"Does technology make us do it?".
Schmidt, Lawrence E. ; Marratto, Scott ; Cayley, David 等
RE: "DOES TECHNOLOGY MAKE US DO IT?" BY ARTHUR SCHAFER
(DECEMBER 2008)
It is hard to know how to respond to Arthur Schafer's
"review" of The End of Ethics in a Technological Society. The
review, which combines Schafer's own reflections on technology with
a serious mischaracterization of our view of ethics and religion, will
make it difficult for a reader of the LRC to gain any idea concerning
the contents of our book.
The book is about the role of technological innovation in creating
the ethical challenges raised by economic growth, environmental
degradation, nuclear power, modern weapons of war, the transformation of
reproduction and genetic manipulation. We devote a chapter to each of
these in turn. As to our ethical approach, contrary to what Schafer
asserts, it is not based in any type of "religious
traditionalism" or biblical fundamentalism. We repeatedly deny that
these challenges can be met by some sort of "return to former
values" achieved by engaging in "nostalgia for the distant
past."
We fully share Schafer's worry about the implications of a
world view that places human beings "at the centre of the
universe:' However, we do not share his confidence that
techno-science has relieved us of such pretensions. On the contrary, we
think that blind faith in technology has intensified this dangerous
illusion. Apparently, for Schafer, that is enough to accuse us of
religious obscurantism: "The supernatural, they insist, will
provide all the answers we need:' This is not our view. Our
analysis draws on the insight, articulated by many contemporary
philosophers and theorists of science, that the ideology of modern
techno-science conceals a fundamental prejudice: the belief that nature
is best understood when it is viewed "objectively," as an
ensemble of value-neutral "facts." We say, on the contrary,
that techno-science can never be value-free and the belief that it can
be is one of the fatal delusions of our age. Ethical reflection must
inform science; it is not enough for ethics to come on the scene only
after the scientists have reinterpreted our life-world as so much raw
material.
We are critical of the consequentialist, cost-benefit analysis that
Schafer propounds. How are we to balance the likely benefits and harms
in the absence of any ethical principles beyond the utilitarian
calculus? Who is to decide what the balance is? In our calculations
concerning the consequences of the expansion of nuclear energy or the
refusal to severely limit our carbon emissions, we are not only
undertaking risks to the health of our own lives but to that of future
generations who will have no say in whether they wish to accept them.
The world in which we and our grandchildren must actually live may well
turn out to be something quite different from the projected world of
scientific and consequentialist calculation.
Schafer asserts that we endorse "technological
determinism" On the contrary, we conclude our book with the
statement that "our fate is not determined, and reflection on the
nihilism of modern ethics can open up the possibility of meditation on
the true end of ethics"
LAWRENCE E. SCHMIDT
TORONTO, ONTARIO
SCOTT MARRATTO
WEST PENNANT, NOVA SCOTIA
When I noticed that your review of The End of Ethics in a
Technological Society had the subhead "Two very different views on
ethics in the modern age" I looked--in vain--for the title of the
second book under review. However, I soon realized that the second
"very different view" referred to the position of your
reviewer, Arthur Schafer. Then I read his scornful and derisory review,
and wondered whether your subhead might have been put there defensively.
Perhaps you were so embarrassed by Professor Schafer's unfairness
to the book you had asked him to review that you wanted to make it
appear that what was going on was a debate and not a hatchet job. In any
event, no debate ever occurs, since your readers must depend on Schafer
for a digest of Schmidt's and Marratto's views, and Schafer is
so utterly unsympathetic to their premises that he can barely recognize
that they have a position, let alone give a fair account of what it is.
Schmidt and Marratto's meditations on technology belong to a
lineage that includes, among others, Martin Heidegger, George Grant,
Jacques Ellul and Ivan Illich, all of whom are cited in their book. All
these thinkers in one way or another came to the conclusion that one can
no longer think about technology by reasoning about the costs and
benefits of this or that technique--windmills good, nuclear reactors
had; yes to in vitro fertilization, no to cloning; etc. They have argued
that technology now amounts to a comprehensive world view--a fate,
George Grant said--that prevents people from thinking in
non-instrumental ways. Technology, in other words, is something more
than just the ensemble of techniques currently in use. Two consequences
follow: first, it has to be recognized that, if technology is a stance
toward the world and not just a set of tools, then the essence of
technology is, as Heidegger says, "nothing technological" hut
must arise from some deeper disposition of our now worldwide
civilization; and, second, it is scarcely possible for those within this
comprehensive fate/stance/paradigm to get outside of it, though those
who listen may discern what George Grant called "intimations of
deprival."
The End of Ethics in a Technological Society broods on this
difficulty: how is ethical reflection on technology possible when
technology is also the horizon within which the reflection is supposed
to occur? Arthur Schafer takes the view, if I understand him rightly,
that technologies have costs and benefits, and we can sort out which is
which in a realm called "politics" that stands outside
technology. This would be all right if he recognized that another view
is possible, and that politics, on Schmidt and Marratto's account,
is itself no more than a branch of technological science, but he does
not seem able or willing to give his opponents even this much credit.
Instead he simply calls them impertinent and inappropriate names. He
diagnoses technophobia. He calls them religious traditionalists. He
implies, by his account of how "science makes it difficult to hang
onto the comforting notion that humankind is at the centre of the
universe" that Schmidt and Marratto may still believe in Ptolemaic
astronomy. He claims that they appeal "to 'miracle, mystery
and authority' in the spirit of Dostoevsky's Grand
Inquisitor"
Schmidt and Marratto, in Arthur Schafer's eyes, are
mystagogues and obscurantists in the grip of a phobia. On my reading of
their book, this is untrue and grotesquely unfair. I'm sure The End
of Ethics could have been constructively criticized, but this would have
required your reviewer to engage with the book instead of patronizing
it.
DAVID CAYLEY
TORONTO, ONTARIO