Legal determinacy as presumptive fiction: the Blackmun papers on the primacy of life and the machinery of death.
Rice, Stephen K.
Concerns for rationality and consistency have informed contemporary
legal philosophy in no small measure. So-called "non-skeptic"
jurists such as Ronald Dworkin (1) and Nell MacCormick (2) have been
characterized as "formalist standard bearers" for their
thoughts regarding the need for logical, deductive justification in the
law and the application of clear and unambiguous legal propositions. (3)
Formalist sensibilities, or the "classical model" of legal
decision-making, views law as integrity, that is, the consistent
application of precedent by judges who decide cases on the basis of
rules that justify unique results in most cases. (4) Dworkin
characterizes formal legal decision-making as a "chain novel"
that is passed down from one author (jurist) to the next, all the while
being sustained by an implicit understanding that future voices must
respect the tone, tenor, and plot of the chapters that precede it. (5)
This metaphor presumes that as chapters are written, the judicial
decision-making of subsequent authors is increasingly constrained. (6)
But just as judicial decision-making is informed by general principles,
so too does decision-making vary in the nature of the principles that a
legal actor draws upon to make his/her argument.
In their critical legal-studies-based critique of formalism, legal
scholars Mark Tushnet and Jennifer Jaff have identified four subsets of
legal formalism: (1) classical doctrinal formalism, or principles of law
drawn from controlling legal documents; (2) law and economics, or legal
principles drawn from the logically consequences of rationality that
manifest in scenarios of limited resources; (3) moral philosophy, or
legal principles determined by principles of morality; and, (4) the
sociology of professions, or principles based upon systematic
observation of the actions of participants in the legal system. (7) The
recently released papers of Justice Harry A. Blackmun allows legal
analysts to gauge whether the formalist arguments have merit, or, to put
it another way, whether the sweep of time in the U.S. Supreme Court
during the last quarter of the twentieth century is best explained
formalistically or by something altogether different.
Realist Critiques
Finding much of its basis in the "revolt" by Justice
Oliver Wendell Holmes in his Lochner (1905) dissent and in the
scholarship of Jerome Frank, Karl Llewellyn, and Herman Oliphant, legal
realists have vigorously criticized formalist assumptions of strict
judicial adherence to rules for much of the twentieth century. (8) As
law and philosophy professor Brian Leiter explains:
The Realists argued ... that careful empirical consideration of how
courts really decide cases reveals that they decide not primarily
because of law, but based (roughly speaking) on their sense of what
would be "fair" on the facts of the case.... Legal rules and
reasons figure simply as post-hoc rationalizations for decisions
reached on the basis of non-legal considerations. (9)
Beginning in the 1920s, decades of research were borne in the
spirit of critiquing formalist assumptions in the law, mostly through
empirical analysis. Existing definitions of the law were examined for
consistency with "nature" (i.e., the way law
"really" operates). (10) As a consequence, realism
characterizes the law as both rationally indeterminate (i.e., not
justifying a unique decision based on an available class of legal
reasons) and causally indeterminate (i.e., not sufficient to explain why
judges act as they do based on legal reasons). One can thus characterize
the primary question for realists as "why did the judge reach that
result, given that law and legal reasons did not require him to do
so?" (11)
The Release of the Blackmun Papers
The recent release of the Blackmun Papers provides a unique
opportunity to assess extant critiques of formalism and realism in a
context rarely open to public scrutiny: via the personal letters, notes,
and journals of a prominent U.S. Supreme Court Justice. Even more
uniquely, the timing of the release of these papers affords insight into
the functioning of the Court while various principals still serve on the
bench, something justices do not often permit. (12) The information
cited in this study is compiled from sources housed at the Library of
Congress, media accounts of those granted advance access to the Blackmun
Papers (e.g., New York Times; National Public Radio), and scholarship
produced soon after the release of the papers. (13) The Blackmun Papers,
consisting of over a half-million items, include notes from oral
arguments and conferences, draft opinions, and memoranda. They have been
described as an "exhilarating" set of materials for legal
scholars because they provide insight into perceptions of precedent and
judicial decision-making. (14)
The Blackmun Papers on Abortion and Privacy Rights
As opposed to the monastic life of a conventional district judge,
(15) the Blackmnn Papers lift the veil on a rarely seen dynamic: a
community of appellate jurists who must pull, push, and compromise on
the great issues of the day. Involved in several of the most important
cases and controversies of the Burger and Rehnquist Courts (e.g.,
Pentagon Papers (1971); Watergate tapes (1974); Lee v. Weisman (1992)),
Blackmun, during his tenure as an Associate Justice from 1970 to 1994,
is best known for his landmark opinions in Roe v. Wade (1973) and Doe v.
Bolton (1973) concerning abortion and privacy rights. Indeed, the
disproportionality of Blackmun's writings in this area casts Roe as
the "sigma of his judicial career--the snapshot of his legacy to
the law." (16)
Interestingly, contemplations regarding abortion and privacy rights
during Blackmun's tenure on the U.S. Supreme Court suggest fluidity
in legal opinion, outcomes which stand in contrast to black-letter law.
(17) As New York Times journalist and Blackmun biographer Linda
Greenhouse proffers, during the spring of 1992 Blackmun struggled to
preserve the fight to abortion as five of his colleagues voted in a
closed-door conference to uphold provisions in Pennsylvania's more
restrictive abortion law in Planned Parenthood v. Casey. (18) As
Greenhouse explains, "[t]hen, suddenly, everything changed.... [A
letter from] Justice Anthony M. Kennedy, whom Justice Blackmun had long
since written off as a potential ally, arrived at his chambers.
'Dear Harry,' the letter began. 'I need to see you as
soon as you have a few free moments. I want to tell you about some
developments (in Casey), and at least part of what I say should come as
welcome news." As the country would later learn, Kennedy had
organized a group of three Republican-appointed justices (himself,
Sandra Day O'Connor, and David Souter) to preserve abortion rights.
As Blackmun noted after his meeting with Kennedy, "Roe sound."
(19)
Was new legal information brought to bear on Kennedy during the
interval, or is Greenhouse correct in her assessment that a trio of
Republican-appointed justices had secretly formed a team to preserve the
fight to an abortion? Group-based decision-making and consensus building
raises important issues concerning judicial impartiality. Materials
drafted by Blackmun law clerk Stephanie Dangel validate
Greenhouse's assertion, referring to a "troika" of
Justices O'Connor, Souter, and Kennedy upholding Roe: "Given
the middle ground that they have taken, I fear the decision may have the
effect of removing abortion from the political agenda just long enough
to ensure the reelection of Pres. Bush and the appointment of another
nominee from whom the Far Right will be sure to exact a promise to
overrule Roe." (20) Additional clerk missives indicate attention to
political considerations, including the most fortuitous time to hear
cases. Molly S. McUsic argued that if Planned Parenthood v. Casey were
to imperil the overthrow of Roe, "it would be better to do it this
year before the election and give women the opportunity to vote their
outrage." (21) Such considerations smack of Holmes'
century-old argument on "formalism as fiction," where judicial
decisions are based less on legal reasoning than "a concealed,
half-conscious battle on the question of [indeterminate] legislative
policy." (22)
The Blackmun Papers also illuminate the Justice's readiness,
at an earlier date than previously realized, to embrace the right to
privacy as the foundation for abortion rights. (23) In 1971, two years
before Roe, U.S. v. Vuitch challenged the District of Columbia's
criminal abortion statute but was decided without addressing the broader
constitutional issue. (24) Blackmun dictated a memo to himself:
"'Here we go in the abortion field," he began, reflecting
on the justices' awareness that abortion cases were increasingly
making their way to the Court chamber. Blackmun then reviewed the
Court's recent precedents establishing a fight to privacy for the
use of birth control and the private possession of pornography. These
cases, he wrote, "afford potent precedence in the privacy
field," adding: "I may have to push myself a bit, but I would
not be offended by the extension of privacy concepts to the point
presented in the present case. I think I could go along with any
reasonable interpretation of the problem on principles of privacy."
(25)
Here, one should note Blackmun's mental (read: legal)
flexibility, that is, how he is willing to go along with any reasonable
interpretation, a central presumption of the realist tradition
(particularly Frank's assertion of "normative quietism"
in law, that is, jurists who rule based on personal predilection, or
"hunch-based" decision-making). (26) Even more striking is the
portrait of the intersections of Blackmun's personal and
professional lives. As Greenhouse explains, Blackmun's
nineteen-year-old daughter Sally became pregnant in 1966, an event which
caused her withdrawal from college, marriage to a twenty-year-old
boyfriend, miscarriage, and subsequent divorce. "In one variation
or another," Greenhouse writes, "such family traumas were
hardly uncommon at a time when reliable birth control was difficult to
obtain, particularly for unmarried women; when half of all pregnancies
were unintended; and when some one million women a year risked sterility
or death to terminate unwanted pregnancies." (27)
Realists who espouse a social-psychological model of legal
decision-making argue that Blackmun's personal biography matters
immensely, that "[a] truly realistic theory of judicial
decision-making must conceive every decision as ... a product of social
determinants." (28) Rather than view law as consisting of
fundamental, a priori principles that can be applied in value-neutral
frameworks, realists would very much expect Blackmun's daughter to
matter mightily. In other words, law, in practice, leaves a great deal
of room for life experiences to inform judicial review. (29) For
realists, then, Blackmun will be forever associated with abortion and
privacy law, as the architect of the trimester framework (Roe) and his
ever more strident and emotional rhetorical style. (30)
The Blackmun Papers and Ultimate Sanction
Greenhouse's Becoming Justice Blackmun (2005), the most
comprehensive explication on the Blackmun Papers to date, makes Roe v.
Wade and Blackmun's lifelong relationship with Chief Justice Warren
Burger the "twin hub" of his development as a justice. (31)
But as political scientist Joseph Kobylka argues, this is a limited
orientation, one that "dulls the color that fills both the canvass
of his career and the Court on which he sat." (32) Among the other
vivid colors, one would have to include Blackmun's involvement in
matters related to the death penalty.
The death penalty holds a central place in a criminal justice
system whose meaning is both symbolic and variable. (33) As opposed to
the years preceding Furman v. Georgia (1972) when executions could be
conducted in relative obscurity, recent calls for transparency in
capital--sentencing decisions, media coverage of executions, and greater
insight into condemned inmates' perceptions and experiences
compliment insights gleaned from the Blackmun Papers regarding the
development of death penalty law. (34) Death penalty opponents insist
that "law's violence be acknowledged, not just at the
extremities of the legal order, but at the center of the process in
judicial interpretation." (35) It is in the process of judicial
interpretation that Blackmun is criticized on the grounds that his
record lacks evidence of an appreciation for the restrained role of the
jurist, or of a formalist ethos. (36) While some have pointed to the
years prior to Blackmun's appointment to the U.S. Supreme Court for
evidence of personal opposition to the death penalty, (37) the years
post-Furman and post-Gregg v. Georgia (1976) (38) provide the most
ballast.
Furman (1972) and Gregg (1976) are fascinating in and of themselves
as Blackmun dissented in the former, but concurred in the latter due to
his belief that the issue belonged under the purview of democratic, not
judicial, action. (39) In his Furman dissent, Blackmun explained that he
"yield[ed] to no one in the depth of [his] distaste, antipathy, and
indeed, abhorrence for the death penalty, with all its aspects of
physical distress and fear and of moral judgment exercised by finite
minds....," and expressed his belief that the penalty violated his
"childhood training and life experiences ... life convictions and
sense of reverence for life." (40) When one thinks back to
"formalist standard bearers" and their insistence for the
logical, deductive application of unambiguous legal propositions,
Blackmun's admission of "distaste, antipathy and ...
abhorrence" toward the death penalty and its violation of his
"life convictions" is extraordinary. One has to wonder how
observers of today's Court would react if Justices John Roberts,
Antonin Scalia, Clarence Thomas, or Samuel Alito were to frame their
dissent of an abortion rights ruling in such a manner. As political
scientist Barbara Perry speculates, the "excess daylight" that
such passionate, realist, formulations would unleash might well damage
the Court's authority as an enduring emblem of the rule of law.
(41) In other words, the explication of strong personal views in
one's opinions subordinates the law to the judge. (42)
With regard to his voting record, a more active anti-death penalty
orientation marked the remainder of Blackmun's career in cases that
include Lockett (1978) and Wainwright (1985). (43) The Blackmun Papers
provide an interesting insight into one such case, Callins v. Collins
(1994), (44) in which a denial of certiorari provided a forum for
Blackmun to utter one of the more famous lines in modern jurisprudence.
As Greenhouse explains:
The project, known [among Blackmun's clerks] ... as the 'death
penalty dissent,' had two separate parts: to draft an opinion and
then to select a case--a 'vehicle,' they called it--in which the
opinion could be used to best effect.... By late October, [clerk
Michelle L. Alexander] had a draft to show Blackmun. 'This is a
very personal dissent, and I have struggled to adopt your 'voice'
to the best of my ability ... I have tried to put myself in your
shoes and write a dissent that would reflect the wisdom you have
gained, and the frustration you have endured, as a result of twenty
years of enforcing the death penalty on this Court'.... On February
22, 1994, the Court denied review in Callins v. Collins, over
Blackmun's twenty-two-page solitary dissent. (45)
Consider the draft of the dissent from the Blackmun Papers (see
Figure 1), including the interesting linguistic formulation of the
famous edict: "I no longer shall tinker with the machinery of
death." As is the case in so much of Blackmun's record, one
should note his use of language. In this instance, there is nothing
"mechanical" about Blackmun. Rather than focus strictly on how
the penalty may violate the Eighth or Fourteenth Amendments (as in
Furman or Gregg), Blackmun's emotional, moralistic argument
buttresses law as explanatorily indeterminate (i.e., influenced by a
jurist's moral or political persuasion).
It is reasonable to argue that over time, Blackmun's votes in
death penalty cases became completely aligned with his personal views,
and that the tone and tenor of his opinions became ever more
egalitarian, demonstrating personalization and sympathy for the
defendant. (46) In McCleskey v. Kemp (1987), (47) the well-known case
that challenged Georgia's administration of the death penalty based
on statistical evidence of racial disparities in sentencing, Blackmun
condemned the Court's unwillingness to consider such evidence. (48)
Memoranda found in his papers indicate that the subsequent execution of
Warren McCleskey weighed heavily on Blackmun, and that this experience
formed much of the basis for his later Callins opinion. (49)
With regard to the majority opinion, the McCleskey decision makes
for a comprehensive attack on formalism itself because the ruling failed
to uphold requirements outlined by Tushnet and Jaff, namely: (1)
classical doctrinal formalism, (2) law and economics, (3) moral
philosophy, and (4) the sociology of professions. (50) As criminologist
Katheryn Russell argues, on the first point the Court could well have
used its formalistic arguments to reach a contrary result. On the second
point, the Court's holding was not necessary to produce a fair
result within the framework of societal morality. On the third point,
the Court's citation of the history of minority group claims (and
suppositions of future claims were McCleskey to prevail) were largely
groundless on the matter of economic efficiency in the court system.
Concerning the fourth point, Russell asserts that a contrary decision
would not have adversely impacted the role of the prosecutor; instead,
such statistical evidence would have made burdens on the system lighter
as prosecutors and defense counsel would have clearer guidelines
regarding prima facie cases of discrimination. (51) All told, Court
opinions and the more "three-dimensional" view afforded by the
Blackmun Papers into cases such as McCleskey, Callins, and Furman
provide evidence for legal realists to assert that law, in action,
centers on the use of legal rules and reasons as post-hoc
rationalizations for decisions reached on the basis of nonlegal
considerations. (52)
[FIGURE 1 OMITTED]
A page from Justice Blackmun's draft dissent in the death
penalty case, Callins v. Collins. Shown is the correction of the phrase,
"I no longer shall tinker with the machinery of death." Dated
November 22, 1993. (Source: Blackmun Papers, Container 648, Folder 5,
Library of Congress, Washington, D.C.).
The Issue of Justice: Competing Frameworks
Attention to matters of justice is grounded in the desire to
understand how social institutions and societal practices can ensure a
fair distribution of advantages, or what political philosopher John
Rawls has referred to as "the basic structure." (53)
Determining which jurisprudential practice is more "just"
depends, in large measure, on what one wishes to get out of the Court.
It also calls upon observers of the Court to be mindful in employing
terms from the philosophy of law. Law professor Martin Stone, for
example, claims that attacks on formalism have been fraught with
overstatement: "'Formalism,' it has become tempting to
say, is little more than a loosely employed term of abuse, one used to
describe any judicial decision, style of legal thinking, or legal theory
with which the user of the term disagrees." (54) Legal analysts may
criticize judges for being formalistic (rule-bound) while also trying to
contain ultra vires (stepping beyond the rules). (55) The need for
rapidly effective legal reform, perhaps due to the law being perceived
as "out of phase" with contemporary values, might benefit from
an indeterminate court structure, as would legal concerns that would
benefit from more holistic sensibilities, such as therapeutic
jurisprudence. (56) By contrast, perhaps "regular"
(non-appellate) judicial contexts may be better suited to legal
determinacy. (57)
Attempts to reconcile this tension between the impartial and
personal have a long history in jurisprudence and moral philosophy. (58)
Most desire clarity in legal thought, a sense of fairness, and an
opportunity for justice. To Herman Oliphant, this means a return to
stare decisis, or a way to restate legal doctrine in a manner that is
more fact-specific and (therefore) more descriptive. (59) For H.L.A.
Hart, this means a focus on the central core of legal rules in order to
effectively adjudicate "easy" cases. (60) Efforts to determine
which jurisprudential practice is more just requires a careful
determination of one's legal goals and expectations.
On balance, a middle-range model is likely needed: judges should
consider a rule's purpose and whether that aim would be emboldened
or frustrated by its strict application. The "meaning" of a
legal rule would then only be attainable through purposive interpretation. Evoking Judge Learned Hand, the need for a fluid,
iterative process that incorporates the best of both constructs is
likely necessary. (61) The Blackmun Papers provide such a palette. As
opposed to mere speculation about judicial decision-making, the papers
show how it actually manifests over time. (62) Whether Blackmun
"changed pigment" (63) by starkly transitioning himself from a
principled formalist to someone who "allowed his personal
preferences full domination across the field of constitutional
jurisprudence," (64) remains open to debate. (65) It is more likely
that Blackmun followed the arc advanced by Justice Holmes a century
earlier: that of law in action--a corpus which develops less by logic
(or "law in books" (66)) than by the "felt necessities of
the time." (67) While one will still find uncertainty and
instability in the law in the Blackmun Papers, (68) they nonetheless
provide immeasurable insight into the vagaries of abortion and capital
punishment law during the last quarter of the twentieth century.
ENDNOTES
(1) Ronald Dworkin, Law's Empire (London: Fontana, 1986).
(2) Neil MacCormick, Legal Reasoning and Legal Theory (Oxford:
Clarendon Press, 1993).
(3) William Lucy, "Adjudication," in The Oxford Handbook
of Jurisprudence and Philosophy of Law, eds. Jules Coleman and Scott
Shapiro (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2002), 208.
(4) Brian Leiter, "Karl Nickerson Llewellyn," in
International Encyclopedia of the Social & Behavioral Sciences, eds.
Neil J. Smelser and Paul B. Baltes (Kidlington, Oxford: Elsevier Science
Ltd., 2001), 8999.
(5) Dworkin, Law's Empire, esp. 230-32, 255-57.
(6) Stefanie Lindquist and Frank Cross, "Empirically Testing
Dworkin's Chain Novel Theory: Studying the Path of Precedent,"
New York University Law Review 80 (October 2005): 1156.
(7) Mark Tushnet and Jennifer Jaff, "Critical Legal Studies
and Criminal Procedure," Catholic University Law Review 35 (Winter
1986):361-62.
(8) Brian Leiter, "Classical Realism," in Social,
Political, and Legal Philosophy, eds. Ernest Sosa and Enrique Villanueva
(Boston: Blackwell Publishers, 2003), 256-57. See also Michael S. Moore,
"The Semantics of Judging," Southern California Law Review 54
(January 1981):151-53.
(9) Leiter, "Karl Nickerson Llewellyn," in International
Encyclopedia of the Social and Behaviorial Sciences, eds. Smelser and
Baltes, 8999-9000.
(10) Good examples are Katheryn K. Russell's empirical
critique of McClesky v. Kemp ("A Critical View from the Inside: An
Application of Critical Legal Studies to Criminal Law," Journal of
Criminal Law and Criminology 85 (Summer 1994):222-40) and Lindquist and
Cross' empirical test of the role of precedent in judicial
decision-making ("Empirically Testing Dworkin's Chain Novel
Theory," 1156-1206). See also Karl N. Llewellyn's seminal work
on the application of the Universal Commercial Code ("Remarks on
the Theory of Appellate Decision and the Rules and Canons about how
Statutes are to be Construed," Vanderbilt Law Review 3 (April
1950):401). Llewellyn argues that by following such a tack, the law is
asserting, simultaneously, that "[a] statute cannot go beyond its
text," yet also "[t]o effect its purpose a statute must be
implemented beyond its text. See discussion by Leiter, "Karl N.
Llewellyn," in International Encyclopedia of the Social and
Behavioral Sciences, eds. Smelser and Baltes, 9000. See also James J.
White, "The Influence of American Legal Realism on Article 2 of the
Uniform Commercial Code" in Perscriptive Formaility and Normative
Rationality in Modern Legal Systems, eds. Werner Krawietz, Neil
MacCormick, and Georg Henrik von Wright (Berlin: Duncker & Humblot,
1994), 401.
(11) Leiter, "Karl Nickerson Llewellyn" in International
Encyclopedia of the Social and Behavioral Sciences, eds. Smelser and
Baltes, 9000. Two further delineations of realism, that of the
"sociological" and "idiosyncratic" wings (associated
with Llewellyn and Frank, respectively), assess social and psychological
factors that frame decision-making by jurists.
(12) After retiring in 1994, Blackmun gave his papers to the
Library of Congress on the condition that they remain closed to the
public until five years after his death. See Linda Greenhouse, Becoming
Justice Blackmun: Harry Blackmun's Supreme Court Journey (New York:
Times Books, 2005), xi. Not surprisingly, the release of the papers so
soon after Blackmun's death generated considerable debate as to
"... how much we should know about what goes on at the Court, an
institution long shrouded in secrecy and confidentiality." Martha
Dragich Pearson and Christina Wells, "Reflections on Judging: A
Discussion following the Release of the Blackmun Papers," Missouri
Law Review 70 (Fall 2005):966.
(13) See Linda Greenhouse, "The Blackmun Papers: Documents
Reveal the Evolution of a Supreme Court Justice," New York Times,
March 4, 2004, A1. See also Linda Greenhouse, "At a Shrine of
American Documents, Pathos, Poetry and Blackmun's
'Rosebud,'" New York Times, March 7, 2004,
http://topics.nytimes.com/top/reference/timestopics/people/b
/harry_a_blackmun/imndex.html (accessed August 14, 2007), 1-2; Library
of Congress, "About the Harry A. Blackmun Papers,"
http://lcweb2.1oc.cgibin/faidfruquery/r?faidfr:@field(SOURCE+@blackmun+harr+a) (accessed August 14, 2007), 1; "Justice Harry
Blackmun's Papers: Documents, Oral History Reveal Supreme
Court's Inner Workings,"
http://www.npr.org/news/specials/blackmun (accessed August 14, 2007);
Greenhouse, Becoming Justice Blackmun; Pearson and Wells,
"Reflections on Judging," 965-72; Suzanna Sherry,
"Politics and Judgment," Missouri Law Review 70 (Fall
2005):973-88; Colleen McMahon, "The Monastic Life of a Federal
District Judge," Missouri Law Review (Fall 2005):989-94; Duane
Benton and Barrett J. Vahle, "The Burger-Blackmun Relationship:
Lessons for Collegiality from the Blackmun Papers," Missouri Law
Review 70 (Fall 2005):995-1036; Tony Mauro, "Lifting the Veil:
Justice Blackmun's Papers and the Public Perception of the Supreme
Court," Missouri Law Review (Fall 2005): 1037-47; Gregory C. Sisk,
"The Willful Judging of Harry Blackmun," Missouri Law Review
(Fall 2005): 1049-74; Joseph Kobylka, "Tales from the Blackmun
Papers: A Fuller Appreciation of Harry Blackmun's Judicial
Legacy," Missouri Law Review (Fall 2005):1075-1132; Ellen E.
Deason, "Perspectives on Decionmaking from the Blackmun Papers: The
Cases of Arbitrability and Statutory Claims," Missouri Law Review
70 (Fall 2005): 1133-82; Martha Dragich Pearson, "Revelations from
the Blackmun Papers on the Development of Death Penalty Law,"
Missouri Law Review 70 (Fall 2005): 1183-98; Richard C. Reuben,
"Justice Blackmun and the Spirit of Liberty," Missouri Law
Review 70 (Fall 2005): 1199-1208; Theodore W. Ruger, "Justice Harry
Blackmun and the Phenomenon of Judicial Preference Change,"
Missouri Law Review 70 (Fall 2005): 1209-30; Daniel A. Farber, "Did
Roe v. Wade Pass the Arbitrary and Capricious Test?" Missouri Law
Review 70 (Fall 2005): 1231-60; Lawrence S. Wrightsman, "Why Do
Supreme Court Justices Succeed or Fail?: Harry Blackmun as an
Example," Missouri Law Review 70 (Fall 2005):1261-88; Margaret E.
McGuinness, "The Internationalism of Justice Harry Blackmun,"
Missouri Law Review 70 (Fall 2005): 1289-1308; Christina E. Wells,
"Some Reflections on the Symposium: Judging, the Classical
Paradigm, and the Possible Contributions of Science" Missouri Law
Review 70 (Fall 2005): 1309-14.
(14) Pearson and Wells, "Reflections on Judging," 965.
(15) McMahon, "The Monastic Life of a Federal District
Judge," 989-94.
(16) Kobylka, "Tales from the Blackmun Papers," 1076.
(17) Black-letter law refers to law "on the books" or
"the law that legislators enact, the law ... set down by the
Founding Fathers ... the law that evolves through common-sense cases and
through appeals decisions." See Norman J. Finkel, Commonsense
Justice: Jurors' Notions of the Law (Cambridge, MA: Harvard
University Press, 2001), 2.
(18) Planned Parenthood v. Casey, 505 U.S. 833 (1992).
(19) Greenhouse, "The Blackmun Papers" New York Times,
March 4, 2004, A1.
(20) Mauro, "Lifting the Veil," 1044.
(21) Greenhouse, Becoming Justice Blackmun, 202.
(22) Oliver Wendell Holmes, Jr., "The Path of the Law,"
Harvard Law Review 10 (March 1897):467.
(23) Greenhouse, Becoming Justice Blackmun, 76.
(24) U.S. v. Vuitch 402 U.S. 62 (1971).
(25) Greenhouse, Becoming Justice Blackmun, 73.
(26) Jerome Frank, "Are Judges Human?" University of
Pennsylvania Law Review 80 (November 1931): 27.
(27) Greenhouse, Becoming Justice Blackmun, 74-75.
(28) Felix S. Cohen, "Transcendental Nonsense and the
Functional Approach," Columbia Law Review 35 (June 1935):843.
(29) Wells, "Some Reflections on the Symposium," 1309-14.
(30) Kobylka, "Tales from the Blackmun Papers," 1075,
1105.
(31) Greenhouse, Becoming Justice Blackmun. See also Kobylka,
"Tales from the Blackmun Papers," 1075-1132.
(32) Kobylka, "Tales from the Blackmun Papers," 1076.
(33) John Hagan and Celeste Albonetti, "Race, Class, and the
Perception of Criminal Injustice in America" American Journal of
Sociology 88 (September 1982):329.
(34) William J. Bowers, "The Capital Jury Project: Rationale,
Design, and Preview of Early Findings," Indiana Law Journal 70
(Fall 1995): 1043-1102; Henry Schwarzschild and Robert R. Bryan,
"To See or Not to See: Televising Executions;' in The Death
Penalty in America." Current Controversies, ed. Hugo A. Bedau (New
York: Oxford University Press, 1994), 384-86; Austin Sarat,
"Killing Me Softly: Capital Punishment and the Technologies for
Taking Life," in Pain, Death, and the Law, ed. Austin Sarat (Ann
Arbor, MI: University of Michigan Press, 2001), 43-70.
(35) Jonathan Simon, "The Vicissitudes of Law's
Violence," in Law, Violence, and the Possibility of Justice, ed.
Austin Sarat (Princeton, N J: Princeton University Press, 2001), 23.
(36) Such as sentimentality and strong emotion: "There is
something lawless ... about the notion that warmhearted impulses are
more important than legal reasoning." See Jeffrey Rosen,
"Sentimental Journey: The Emotional Jurisprudence of Harry
Blackmun" New Republic, May 2, 1994, 13. See also Richard A.
Posner, "Judges' Writing Styles (And Do They Matter?),"
University of Chicago Law Review 62 (Fall 1995): 1447. Sisk, "The
Willful Judging of Harry Blackmun," 1066.
(37) Martha J. Dragich, "Justice Blackmun, Franz Kafka, and
Capital Punishment," Missouri Law Review 63 (Fall 1998):855.
(38) Gregg v. Georgia 478 U.S. 153 (1976).
(39) Sisk, "The Willful Judging of Harry Blackmun" 1050.
(40) Furman v. Georgia, 408 U.S. 238 (1972).
(41) Barbara Perry, The Priestly Tribe: The Supreme Court's
Image in the American Mind (Westport, CT: Praeger, 1999), 155.
(42) Sisk, "The Willful Judging of Harry Blackmun," 1053.
(43) Lockett v. Ohio, 438 U.S. 586 (1978); Wainwright v. Witt, 469
U.S. 412 (1985).
(44) Callins v. Collins 510 U.S. 1141 (1994).
(45) Greenhouse, Becoming Justice Blackmun, 177-79.
(46) Sisk, "The Willful Judging of Harry Blackmun," 1066.
See also Pearson, "Revelations from the Blackmun Papers on the
Development of Death Penalty Law," 1195.
(47) McClesky v. Kemp, 481 U.S. 279 (1987).
(48) The Court, in a 5-4 decision, ruled that the statistical
evidence was "clearly insufficient to support an inference that any
of the decision makers in McCleskey's case acted with
discriminatory purpose...." See Russell, "A Critical View from
the Inside," 222-40.
(49) Pearson ("Revelations from the Blackmun Papers on the
Development of Death Penalty Law," 1195) provides an excellent
outline of the evidence that McCleskey's execution provided both a
legal and emotional segue to the latter Callins opinion. Memoranda from
the period by clerks Stephanie Dangel and Andrea Ward (found in the file
of Sawyer v. Whitley, a case under consideration at the time of the
execution), refer to "notes you dictated to me the morning after
Warren McCleskey was executed last fall," "comments you made
at breakfast shortly after the McCleskey execution last fall," and
"the discussion we had earlier in the year after Warren
McCleskey's execution" (Blackmun Papers, Box 604, Folder 6,
Library of Congress). Blackmun's off-cited dissent in the later
Callins case, which included "graphic images ... of the defendant
strapped to the gurney, intravenous tubes in his arms" (Pearson,
"Revelations from the Blackmun Papers on the Development of Death
Penalty Law," 1197), has been thought to stem largely from
Blackmun's reaction to McCleskey (Pearson, "Revelations from
the Blackmun Papers on the Development of Death Penalty Law,"
1195).
(50) Tushnet and Jaff, "Critical Legal Studies and Criminal
Procedure," 361.
(51) Russell, "A Critical View from the Inside," 226-27.
(52) Leiter, "Karl Nickerson Llewellyn," in International
Encyclopedia of the Social and Behavioral Sciences, eds. Smelser and
Baltes, 9000.
(53) John Rawls, Justice as Fairness: A Restatement (Cambridge, MA:
Harvard University Press, 2001), 10.
(54) Martin Stone, "Formalism," in The Oxford Handbook of
Jurisprudence and Philosophy of Law, eds. Jules Coleman and Scott
Shapiro (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2002), 172. See also Ernest J.
Weinrib, "Legal Formalism: On the Immanent Rationality of
Law," Yale Law Journal 97 (May 1988):949; A.W. Brian Simpson,
"Legal Iconoclasts and Legal Ideals," University of Cincinnati Law Review 58 (Spring 1990):819, 834.
(55) Stone, "Formalism," in The Oxford Handbook of
Jurisprudence and Philosophy of Law, eds. Coleman and Shapiro, 173.
(56) Christopher Slobogin and Mark Fondacaro, "Rethinking
Deprivations of Liberty: Possible Contributions from Therapeutic and
Ecological Jurisprudence," Behavioral Sciences & the Law 18
(August 2000):499-516.
(57) Leiter, "American Legal Realism," 6.
(58) Margaret Moore, Foundations of Liberalism (New York: Oxford
University Press, 1993), 2.
(59) Herman Oliphant, "A Return to Stare Decisis," in
American Legal Realism, eds. William W. Fisher, et al. (New York: Oxford
University Press, 1928), 199-201.
(60) H.L.A. Hart, The Concept of Law (Oxford: Clarendon Press,
1961). See also Brian Bix's chapter on "clear cases" in
Law, Language, and Legal Determinacy (New York: Oxford University Press,
1993), 63-76.
(61) "The spirit of liberty is the spirit which is not too
sure it is right." Learned Hand, "The Spirit of Liberty,"
in Learned Hand." The Spirit of Liberty, ed. Irving Dillard, 3rd
ed. (New York: Alfred A. Knopf, 1960), 190.
(62) Mauro, "Lifting the Veil," 1037.
(63) Kobylka, "Tales from the Blackmun Papers," 1075.
(63) Sisk, "The Willful Judging of Harry Blackmun," 1066.
(64) Reuben, "Justice Blackmun and the Spirit of
Liberty," 1199-1208.
(66) Roscoe Pound, "Law in Books and Law in Action,"
American Law Review 14 (January-February 1910): 12-36.
(67) Oliver Wendell Holmes, Jr., The Common Law (Boston: Little,
Brown, and Co., 1881; repr., Mineola, NY: Dover Publications, 1991), 1.
(68) Pearson, "Revelations from the Blackmun Papers on the
Development of Death Penalty Law," 1184.