of governance interventions that have taken place since
September 11, 2001--in Afghanistan, Haiti, Solomon Islands, Cote
d'Ivoire, and Papua New Guinea--have made use of a variety of
techniques and rationales. Different strategic theorists have
conceptualized the interventions in various ways: Barnett, for example,
refers to the developed world "exporting security" to failing
states. (66) Hugh White talks of the application of "firm
power," where military and police "hard power"
pacification of violent societies is combined with "soft
power" in the form of developed states' legal, administrative,
and financial expertise to build strong institutions of governance. (67)
In the case of Afghanistan, direct military intervention was used to
topple a dangerous and misgoverning regime. A pacification force was
inserted into Haiti to stabilize a society that had been driven to chaos
by the misrule of a democratically elected government. The interventions
into the Solomon Islands and Papua New Guinea have had this objective,
but have also taken on the role of helping to construct more robust
systems of governance and public order.
But as with economic, political, and human rights intervention,
governance intervention is fraught with difficulties. When governance
interventions require not only the construction of robust institutions
but the transformation of political systems, as in Afghanistan, they
confront all of the problems of political interventions. Despite its
shift in meaning, "governance" continues to refer not only to
the existence of frameworks of order and regulation, but the willingness
and capacity of society to be shaped by these frameworks--a conception
close to Michel Fou cault's discussion of
"governmentality." (68) And often when political systems and
governance frameworks appear to be externally imposed, particularly
after an armed invasion, the receptiveness of segments of society to the
new systems is reduced. When governance interventions do not require or
propose a change in the politics of the state, and confine themselves to
technocratic tasks, such as in the Solomon Islands and Papua New Guinea,
other problems can arise. On the one hand, as Fukuyama has argued
convincingly, history shows that technocratic solutions that work in one
situation often fail in others, due to the advising technocrats'
inattention to local variations. (69) On the other hand, such
interventions' lack of attention to local political dynamics can
mean that the technocratic solutions they propose will soon succumb to
destabilizing political competition and violence. For instance, there
are strong reasons to question how durable the institutions erected by
the Australian-led governance intervention in the Solomon Islands will
be, because the mission has no mandate to address the land rights issues
that lie at the root of that country's present crisis. Indeed,
given Australia's difficulty in addressing its own indigenous land
rights issues, there is little hope that the current intervention will
even begin to resolve the conflicts underlying the Solomon Islands'
chronic state weakness.
TOWARD A NEW FRAMEWORK FOR INTERVENTION?
In examining the successive rise of different dominant phases of
humanitarian intervention, it has been my intention to demonstrate that
inattention to the considerations of realist ethical concerns leads to
sporadic and inadequate interventions and to significant rates of
failure. Two generic problems recur in each type of humanitarian
intervention. The first is a commitment shortfall on behalf of
intervening states, leading to a lack of dedication to long-term
engagement and to accepting and working with local requirements. Such
commitment shortfalls often derive from the lack of a compelling
self-interest that drives many cases of humanitarian intervention: in
such cases, the capacity of general humanitarian concern to maintain
states' involvement evaporates quickly. The second is a receptivity
shortfall within societies subject to intervention, meaning a lack of
willingness and capacity on the part of local populations to accept the
changes advocated. These receptivity shortfalls demonstrate that even
though the normative regime against interference in the domestic affairs
of developing states is being eroded internationally, post-colonial
sensitivities, particularly over perceptions of
"civilizational" gaps, are strongly felt domestically.
Furthermore, receptivity shortfalls lead to a range of intervention
pathologies--ranging from damaging failures to mission creep and
open-ended, mandate-like commitments--that in turn result in reluctance
of the international community to intervene in states in genuine need of
help. This reluctance has led to an extreme caution in developed
countries, dictating that interventions are considered from within the
prism of national self-interest. This in turn leads to cynicism within
the developing world about the motives of intervention, which further
extends receptivity shortfalls.
Despite its failings so far, the dynamic driving governance
interventionism offers the best chance of aligning the motivations,
justifications, and validity underpinning humanitarian intervention.
With the rise of the transnational security agenda, pathologies in the
domestic governance of developing states have become central to the
self-interest of developed states. Two attributes of modernity may
intensify this alignment: globalization and, to borrow Emile
Durkheim's term, the increasing organicism of society. (70) Just as
globalization can transmit the effects of state weakness and social
disorder across borders more rapidly and extensively than ever before,
the greater organicism of modern societies--meaning the advancing
interdependence and greater functional specialization of actors and
institutions--has led to huge increases in the vulnerability of modern
societies to catastrophic disruption. (71) Thus, just as states have
become increasingly alert to attacks on their infrastructure by other
states, they have also become more sensitive to the types of
international heterogeneity that can transmit the dangerous consequences
of state weakness toward their own societal and infrastructural
vulnerabilities.
For this reason, the trend of greater interventionism by developed
states, oriented toward protecting their vulnerabilities but at least
partly bound up in humanitarian concern, will likely continue.
Interventionism may change as developed states' perceptions of
their vulnerabilities change--for example, the next phase of
interventionism may be "biosocial" aimed at changing the
environmental, social, and agricultural practices of societies that give
rise to dangerous zoonotic diseases, such as SARS and avian flu--but it
will likely continue. Transnational threats--from terrorism to
pandemics--have conceptually linked the functionality of separate
societies as never before on a global scale in international relations.
With each new terrorist attack, wave of narcotics, or pandemic outbreak,
governments and societies grow increasingly aware of their vulnerability
to transnational networks deriving their potency from their ability to
arbitrage different levels of governance internationally. (72)
If concern with transnational threats continues and broadens past
the current focus on terrorism, it will offer an opportunity to develop
a shared framework of domestic and international order that may align
the three components of a realist ethics of intervention: motivation,
justification, and validity. The lack of alignment among these
components has led to the commitment shortfalls and receptivity
shortfalls that have plagued each form of intervention. The central
tension that needs to be resolved in such an alignment is between the
central requirement of motivation--the self-interest of intervening
states--and one of the key conditions of viable justification--formal
justice, or the need to treat like cases alike. Concern with
transnational threats, if it can be translated into an internationally
agreed framework of state effectiveness, offers a chance to resolve this
tension. If developed states' perceptions of insecurity can be
linked to state failure everywhere, rather than just in some regions,
poor governance may continue to furnish motivations for intervention.
Prioritizing interventions on the basis of objective, general
performance indicators measuring a state's provision of security
and welfare to its people would bolster the justification for
interventions. States falling short on such indicators would need to
demonstrate a marked record of improvement to avoid triggering targeted,
calibrated interventions at certain thresholds. Intervention in most
cases should involve a long-term commitment to help build state capacity
and institutions of governance, further strengthening justifications and
claims to validity. Ironically, and unfortunately, it may only be
through the increasing insecurity of developed societies that a realist
normative framework for humanitarian intervention can gain traction.
(1) See, e.g., Simon Chesterman, Just War or Just Peace?
Humanitarian Intervention and International Law (Oxford: Oxford
University Press, 2001); Deen K. Chatterjee and Don E. Scheid, eds.,
Ethics and Foreign Intervention (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press,
2003); Stanley Hoffmann, The Ethics and Politics of Humanitarian
Intervention (Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press, 1997); J. L.
Holzgrefe and Robert O. Keohane, eds., Humanitarian Intervention:
Ethical, Legal, and Political Dilemmas (Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press, 2003); and Pierre Laberge, "Humanitarian Intervention: Three
Ethical Positions," Ethics & International Affairs 9 (1995),
pp. 15-36.
(2) See, e.g., Nicholas J. Wheeler, Saving Strangers: Humanitarian
Intervention in International Society (Oxford: Oxford University Press,
2001).
(3) The 2003 invasion of Iraq, even though partially justified by
concern for the Iraqi people and committed to reconstructing Iraq's
institutions of governance, was undertaken for predominantly strategic
reasons.
(4) Although Andrew Linklater, in his Men and Citizens in the
Theory of International Relations (London: Palgrave Macmillan, 1990),
points out that jurists and philosophers have discussed such issues
since the early modern period.
(5) See Thomas Hobbes, The Elements of Law, Natural and Politic
(London: Cass, 1969), Part I; and David Hume, A Treatise of Human Nature
(Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1978), Book III.
(6) Niccolo Machiavelli, The Prince, trans. W. K. Marriott (London:
Dent, 1958).
(7) See Michael Walzer, "Political Action: The Problem of
Dirty Hands," Philosophy & Public Affairs 2, no. 2 (1973), pp.
163-64; Gerald F. Gaus, "Dirty Hands," in R. G. Frey and
Christopher Heath Wellman, eds., A Companion to Applied Ethics (Oxford:
Blackwell, 2003), pp. 167-79; C. A. J. Coady, "Politics and the
Problem of Dirty Hands," in Peter Singer, ed., A Companion to
Ethics (Oxford: Blackwell, 1991), pp. 373-83; and Martin Hollis,
"Dirty Hands," British Journal of Political Science 12 (1982),
pp. 385-98.
(8) Martin Wight, Systems of States (London: Leicester University
Press, 1977).
(9) Carl Schmitt, The Concept of the Political, trans. George
Schwab (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1996).
(10) See, e.g., Arnold Wolfers, Discord and Collaboration: Essays
on International Politics (Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press,
1962), pp. 47-65.
(11) Inis L. Claude, Jr., "Collective Legitimization as a
Political Function of the United Nations," International
Organization 20, no. 3 (1966), pp. 367-79.
(12) Joseph S. Nye, Jr., Soft Power: The Means to Success in World
Politics (Washington, D.C.: PublicAffairs, 2004). (13) Hedley Bull, The
Anarchical Society (London: Macmillan, 1977). Bull and his followers
distinguish an attentiveness to principles of international order from
the "Hobbesian" realist position in international relations,
yet fail to provide any convincing evidence that realists have little
regard for these issues.
(14) See Hedley Bull, ed., Intervention in World Politics (Oxford:
Oxford University Press, 1984); and Wheeler, Saving Strangers.
(15) See Georg Schwarzenberger, Power Politics: A Study of
International Society (London: Stevens and Sons, 1951), pp. 218-32.
(16) Lawrence Freedman and Efraim Karsh, The Gulf Conflict
1990-1991: Diplomacy and War in the New World Order (London: Faber and
Faber, 1993).
(17) Robert H. Jackson, Quasi-States: Sovereignty, International
Relations and the Third World (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press,
1990).
(18) The exception, of course, was France, which continued to
consider itself bound by ongoing responsibilities toward its former
colonies, especially in West Africa, and to intervene in their affairs.
(19) Jackson, Quasi-States, p. 196.
(20) See Stephen Krasner, "Power Structures and Regional
Development Banks," International Organization 35, no. 2 (1981),
pp. 303-28.
(21) Michael J. Hogan, The Marshall Plan: America, Britain and the
Reconstruction of Western Europe, 1947-1952 (Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press, 1987).
(22) A minor exception is the rise of government-funded programs,
such as the Peace Corps, and civil society organizations, such as Oxfam,
but these have never matched the scale or impact of Marshall Plan
involvement.
(23) World Bank, Worm Development Report 1997 (Washington, D.C.:
World Bank, 1997).
(24) John Toye, Dilemmas of Development (Oxford: Black well, 1987).
(25) William Easterly, "The Lost Decades: Developing
Countries' Stagnation in Spite of Policy Reform" Journal of
Economic Growth 6, no. 2 (2001), pp. 135-57.
(26) Francis Fukuyama, State-Building: Governance and World Order
in the 21st Century (Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 2004), p. 5.
(27) Michel Camdessus, "The IMF at the Beginning of the
Twenty-First Century: Can We Establish a Humanized Globalization?"
Global Governance 7, no. 4 (1997), p. 364.
(28) See Ray Kiely, "Neoliberalism Revised? A Critical Account
of World Bank Concepts of Good Governance and Market Friendly
Intervention," Capital and Class 64 (Spring 1998), pp. 63-88; and
Susanne Soederberg, "The Emperor's New Suit: The New
International Financial Architecture as a Reinvention of the Washington
Consensus," Global Governance 7, no. 4 (2001), pp. 453-67.
(29) John Lewis Gaddis, The Long Peace: Inquiries into the History
of the Cold War (New York: Oxford University Press, 1987).
(30) Examples include Iran in 1953, Chile in 1973, and Nicaragua in
1979.
(31) Jeane J. Kirkpatrick, Dictatorships and Double Standards:
Rationalism and Reason in Politics (New York: Simon & Schuster,
1982).
(32) See James Mann, The Rise of the Vulcans (New York: Penguin
Books, 2004), ch. 8, for an account of the development of concern for
democracy and human rights as part of the conservative agenda in the
United States.
(33) Walter Russell Mead, Special Providence: American Foreign
Policy and How It Changed the World (New York: Routledge, 2002).
(34) See Michael W. Doyle, "Liberalism and World Poli
tics," American Political Science Review 80, no. 4 (1986), pp.
1151-69.
(35) See, e.g., Joshua Muravchik, Exporting Democracy: Fulfilling
America's Destiny (Washington, D.C.: American Enterprise Institute
Press, 1991).
(36) See John C. Hulsman, A Paradigm for the New World Order
(Basingstoke, U.K.: Palgrave Macmillan, 1997).
(37) Anthony Lake, "From Containment to Enlargement,"
Vital Speeches of the Day 60, no. 1 (1993), p. 17. (38) See, e.g.,
Francis Fukuyama, The End of History and the Last Man (London: Penguin
Books, 1992); and Muravchik, Exporting Democracy.
(39) See Robert Packenham, Liberal America and the Third World
(Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1973).
(40) Charles T. Call and Susan E. Cook, "On Democratization
and Peacebuilding," Global Governance 9, no. 2 (2003), p. 235.
(41) See Bob Woodward, Plan of Attack (New York: Simon &
Schuster, 2004).
(42) See Juan J. Linz and Alfred Stepan, Problems of Democratic
Transition and Consolidation (Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press,
1996).
(43) Jackson, Quasi-States, p. 152.
(44) Jack Donnelly, Universal Human Rights in Theory and Practice
(Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 1989).
(45) R. J. Vincent, Human Rights and International Relations
(Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1986).
(46) Roy Gutman, A Witness to Genocide (Shaftsbury, U.K.: Element,
1993); and Salahi Ramadan Sonyel, The Muslims of Bosnia: The Genocide of
a People (Markfield, U.K.: The Islamic Foundation, 1994).
(47) International Commission on Intervention and State
Sovereignty, The Responsibility to Protect (Ottawa: IDRC, 2001).
(48) Michael Wesley, Casualties of the New World Order: The Causes
of Failure of UN Missions to Civil Wars (Basingstoke, U.K.: Macmillan,
1997).
(49) Lake, "From Containment to Enlargement," p. 17.
(50) Mohammed Ayoob, "Third World Perspectives on Humanitarian
Intervention and International Administration," Global Governance
10, no. 1 (2004), pp. 99-118.
(51) Kosovo's effective independence from Serbia under the
autonomy framework of the Rambouillet Accords is unlikely ever to be
transformed into statehood; in the case of East Timor, the UN
intervention occurred after the formal vote for independence from
Indonesia.
(52) A good example of this can be seen by tracing the history of
the various international peace plans for Bosnia and the Dayton Accords,
all of which insisted that Bosnia would be reconstituted as a
functioning multiethnic democracy; see Wesley, Casualties of the New
World Order.
(53) See, e.g., World Bank, World Development Report 1997; and
James N. Rosenau and Ernst-Otto Czempiel, eds., Governance without
Government: Order and Change in World Politics (Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press, 1992).
(54) United Kingdom Foreign and Commonwealth Office, "Foreign
and Commonwealth Office Departmental Report," London, U.K., May
2003, p. 3.
(55) Fukuyama, State Building, p. xi.
(56) See, e.g., Elsina Wainwright, "Responding to State
Failure: The Case of Australia and the Solomon Islands," Australian
Journal of International Affairs 57, no. 3 (2003), p. 489.
(57) Richard N. Haass, "The Changing Nature of
Sovereignty," speech given to the School of Foreign Service,
Georgetown University, Washington, D.C., January 14, 2003. (58)
Government of Australia, "Advancing the National Interest:
Australia's Foreign and Trade Policy White Paper," Canberra,
April 2003.
(59) Thomas P. M. Barnett, The Pentagon's New Map (New York:
G. P. Putnam's Sons, 2004), p. 8.
(60) John Howard, speech given to the Australian Strategic Policy
Institute, Sydney, Australia, June 18, 2004; available at
www.pm.gov.au/news/speeches/speech921. html.
(61) Haass, "The Changing Nature of Sovereignty."
(62) Elke Krahmann, "National, Regional and Global Governance:
One Phenomenon or Many?" Global Governance 9, no. 3 (2003), p. 327.
(63) See Robert I. Rotberg, "Strengthening Governance: Ranking
Countries Would Help," Washington Quarterly 28, no. 1 (2004/05),
pp. 71-81.
(64) China and Russia reacted to September 11, 2001, not by
focusing on governance but by emphasizing the great powers' common
struggle against radical pan-Islamism; see Ariel Cohen, "Russia,
Islam, and the War on Terrorism: An Uneasy Future,"
Demokratizatsiya 10, no. 4 (2002), pp. 556-67; and Ahmad Lutfi,
"China's Islamic Awakening," China Brief 4, no. 10
(2004); available at www.jamestown.org/images/pdf/cb_004_010.pdf.
(65) Several South Pacific governments, for example, have expressed
concern that their legal and bureaucratic systems will be unable to
design and enact the required legislation by the deadlines set.
(66) Barnett, The Pentagon's New Map, pp. 230-33.
(67) Hugh White, "Not Hard Cop, Not Soft Cop, But Still Firmly
into PNG," Sydney Morning Herald, September 23, 2003; available at
www.smh.com.au/articles/2003/09/
22/1064082927285.html?from=storyrhs&onedick=true.
(68) Foucault saw government as one possible modality of the
exercise of power. His discussions of governmentality focus on the
reciprocal relationship between governments that specify certain types
of behavior and subjects that are variously willing to constitute
themselves (as certain "subjectivities") in ways that
complement government preferences. See The Essential Works of Foucault,
1954-1984, Volume 111: Power, ed. James D. Faubion, trans. Robert Hurley
(London: Penguin Press, 1994).
(69) Fukuyama, in State Building, draws attention to the cases of
Russia and Argentina, which took technocratic advice on economic
restructuring only to fall prey to catastrophic financial failures and
long-term economic decline.
(70) Emile Durkheim, The Division of Labor in Society (New York:
Free Press, 1984).
(71) For example, the almost total dependence of modern societies
on information infrastructure and "just-in-time" inventory and
production systems is leading to an exponential growth in their exposure
to losses should all or a part of their vital infrastructure fail; see,
e.g., Stephen J. Lukasik, Seymour E. Goodman, and David W. Longhurst,
"Protecting Critical Infrastructures Against Cyber-Attack"
Adelphi Paper no. 359 (London: IISS, 2003). This problem has been
somewhat more polemically discussed in Ulrich Beck, Risk Society,
Towards a New Modernity, trans. Mark Ritter (London: Sage Publications,
1992). My thanks to an anonymous reviewer for this suggestion.
(72) Here I emphasize that transnational networks don't only
rely on weak governance--transnational criminals and terrorists prefer
to route their finances through states with stable institutions of
financial governance but low reporting requirements.
Michael Wesley, My thanks to Will Alker for research assistance and
to Marc Williams, Tiziana Torresi, Dirk Moses, CY, Paige Arthur, and an
anonymous reviewer for their comments on successive drafts of this
article; however, I am responsible for any mistakes or
misinterpretations in this essay.