The scientistic revolution.
Callahan, Gene
The Invention of Science: A New History of the Scientific
Revolution, David Wootton, Harper, 784 pages
David Wootton here has written not a single book but two
intertwined ones. One of them, written by Wootton the highly skilled
professional historian, seeks to overturn the recent consensus on the
"Scientific Revolution," which has been that talk of a
revolution is overblown, and what really happened was a gradual
development of older ideas into what we now regard as modern science. In
this work, Wootton mines his sources to great effect, arguing that, in
fact, the Scientific Revolution really did represent a dramatic break
with earlier approaches to understanding nature.
But mixed with that historical work is another in which David
Wootton, advocate of science as the pinnacle of human knowledge, hopes
to convince readers of his worldview. Here Wootton is forwarding a value
judgment about the relative worth of the different ways in which humans
attempt to comprehend our world. Wootton's great achievement in his
historical work should not intimidate us into acquiescing to the
conclusion of his philosophical work--which is not, and could not
possibly be, the conclusion of an historical investigation since it is
not about what really happened in the past.
In On History, the philosopher Michael Oakeshott explains that we
can approach the past with various attitudes, and those different
attitudes create different pasts. We may contemplate the past in a state
of artistic reverie, as Marcel Proust did in his masterpiece, In Search
of Lost Time. This produces a "poetic past," a past mined for
its artistic yield. More commonly, we encounter what Oakeshott called
the "practical past": the past employed as a source of
guidance to steer us through present perplexities. Oakeshott argues that
the "historical past" is different from these other attitudes
towards the past, in that its special focus is strictly upon what the
historical evidence indicates really occurred, and not the beauty of
those events or their lessons for us today. And it is that past that
professional historians are uniquely qualified to comment upon.
Wootton knows that attempts to cloak value judgments as historical
conclusions have been subject to serious critique in the past, so he
takes time out from his central theses to forestall similar criticism.
He sets up a straw-man version of Herbert Butterfield--who in his work
on the philosophy of history was an ally of Oakeshott--and then knocks
that scarecrow down. Wootton says of Butterfield:
In 1931 he had published The
Whig Interpretation of History
... Butterfield argued ... it was not
the historians' job to praise those
people in the past whose values
and opinions they agreed with
and criticize those with whom
they disagreed; only God had
the right to sit in judgment ... It
should be obvious that he was not
right about this: no one, I trust,
would want to read an account of
slavery written by someone incapable
of passing judgment.
But this is a caricature of what Butterfield wrote. Consider the
following quotes from The Whig Interpretation of History: "There
can be no complaint against the historian who personally and privately
has his preferences and antipathies"; "If [the historian]
deals in moral judgements at all he is trying to take upon himself a new
dimension, and he is leaving that realm of historical explanation
..."
Butterfield quite explicitly says that, far from being
"incapable of passing judgment," it is fine for historians to
pass judgments as human beings. Butterfield personally is just as
capable of disliking slavery as Wootton. Butterfield's point,
however, is that the historian's job is to determine what happened
in the past, and condemning or praising various participants in that
past is no part of that job. This is analogous to the principle that, as
a physician, it is not the doctor's job to pass judgment on the
sick who appear before him but to cure them. Once Stalin or Gandhi is
cured, the doctor is free to disparage the first and praise the latter.
One may agree or disagree with this separation of roles, but it is far
from the silliness that Wootton attributes to Butterfield.
Woottons great achievement in historical scholarship in The
Invention of Science is a serious challenge to the
"gradualist" thesis of scientific development. Wootton
presents extensive evidence, much of it linguistic, that something
genuinely new was going on in the 16th and 17th centuries, something
essentially different from the attempts of the ancient Greeks or
medieval schoolmen at understanding the physical world. (An important
caveat here: Wootton certainly does not subscribe to the popular canard
that the Middle Ages were a time of abysmal ignorance, during which no
scientific advances occurred, just as his opponents would never deny
that Copernicus, Galileo, Kepler, Harvey, Boyle, Pascal, Newton, etc.
made significant advances over their medieval predecessors. The
professional debate is over how radical that advance was.)
In particular, Wootton attempts to show that the concepts of facts,
experiments, natural laws, scientific theories, and evidence all either
altered radically or indeed came into being during the 16th and 17th
centuries. He claims, backed by extensive source material, that the very
word "fact" only entered the English language in the middle of
the 1600s. For anyone interested in the twists and turns of the debate
on whether there really was a revolution in thought during those
centuries, Woottons work is must-reading.
What's more, along the way we are treated to various wonderful
historical anecdotes. For instance, we discover that what scientists
consider simply out of the question has differed considerably over time.
As an example:
Eighteenth-century English and
French scientists rejected the
ample testimony as to the reality
of meteorites, as we reject stories
of alien abduction. On 13 September
1768 a large meteorite fell
... [in] Pays de la Loire. Numerous
people (all of them peasants) saw
it fall. Three members of the Royal
Academy of Sciences (including
young Lavoisier) were sent to investigate.
They concluded that
lightning had struck a lump of
sandstone on the ground; the idea
of rocks falling from outer space
was simply ridiculous.
I also learned something new about Descartes. I knew that his claim
to have thought up everything in his philosophy from scratch was false:
scholars have found many elements of it in his own schoolbooks. But I
had thought he was simply deceiving himself. Based on Wootton's
description of how Descartes vehemently denied his considerable debt to
Beeckman, however, it now seems to me more likely that he was
consciously promoting what he knew to be a lie.
But now we must turn our attention to the more dubious of
Wootton's two projects, that of asserting the superiority of
science to all other forms of knowledge. Speaking of "fact,"
"experiment," "hypothesis," "theory," and
"laws of nature," he claims that these terms "served as a
passage between Montaigne's world, a world of belief and misplaced
conviction, and our world, the world of reliable and effective
knowledge."
This is a remarkable contention: before science, human beings had
no "reliable knowledge"! Our ancestors weren't sure
whether planting seeds or stones would grow wheat. When they went to
hunt deer, they didn't know if they should put arrowheads or fur on
the end of their arrows. If they were thirsty, they were uncertain if
they should ingest water or sand. When freezing, sometimes they put on
furs, but other times they lay down naked in the snow: who knew which
would work? Wootton makes a passing nod to the reliability of practical
knowledge before that provocative quote, but he clearly regards it as
nescience when compared to scientific knowledge.
He does provide examples of extremely fanciful beliefs our
forebears held, for example, that garlic negates the power of magnets.
But as Wootton himself notes, before the compass, magnets were rarely
encountered and of no practical import. To place this in perspective,
magnets were for people before 1400 as conservatives are to Park Slope
progressives today: the people in the first term of the relationship
have heard rumors that the entities in the second term exist, but they
never have encountered and never expect to encounter them. Thus, just as
a modern Park Slope resident can believe the most outlandish things
about conservatives with no practical consequence, so could a European
of 1100 believe pretty much anything about magnets without it mattering
much.
The misapprehension about knowledge plaguing Wootton becomes clear
in this passage: "Evidence-Indices [e.g., smoke as a sign of fire]
may always have been used in an unthinking way by people going about
their daily business; but to elevate them into being a reliable basis
for theoretical knowledge" Wootton claims the Scientific Revolution
replaced a world of profound ignorance with one that for the first time
contains true knowledge because Wootton does not consider ordinary
people's day-to-day activities to entail thought at all. But this
is wrong: to move from an index to what that index signifies is an act
of interpretation. In other words, it is thinking. It may not be great
thinking, it may not be theorizing, and the move may have become so
habitual that the thinker barely notices the thought involved. But
nevertheless, it is an act of intelligence, and constitutes a genuine
form of knowledge, without which the human species would not have
survived a week after it had evolved.
Given his embrace of scientism, it is unsurprising that Wootton
deems the Scientific Revolution the most important event in human
history since the Neolithic Revolution. So it is, per Wootton, more
important than, for instance, the Axial Age, the discovery of
monotheism, the creation of philosophy, or the rise of Christianity. But
what historical evidence lies behind such a claim? Wootton might argue
that the Scientific Revolution transformed humans' material life
more than any of those other happenings, but why should "material
transformation" be the decisive measure of "importance"?
After all, "importance" is itself not a material thing that
can be measured. And so, when I claim that Wootton has produced both a
great work of historical scholarship and a slipshod piece of
philosophical argumentation, I wonder how his materialist bias might
measure my claim.
Gene Callahan teaches economics and computer science at St.
Joseph's College in Brooklyn and is the author of Oakeshott on Rome
and America.