Olympians on the march: the courts & the culture wars.
Bork, Robert H.
[T]o be "reactionary" means nothing more than to believe
that in some of its aspects, however secondary, the past was better than
the present.--Leszek Kolakowski
Everything has been said before, but since nobody listens we have
to keep going back and beginning all over again.--Andre Gide
Walter Bagehot said of the English constitution, "[I]n the
full activity of an historical constitution, its subjects repeat phrases
true in the time of their fathers, and inculcated by those fathers, but
now no longer true?, So it is with us. We are living with a vision of a
Constitution that no longer exists. The reason is apparent. The
Constitution, which is, for all practical purposes, the Supreme Court,
follows the elite culture. Thus it is that the liberal transformation of
the Constitution over the past fifty years has been accomplished by
Courts with heavy majorities appointed by Republican presidents (the
current count is seven to two).
As cultural dominance passes from one elite to the next, so does
the Supreme Court's law change to reflect the views of the new
elite. New values are added and old ones abandoned. Not all values,
however, can find even remotely plausible support in the historical
Constitution. When vagabond values are to be implemented, the
Court's declarations that various executive or legislative acts are
unconstitutional are often not even colorably related to the charter
supposedly being applied. Disregard for text, legislative purpose, and
history confers enormous freedom, so that the Court, employing some
primitive and often sophomoric version of moral philosophy or natural
law, is at liberty to enforce what it chooses. It is not to be expected
that lives devoted to lawyers' arts would, upon the donning of
black robes, suddenly produce philosophers. We are then governed not by
law but by the moods of an unelected, unrepresentative, and
unaccountable committee of nine lawyers. What they decide is often law
only in the sense that we will obey their ukases, even when they split
five to four and the four have by far the better arguments. What they
decide is not law in the sense that it has its origin, its root, in any
legal materials and that the result falls within a range that would be
regarded as acceptable by most judges, past, present, and future. Moods
shift; fair readings do not.
The progression is clear on the record. In the last third of the
nineteenth century and the first third of the twentieth, the dominant
culture was that of the business class, mad the Court often responded
with the invention of constitutional rights favorable to that class,
striking down reform legislation which, however unwise, was clearly
within the constitutional powers of state and federal legislatures. The
Court invented, for example, a right to enter into contracts that is
nowhere to be found in the Constitution. Lochner v. New York, a 1905
decision, is the classic example. The Court, dividing six to three,
struck down a state statute setting maximum hours for bakers as
violative of the (nonexistent) right to make contracts. Early New Deal
economic regulations were routinely invalidated until a series of
retirements and deaths enabled Franklin Roosevelt to remake the Court.
The cultural dominance of the business class having been ended by the
Great Depression, the new Court freely approved economic regulations and
began to prepare the ground for the creation of new rights. An even more
momentous shift came with the Court headed by Earl Warren.
The New Deal Court had been philosophically riven. Arthur
Schlesinger, Jr., has described the Court as it stood in 1947. The wing
occupied by Justices Black and Douglas was "concerned with settling
particular cases in accordance with their own social
preconceptions," a version of "value jurisprudence"
identified largely with the Yale law school. Its dominant theme was
equality, as shown by its heavy reliance upon the Equal Protection
Clause. Schlesinger, Jr. wrote that "Black and Douglas vote less
regularly for doctrines than for interests--for the trade union against
the employer, for the government against the large taxpayer, for the
administrative agency against the business, for the injured workman, for
the unprotected defendant, against the patent holder--so that in the
phrase of Professor Thomas Reed Powell 'the less favored in life
will be the more favored in law.'" This was a flat
contradiction of the judicial oath to "administer justice without
respect to persons and do equal right to the poor and to the rich."
It was as well an expression of the socialist impulse which,
significantly, became the regnant outlook of the Court at a time when
the American intelligentsia was socialist. As a consequence of the
Warren Court's preference for equal results rather than equal
justice, it politicized every branch of the law, statutes as well as the
Constitution. Ironically, the Court's favored constitutional
implement was the clause of the Fourteenth Amendment promising
"equal protection of the laws."
Socialism, however, was then discredited. In practice it produced
impoverishment and tyranny so that not even intellectuals could cling to its dream, or at least most of them could not do so publicly. Radicalism
took the form of the New Left of the 1960s, which gradually grew more
interested in personal freedom unrestricted by law, morals, or even the
rules of self-preservation (drugs and filthy living conditions were
often considered signs of "authenticity"). The New Left
practiced a politics of expression and self-absorption. A vision of
radical individual autonomy thus lay at the heart of their world view.
There was a good deal of that in their intellectual class elders and now
it is the dominant mood of the intelligentsia.
It is not too surprising, then, that a mood of radical autonomy or,
if you will, moral relativism began to appear in the jurisprudence of
the Supreme Court. The Court, in step with the intellectual class, has
dropped the socialist drive of the Warren Court. The difference between
the two Courts is shown by the differing fates of the two fields I know
best, antitrust and constitutional law. The death of the socialist
illusion made possible the use of basic economics to return antitrust to
rationality. But the rise of moral relativism--perhaps a better term
would be moral chaos--drove constitutional law in a new but no more
respectable or rational direction.
Today, a lawyer who appears before the Court in a case involving
antitrust, taxation, labor law, or a similar question will find his case
is typically dealt with in a straightforward, lawyerly manner. But when
the Court is presented with a cultural issue in a constitutional
context, the Court majority usually departs from the Constitution, often
indeed from any conceivable meaning of the Constitution, in order to
enact an item on the modern liberal agenda, generally resulting in the
enshrinement of radical individual autonomy as part of the Bill of
Rights. That is signified by the Court's heavy use of the Due
Process Clause's guarantee of liberty. To some considerable degree,
therefore, it seems valid to say that the current Court is dominated by
a gentrified form of Sixties radicalism. I do not know how otherwise to
account for the absolute mess of our current jurisprudence of individual
rights.
Though the justices are properly criticized for abandoning the
proper judicial function to follow intellectual class fecklessness,
responsibility for the health of the legal order does not, of course,
depend entirely upon judges or even upon a reckless intellectual class.
Responsibility rests as well with the practicing bar, the law schools,
and, ultimately, with the public that elects or delegates to
representatives the election of judges. None of these is performing well
or even tolerably. The problems, not all of which may be soluble, lie in
the nature of legal practice, the way law is taught, the modern
conception of legal scholarship, the ideological direction of the
courts, the enormously enlarged area of authority and competence
appropriated by those courts, the eagerness of factions to circumvent
democracy by litigation, and, finally, public incomprehension of what is
and is not in our Constitution and so the public's inability to
judge the judges. I have had some experience as a practitioner,
professor, government lawyer before the Supreme Court, and judge;
doubtless my views are colored by that fact.
When college graduation approached and I was trying to decide on a
career, law still recruited the young with prettified images of Holmes
and Brandeis. It was Holmes who said that it was possible to live
greatly in the law, a rather obscure remark that seemed meaningful at
the time. A life in the law seemed to promise battle, require devotion,
and reward learning--and what idealistic young man would not choose to
be warrior, priest, and scholar? The reality proved to be rather
different. Economic pressures have made law less of a profession and
more of a business, drastically limiting the role the bar can play in
maintaining the integrity of the law. Such concerns necessarily give way
to an absorption with billable hours. Though it is not quite true, as a
British barrister put it, that success in law depends on the ability to
eat sawdust without butter, quite a bit of sawdust-munching is required.
Firms have, moreover, entered an era of giantism. When I joined the
largest law firm in Chicago, it had fifty-three lawyers with fewer than
a dozen more in a Washington branch. Today the firm has over 450 lawyers
in Chicago and well over 900 nationwide, and it is by no means the
largest in either category. A firm of fifty-three lawyers today would
today be considered practically a boutique operation. Giantism produces
an atmosphere more like a corporate headquarters than a partnership.
Corporations are not known for a selfless devotion to sound public
policy, nor, it turns out, is the practicing bar. That is not a
criticism of either business or the bar, but merely a fact that probably
cannot be altered.
At one time we were reconciled to the democratic unaccountability of courts by the promise that their powers would be kept within
tolerable limits by the informed criticism of the bar. That has not been
borne out. Practitioners have provided very little in-depth analyses of
major constitutional doctrines; the organized bar has offered none.
Attorneys, by and large, have not the time and energy left over from
busy practices to study the fields in which the courts operate or to
engage in sustained critiques. My practice was primarily in antitrust,
but while it was apparent that the law was a doctrinal mess, there was
no time to study it as a field; the problems present themselves case by
case so that connecting links are not obvious, nor is it in either the
client's or the firm's interest to have lawyers spending time on theoretical inquiries that, in any event, a judge is more likely to
find irritating than persuasive. It is probably for that reason that the
reform of antitrust law, when it occurred, came from the academy rather
than from the practicing bar. Fields such as constitutional law, which
rarely arise in ordinary practice, go almost entirely unexamined. Only
ideological litigants, like the ACLU which is devoted to distorting
constitutional law in the service of cultural leftism, have any occasion
to spend a great deal of time on the subject. Moreover, since their
success depends on judges, very few lawyers are willing to risk
criticizing them. Bar politicians, leaders of the American Bar
Association, for example, find it congenial to hobnob with judges and
defend them from criticism. (The ABA, while it engages in professional
training to some extent, is increasingly a culturally liberal political
organization rather than a professional one, passing resolutions
favoring a right to abortion, racial preferences, a universal right to
food, AIDS needle-exchange programs, campaign finance reform, and
opposing laws regulating sexual conduct between adults.) Its presidents
make statements favoring judicial activism. Rather than providing an
informed critique of the courts' performance, the ABA is a
cheerleader for some of the worst tendencies of modern jurisprudence.
The exigencies of law practice discourage inquiries that have no
immediate practical use. The last thing an advocate wants to tell a
judge is that the case at bar presents a profound, or even a moderately
interesting, question. That would suggest the case could be decided
either way. His case, the lawyer must say, with every appearance of
sincerity, is clear, so simple that it is hardly worth discussing, and
must obviously be decided in favor of his client. The cases he cites are
controlling whereas those mistakenly, and perhaps disingenuously, relied
upon by his opponent are wide of the mark. So, too, with respect to
policy arguments and hypothetical instances, both relied upon to show
that only beneficial results will follow from accepting his position
while his adversary's contentions would plunge the law into chaos
and black night. It can be an exhilarating game, but some lawyers
eventually find its repetition turns into drudgery. If they are lucky,
they find alternatives.
While the time had come to leave the practice, I do not regret in
the slightest the eight years I spent there. There was a great deal of
satisfaction in winning, the excitement of the contest, the tactical
maneuvering, and the camaraderie of a team working on high-stakes and
difficult cases. There was the night of the "lost chord" when
at 4 A.M. a colleague at last found the perfect precedent for our side
and slapped the book triumphantly back on the shelf. We went down the
hall for a celebratory coffee, only to discover, upon returning to the
library, that we never could find that case again. Or the night in the
conference room when I looked up from drafting a difficult paragraph,
found that my colleague had disappeared, and finally located him
sleeping on the floor underneath the table. There was the romanticism (I
don't know how else to put it) of leaving the office in the first
gray light before dawn, the old stone buildings of Chicago just
beginning to emerge from the blackness beyond the reach of the street
lamps, catching a rare cab on Michigan Boulevard to go home to Hyde
Park, shower, shave, put on fresh clothes, and, my wife and children
still asleep, return downtown for another day's work.
Ultimately, however, that was not the intellectual life the law had
seemed to promise. Litigation is a plastic art; only those who were
involved remember it at all. Like working a crossword puzzle, it is
absorbing while you are doing it, but, when it is done, there is nothing
left. In the days and nights, for weeks on end, that a friend and I
spent writing and endlessly rewriting a brief about a now-forgotten
trust estate worth many millions, we could have produced, I flatter
myself, a book of some worth. In the long run, however, the real value
of practice to me was that I learned how the court system works. Too
many students and professors are inclined to view judges, particularly
Supreme Court justices, as philosopher kings. Some experience trying to
persuade judges would disabuse the professors, and hence their students,
of that notion.
In seeking an academic position, I discovered that eight years of
practice made me highly suspect. Some professors apparently thought
former practitioners would tell war stories about their cases and teach
students how to schmooze with the court clerk. Yale, however, with
whatever reservations, appointed me to its law faculty, for which I will
always be grateful. The first five years, until the student radicals
arrived, were the best years of my professional life. The students were
bright and argumentative. Ward Bowman, an economist, provided invaluable
discussions about antitrust. Alexander Bickel--whom I count as the best
friend I ever had--was equally important to my development of a theory
of constitutional interpretation, though we disagreed about it.
Together, we taught a seminar in Constitution Theory. Influenced by John
Stuart Mill and extrapolating from Griswold v. Connecticut, the original
right of privacy case, I made the preposterous argument that the only
harm government should be permitted to prevent was physical injury.
Bickel said, "What if I engage in indecent exposure?" I
replied that the law already had a doctrine to deal with that.
"What doctrine?," Bickel asked. "De minimis non curat
lex--the law does not take cognizance of trifles." That was the
only time in a long relationship that he was silenced for a minute.
Bickel emphasized tradition as the only effective curb on courts.
His judicial philosophy, I told our class on the First Amendment, was a
combination of Edmund Burke and Fiddler on the Roof. That one he liked.
He recognized, however, that the Warren Court had shattered whatever
tradition there was left to lean upon. I, in contrast, was searching for
a firm theory of when government was permitted to coerce and when it was
not. Both of us, I now think, were wrong. The tradition, such as it was,
is now gone forever, and I came to realize that Lord Patrick Devlin was
right: "it is not possible to set theoretical limits to the power
of the State to legislate against immorality."
Teaching is the best way to learn an entire field of law.
Practitioners drill deeply into narrow areas in preparing a case.
Academics teach across an entire field. Each has advantages, and, when
combined, they nourish each other. When not combined, there is in each
the danger of sterility. It is unfortunate that these two branches of
the profession view each other with suspicion. It is even more
unfortunate that sometimes the suspicion on both sides is justified. The
aversion of many professors to those who practiced what the professors
were supposedly teaching was astonishing. When I spoke at an
appointments committee meeting against hiring young men and women just
out of school or clerkships, I was met with stony expressions; nobody on
the committee and few on the faculty had more than trivial experience
with the day-to-day operation of the law. One exceptionally able
student, urged to join the faculty, said he would like two or three
years of experience first. He was told not to waste his time.
The insularity of legal academia has become a major problem. Many
articles published in major law reviews are of no use to practitioners
or judges but consist of philosophical exercises (at which law
professors are not very good), often on the trilogy familiar in the
humanities--race, sex, and class. Some prestigious law schools actually
award tenure to those who write stories bereft of any legal analysis
about the anguish of living in an oppressive society. It may be tempting
to view such follies as no more than raw material for another Lucky Jim,
but the situation is serious. Many law students are ill-prepared for
their careers and potentially dangerous to their clients; they must be
socialized and in some cases educated by the law firms that hire them.
Working in tandem with this distrust of professionalism is the
strong liberal bias of law faculties. One professor said to another,
with the intent that I should overhear, that it was the "shame of
the law school" that it had two Republicans when no other
department at Yale had any. Two out of about thirty-five was, in his
view, too many by two, but he was wrong about the rest of the
university: aside from the two excrescences in the law school, there was
one other admitted Republican on Yale's faculty of two thousand.
There surely must have been more, but they had the sense to keep their
heads down.
I would not overstate the matter. There were professors who offered
professional training and maintained good relationships with the
practicing bar. Nor do I do wish to give the impression that I was in
any way ill-treated. Most of the faculty, if somewhat bemused by finding
a conservative in their midst, were friendly and willing to hear, if not
to adopt, nonliberal views. The problem was that ideas and attitudes
were clustered at one end of the spectrum. Students were not exposed to
the full range of opinion about law. The addition of former student
radicals to faculties, moralistic men and women with harder ideological
edges, seems at many schools to have made the few conservatives actually
beleaguered. That is particularly true, though not exclusively so, of
those who teach and write about constitutional law.
My tenure at Yale was interrupted by service as solicitor general of the United States. The solicitor general must approve any government
appeals from adverse decisions in any court, federal, state, or local,
and also, along with members of a relatively small staff, argues
government cases in the Supreme Court. Contrary to what might be
supposed, the Supreme Court is the most enjoyable court to argue before.
The justices are prepared and engage in lively questioning. Not all
courts are like that. There are few more disheartening experiences than
arguing for half an hour or more to a judge who has not read the briefs
and who sits silent and impassive throughout.
The solicitor general necessarily comes to know the justices'
tendencies and abilities very well. There was then, as there is today, a
wide range in both characteristics. Justice Byron White was perhaps the
quickest intellectually, often seeing the point well before the advocate
got to it. At the other end of that spectrum was Justice Harry Blackmun.
The most ideological justice was probably William J. Brennan, Jr., who
was also the most charming and friendly member, though his view of the
judicial function was as different from my own as could be. He was the
real leader of the Court in its adoption of deplorable tendencies. He
was an affable man whose compelling attractiveness undoubtedly accounted
for much of his influence with other justices. It seems likely that
Brennan played a major role in converting Earl Warren, whose strong
point was not conceptual thinking, from a moderate conservative into a
judicial radical.
Robert Nisbet, a particularly insightful observer, stated the
ideological situation in the law schools and the judiciary somewhat
dramatically but with considerable accuracy:
The crusading and coercing roles of the
Supreme Court and the federal judiciary ...
have created a new and important model for
all those whose primary aim is the wholesale
reconstruction of American society.... There
are more mad more judges, more and more
lawyers, and more and more law students and
professors who have entered easily into a state
of mind that sees in the Supreme Court
precisely what Rousseau saw in his archetypical
legislators and Bentham in his omnipotent
magistrate: sovereign forces for permanent
revolution.
The ideological movement of constitutional law can be gauged by the
changes in the casebooks used in the law schools. When I began teaching
the subject in 1964, most of the casebooks concerned the structural
features of the Constitution--separation of powers, federalism, the
scope of Congress's and the President's powers, the legitimacy
and rationale of judicial supremacy, and so on. Cases involving the Bill
of Rights took up less than half the book. Indeed, to a modern reader,
it is amazing that in Joseph Story's Commentaries on the
Constitution of the United States, written in 1833, the discussion of
the first ten amendments, the Bill of Rights, occupies about
one-fiftieth of the pages. In truth, the Bill of Rights, supplemented
after the Civil War by the Fourteenth Amendment guaranteeing due process
of law and the equal protection of the laws against incursions by state
government, did not generate many cases until well into the twentieth
century. The pace picked up with the Warren Court and has not slackened
since. In the 1997 edition of a leading constitutional law casebook,
Bill of Rights cases took up almost four times the space given to the
structural Constitution, signifying an enormous shift from interest in
the processes of government to the rights of individuals. The Bill of
Rights took up about 2 percent of Story's Commentaries and about 73
percent of the casebook. The American public regards constitutional law
as little more than a list of individual rights, and the), may be
correct.
The reasons for this shift are no doubt various, including the
multiplying confrontations of an increasingly pluralistic society. The
judicial response has been to multiply rights. The most important reason
for present purposes, however, was the 1954 discovery by the Supreme
Court that it could order massive social change (the end of government
racial discrimination in Brown v. Board of Education) unrelated, so the
Court thought, to the meaning of the Constitution, and could prevail
over resistance. I have argued elsewhere that Brawn could have been
justified on constitutional principles, but the crucial fact is that the
Court did not think so. Encouraged to improve society further, it went
on to ordain other major changes in governmental processes and in
cultural and moral matters that were clearly not within the Court's
constitutional authority. Thus, as Lino Graglia puts it, "The first
and foremost thing to know about constitutional law ... is that it has
very little to do with the Constitution." The unpalatable truth is
that the Court is making up the Constitution and has been for many
years.
Courts below the Supreme Court have less freedom to legislate large
new principles, but judges at any level can be consciously influenced by
political considerations and personal predilections. In a case with
large political implications, our court clearly lacked jurisdiction, but
one judge, while privately admitting that to be so, placed his decision
on factual grounds because that would leave him free to decide a future
case, as a ruling of lack of jurisdiction would not. "You never
know," he said, "what may come down the pike next." That
was lawlessness. A number of other examples come to mind. I have no
doubt that my views and temperament influenced my judging, but that is
inevitable, and the influence was never conscious. A number of my
colleagues on the bench could honestly say the same thing, and there is
a great difference between judges who, knowing it impossible to succeed
entirely, do their best to eliminate views that have no proper role in
reaching decisions and those who actively enforce their prejudices.
Judges belong to the class that John O'Sullivan first
identified as "Olympians." The political philosopher Kenneth
Minogue described the philosophy of this class:
Olympianism is the project of an intellectual
elite that believes that it enjoys superior enlightenment
and that its business is to spread
this benefit to those living on the lower slopes
of human achievement.... Olympianism
burrowed like a parasite into the most powerful
institution of the emerging knowledge
economy--the universities.
From there the infection spread to other culture-shaping
institutions, most notably the Supreme Court which was accused, justly
in my opinion, with reasoning backwards from desired results to spurious
rationales. "[T]hat is a reality," Alexander Bickel wrote,
"if it be true, on which we cannot allow the edifice of judicial
review to be based, for if that is all judges do, then their authority
over us is totally intolerable and totally irreconcilable with the
theory and practice of political democracy." Yet that is the
reality upon which judicial review rests today.
The Court's dominant theme is now radical personal autonomy or
moral relativism, signified by its emphasis on the liberty mentioned in
the Due Process Clause. That reliance, though repeated scores of times,
is utterly illegitimate. The clause was clearly meant to guarantee that
no one be deprived of liberty without a fair process; it has nothing to
say about a fair substance of the law. History as well as the
constitutional text proves that. As John Hart Ely wrote, "there is
simply no avoiding the fact that the word that follows 'due'
is 'process.' ... [W]e apparently need periodic reminding that
'substantive due process' is a contradiction in terms--sort of
like 'green pastel redness.'" Unfortunately, periodic
reminding does no good. The Court continues on its way, judging the
substance of laws according to the justices' personal opinions of
what liberties we should or should not enjoy. There could be no clearer
demonstration that the Court regularly and frequently orders our lives
changed with a power it has no legitimate claim to wield.
The question arises, why is the movement of judge-made
constitutional law in the direction of extreme personal autonomy? It is,
of course, the world view of the Olympians, but it has also come to be a
feature of popular culture. Look where you will, autonomy erodes
discipline everywhere. Religion is a field in many ways very much like
law, and both have heresies that threaten to overcome orthodoxy. The
phenomenon of "cafeteria Catholics" is well known: despite the
Church's doctrine, Catholic rates of contraceptive use and abortion
are about the same as those of Protestants and Jews. When the Episcopal
Church ordained a practicing homosexual as a bishop, appeals to
scripture were brushed aside with amused disdain. A United Methodist
lesbian minister was acquitted in a church trial of the charge that
lesbianism was incompatible with Christianity, though it clearly is. The
restraints of public decency have been abandoned on cable TV and are
losing force on over-the-air TV and radio. No small part of these
developments is due to the Court's protection of obscenity and its
marginalization of religion. But, equally, no small part of the
Court's behavior is due to the culture in which it operates. The
real doctrines of the Constitution have no more chance to control the
Court than do the real doctrines of the churches to control the behavior
of its clergy and parishioners.
And why are legal arguments--in law schools as much as in
courts--frequently invested with so much anger, an anger that also
suffuses and distorts our politics? Law is unlikely, after all, to
develop an intense emotional temperature unrelated to the wider world of
political and social discourse. To say that the anger is due to the
culture war is accurate but hardly an explanation. An explanation that I
find eminently plausible is that there is always a segment of the
population, usually the intellectuals, that requires meaning in life.
The decline of religion, the loss of its redemptive vision, required a
new transcendent principle. The obvious, the only, candidate was
socialism.
Conservatism offers no comparable utopian goal. As Charles
Krauthammer points out, the collapse of the socialist ideal has left
Olympians with nothing except anger. Anger at the existing state of
society was, of course, always an active ingredient in socialism. Some
compensation for the loss of socialism is sought by various angry
radicals in the extreme versions of feminism, environmentalism, animal
rights, racial and gender preferences, homosexual rights, international
control of American actions, and other causes. That anger characterizes
the Democratic party, which is the party of the Olympians, and the
activist groups that are what's left of socialism.
The debate within the Supreme Court is usually, though not always,
more genteel, but the same urge to reconstruct a highly imperfect
society is apparent. The Supreme Court is enacting a program of radical
personal autonomy, indeed moral chaos, piece by piece, creating new and
hitherto unsuspected constitutional rights: rights to abortion,
homosexual sodomy (and, coming soon, homosexual marriage), freedom from
religion in the public square, racial and sexual preferences. None of
these is justified by the actual Bill of Rights.
I could easily multiply examples. But the underlying philosophy of
the Olympians--if it deserves so dignified a name as
"philosophy"--is wonderfully summed up in the famous
"mystery passage" that Justice Anthony Kennedy first
articulated in an opinion reaffirming the made-up constitutional right
to abortion. "These matters," Justice Kennedy wrote for the
Court,
involving the most intimate and personal
choices a person may make in a lifetime
[abortion, etc.], choices central to personal
dignity and autonomy, are central to the
liberty protected by the Fourteenth Amendment.
At the heart of liberty is the right to define
one's own concept of existence, of meaning, of the
universe, and of the mystery of human life. Beliefs
about these matters could not define the attributes
of personhood were they formed
under compulsion of the State. [emphasis
added]
Although this passage instantly attracted some measure of the
ridicule it deserved, Justice Kennedy chose to repeat it in Lawrence v.
Texas (2003), which pretends to discover a constitutional right to
homosexual sodomy. What other practices, we may wonder, are now "at
the heart of liberty"? Kennedy's aria about "the right to
define one's own concept of existence, of meaning," etc., is
not simply laughable intellectually; it also tells us something grim
about our future, the Court, and a people that supinely accepts such
judicial diktats.
Kennedy's rhetoric is loaded with legal and cultural messages.
First, and most obviously, the "mystery passage" demonstrates
once again that today's Bill of Rights jurisprudence has almost
nothing to do with the Bill of Rights. Once more the procedural meaning
of the Due Process Clause has been transformed into an unconfined
substantive judgment by a majority of the justices. When new rights are
not invented out of whole cloth, as in Lawrence, real rights are
expanded beyond all recognition. The Court is now the Olympians'
heavy artillery and panzer divisions in the culture war. The
"mystery passage" in particular, and the opinions on social
and cultural issues, generally, demonstrate that a majority of the Court
is willing to make decisions for which it can offer no intelligible
argument. There is thus a sharp decline in intellectual honesty and the
integrity of constitutional law. Constitutional law is no longer an
intellectual discipline but a series of political impulses. I sometimes
feel sorry for the editors of casebooks who accompany each opinion with
a series of questions and observations about the doctrines the Court is
laying down, modifying, refining, and abandoning. Doctrines don't
matter; politics do.
The sanctity of these decisions is not just a litmus test for
judicial nominees but an article of faith among Democratic politicians.
One of the more dismaying sights of the year was all seven candidates
for the Democratic presidential nomination standing before a feminist
organization obsequiously pledging allegiance to Roe v. Wade.
The Senate Democrats, along with a few Northeastern Republicans,
will not confirm any nominee to the Supreme Court, and very few to any
federal court, who does not express wholehearted support for that
ghastly decision. To almost all Democratic senators, virtually
unrestrained judicial activism in the service of the cultural Left has
become the "mainstream."
In the hands of the Court, radical individualism approaches
judicial nihilism. Since each individual must be permitted to define
meaning for himself, it must follow that there is no allowable truth,
legal or moral. Yet, as Lord Devlin observed, "What makes a society
of any sort is community of ideas, not only political ideas but also
ideas about the way its members should behave and govern their lives;
these latter ideas are its morals." Partly as a consequence of the
Supreme Court's extra-constitutional adventures, we are losing our
community of ideas about moral behavior. The result is a species of
legal triumphalism: When law has disintegrated the bonds of society, its
common moral assumptions, there will be nothing left but law to sustain
us, and law alone cannot bear that weight.
Even the sense of the sacred is now a mocked and withered virtue.
Today's justices seem to have taken their inspiration from the
radically libertarian John Stuart Mill of On Liberty--from the Mill,
that is, who endorsed the view that "society has no business as
society to decide anything to be wrong which concerns only the
individual." This Mill would have applauded the sentiment if not
the logic of Kennedy's "mystery passage." As Gerturde
Himmelfarb has pointed out, however, there was another, more sober Mill,
a Mill who acknowledged that
In all political societies which have had a
durable existence, there has been some fixed
point; something which men agreed in holding
sacred; which it might or might not be
lawful to contest in theory, but which no one
could either fear or hope to see shaken in
practice.... But when the questioning of
these fundamental principles is (not an occasional
disease but) the habitual condition of
the body politic ... the state is virtually in a
position of civil war; and can never long
remain free from it in act and fact.
That describes our culture war to a T. Examples of the denigration of the formerly sacred are numerous: the symbol of the American flag,
the idea of public decency, the centrality of religion, and even
traditional marriage--all are clearly threatened if not, indeed,
mortally damaged. Of all the institutions of society, perhaps only the
judiciary and, most especially, the Supreme Court is still regarded as
sacred. Certainly, a majority of the justices think of the Court that
way, and three of them have been explicit about the sacrosanct nature of
their office. In Planned Parenthood v. Casey (1992), three of the five
justices who voted to retain a right to abortion wrote of Americans who
would be "tested" by following the Court's decision:
[The American people's] belief in themselves
as [a] people [who aspire to live according to
the rule of law] is not readily separable from
their understanding of the Court invested
with the authority to decide their constitutional
cases and speak before all others for
their constitutional ideals. If the Court's
legitimacy should be undermined, then so
would the country be in its very ability to see
itself through its constitutional ideals.
That the people are "tested" by their willingness to
follow the puerile moralizing of judges and that their "belief in
themselves" is inextricably bound to their obedience to the Court
is a piece of hubris that might have been expected to produce a backlash
of outrage. That it did not is worth pondering.
Having established virtually unquestioned authority on the domestic
front, judges, also without any warrant in the Constitution, appear to
be contemplating roles as international statesmen. Justice Stevens,
writing for four members of the Court in 1988, relied upon "the
views that have been expressed by respected professional organizations,
by other nations that share our Anglo-American heritage, and by leading
members of the Western European community" to hold it a forbidden
cruel and unusual punishment to execute a person for a capital crime
committed when he was fifteen years of age. There have been other
instances of reliance upon foreign decisions and statutes in
interpreting the Constitution of the United States, but perhaps the most
intriguing was Justice Steven Breyer's statement in 1999 that he
found "useful" decisions concerning allowable delays in
executions by the Privy Council of Jamaica, the Supreme Court of India,
and the Supreme Court of Zimbabwe. It is puzzling enough to contemplate
what decisions handed down by foreign courts in the late twentieth
century have to do with an American document written in the late
eighteenth century; it passes understanding how the Bill of Rights
drafted by James Madison is illuminated by the decisions of judges
controlled by Robert Mugabe, the African tyrant and mass murderer.
The citation of foreign decisions in American constitutional
opinions may be irritating, but it may also be only window-dressing: the
Court would probably reach the same results without the aid of the
Supreme Court of Zimbabwe. Still, Justice Sandra Day O'Connor suggests the justices will go further. She said in a recent speech that
decisions by the courts of other countries could be persuasive authority in American courts. At a time, she said, when 30 percent of the United
States's gross national product is internationally derived,
"No institution of government can afford to ignore the rest of the
world:' It might seem that the one institution of government that
should ignore the rest of the world is the one that derives its sole
authority from a purely domestic source, the United States Constitution.
It got worse. Justice O'Connor said the Court had found persuasive
an amicus brief submitted by American diplomats saying that their jobs
in foreign countries were made difficult by the practice of capital
punishment in the United States. Rather than representing us to foreign
nations, the diplomats were representing foreign countries in our Court.
This internationalizing trend is so delightful to Olympians--though they
might draw the line at Zimbabwe--that Linda Greenhouse could write with
apparent approval in The New York Times that "it is not surprising
that the justices have begun to see themselves as participants in a
worldwide constitutional conversation." It would be more accurate
to say that they are participants in a worldwide constitutional
convention.
Perhaps we should have seen this coming. For as Minogue pointed
out, "We may define Olympianism as a vision of human betterment to
be achieved on a global scale by forging the peoples of the world into a
single community based on the universal enjoyment of appropriate human
rights.... Olympians instruct people, they do not obey them." And
Olympians require constitutional courts to make certain their
instructions stick. They may succeed. The idea of international law is
catnip to some people, particularly to the intelligentsia. They may sell
the notion to much of the public because it is often supposed that
removing disputes from the arenas of diplomacy and force is to
substitute high principle for the clash of crass interests. Those who
make and ratify our treaties ought not to place authority in
international courts without considering what we know about judges.
Added to the usual tendency of courts with vague charters to enlarge
their powers beyond anything anticipated by the law writers, there is
the additional, and insoluble, problem of conflicting national interests
and animosities, particularly animosity to the West in general and to
the United States in particular. Nevertheless, the process of
internationalizing law is taking place in our and in foreign courts
without the consent of representative institutions.
In short, what we are witnessing is the homogenization of the
constitutional laws of the nations of the West. And, since
constitutional law is increasingly made by judges without reference to
the actual constitutions they purport to be applying, there is
developing an international constitutional common law. That is made
possible by the fact that judges in almost all Western nations share
Olympian values. Thus, we tend to see indifference or hostility to
religion, the embrace of sexual permissiveness, the normalization of
homosexuality, the creation of abortion rights, the classification of
pornography and extreme vulgarity as protected free speech, hostility to
traditional authorities, and special rights for favored ethnic
minorities and, often, for women. All this leads to the Balkanization of
society and the weakening of social discipline based upon a shared
morality. It is difficult to say what the next developments in the
judicial reconstruction of society will be. No one could have foreseen
many of the developments just listed early in the twentieth century:
many were not anticipated even ten or fifteen years ago. Who even a
decade ago could have concluded that "homosexual marriage" was
a right guaranteed by the Massachusetts state constitution (a document
written by John Adams)?
It sometimes seems that there is nothing left for judges to invent.
But then one recalls the cautionary tale of the patent office
commissioner who resigned in the nineteenth century because he believed
all significant inventions had already been made. We may rely upon the
apparently endless creativity of judges to continue to find new socially
disintegrating rights in various federal, state, and foreign
constitutions.
Though it may seem a matter for wonder that the public and its
elected representatives accept all this with so little resistance, they
are in fact almost completely helpless. Those who devised and ratified
the Constitution had no idea what courts could become and so they built
no safeguards against imperialistic judges. The framers carefully
provided means for Congress to check the President and for the President
to restrain Congress, but they provided no means for either of those
branches to check the judiciary. Impeachment is utterly impracticable.
The Jeffersonians tried that in order to replace the Federalist Supreme
Court and failed. Impeachment is almost never successful unless bribery
is involved. Some commentators suggest reliance on the congressional
power under the Constitution to make exceptions to the Supreme
Court's appellate jurisdiction. But even if the Court would accept
the subtraction of its authority over a class of cases--and it is by no
means certain that it would--the Constitution also provides that
jurisdiction over federal constitutional questions lodges in state
courts, many of which are at least as activist as the U.S. Court, and
neither Congress nor state legislatures could remove it.
Only a draconian response to unconstitutional court decisions
remains. The Massachusetts Supreme Judicial Court has ordered the
state's legislature to amend its statutory law to permit homosexual
marriage. It is, or should seem, extraordinary that a court should order
a legislature to amend and enact laws. The underlying decision is so
self-evidently an act of judicial usurpation of the legislative
function, and so wrong as a matter of constitutional interpretation,
that it might seem that any self-respecting legislature would simply
refuse to comply, and if it did comply, that the governor would veto the
bill. So accustomed have we become to judicial supremacy, however, that
such a course sounds revolutionary. Yet there must be some means of
standing up to a court that itself is behaving unconstitutionally in
very serious matters.
The classic hypothetical supposes that in 1860 the southern states
had claimed a constitutional right to secede (they would have had a
plausible argument) and that the Court, most of whose members were
southerners, had agreed and ordered Lincoln to let the states go
peacefully. Should Lincoln have obediently removed federal troops from
Fort Sumter and ordered the armed forces not to interfere with the
secession? The question answers itself. Some issues are too important
for courts to determine national policy. We may disagree about which
issues are that crucial, but that there must be a line beyond which
courts must not go and demand obedience seems incontrovertible. At
present, we have no criteria for drawing such lines. The Court has
employed the political question doctrine to discipline itself, but that
doctrine rests with the discretion of the Court.
It is understandable that no legislature or governor has taken such
action in the past. (Lincoln provides an exception. During the Civil War
he suspended the writ of habeas corpus before Congress, which alone had
the authority to do so, acted to ratify what he had done.) We have
become so used to the supremacy of the courts that it might be
politically dangerous for legislators to stand against judges. Defying a
court's constitutional ruling, moreover, might set a dangerous
precedent. The power of courts rests entirely upon moral authority
granted by the perception that they stand on principle. Our sense of
their fragility and fear of harming their capacity to do good restrains
us. Thus the vulnerability of courts paradoxically renders them almost
invulnerable. But what has happened in Massachusetts, and is likely to
happen nationally, is so outrageous that a stand against an
imperialistic court might be popular, and it would certainly be wise,
because it would be a last-stand defense of the constitutional order.
The problems with all efforts to rein in runaway courts, including
the appointment of restrained judges, are manifold, but two require
mention. The first is that there is a large and powerful constituency
for activist courts. The Olympians, who control virtually all the means
of opinion formation, are also powerful in the Senate and will resist by
any means available, including, as they are now demonstrating, the
filibuster, to stop any effort to attempt to restrict courts to their
proper constitutional function. In that they will be supported by a
large portion of the non-Olympian public, which simply does not know
what is in the Constitution. The judiciary, and most especially the
Supreme Court, is held in higher esteem, with the possible exception of
the churches, than any other institution, public or private. And this
seems true in all Western nations where judges have acquired the power
of judicial review.
One reason, oddly enough, is that the Court is held in high esteem
precisely because it is unelected, unrepresentative, and
unaccountable--which is to say that the justices are not seen as
politicians. To survive and to get anything done, politicians have to
make expedient compromises. Judges, or so it is mistakenly believed, are
not politicians but men and women of principle, untarnished by
compromise. The public does not stop to consider that compromise gives
all the players some of what they want while judicial principle usually
turns out to be a zero-sum game, and, moreover that the non-elite
majority is usually the loser in ideological litigation. The preference
for judges over legislators seems to signify a weariness with and
distrust of democracy. If so, that is an ominous development and one
encouraged by judges who have insisted not only upon their supremacy but
upon their superior virtue. The appearance of other authoritarians
stronger even than the Court would be an expensive cure for the ills of
radical autonomy. We may come at last, though perhaps too late, to see
the wisdom of Judge Learned Hand's observation about "the
fatuity of the system which grants such powers to men it insists shall
be independent of popular control."