Is social mobility a myth?
Callahan, Gene
The Son Also Rises: Surnames and the History of Social Mobility,
Gregory Clark, Princeton University Press, 384 pages
Most people intuit that coming from the "right sort" of
family is a big advantage in life, while being from the "wrong side
of the tracks" is a serious disability. And they suspect that these
advantages and disadvantages persist, as demonstrated by the continuing
prominence of, say, people whose ancestors "came over on the
Mayflower" among the upper crust in America.
The difficulty with this intuitive understanding is that
social-science research does not seem to back it up. Psychologists,
sociologists, and economists have found rates of social mobility that
ought to wipe out all familial advantage or disadvantage within three to
five generations. Furthermore, the rates of social mobility found in
most of these studies differed greatly from one country to another,
with, for instance, Sweden scoring much higher than the United States in
this regard.
So is this belief in the persistence of familial advantage just a
popular delusion? That is the question that U.C. Davis economist Gregory
Clark takes up in his new book, and the answer he found surprised even
him. He set out thinking the social-science consensus was correct,
intending only to extend those findings further into the past. But the
evidence changed his mind: social scientists have been measuring
mobility the wrong way, and in fact the popular intuition is on target.
The key to understanding Clark's thesis is his division of the
factors that make for success in worldly affairs into an inherited
component and a random component. ("Inherited" here need not
mean "genetic": one could inherit, for instance, one's
family's reputation.) Most previous studies have focused on
movements in social class from one generation to the next. But as Clark
explains using his two-factor model, such a limited time frame means
that the random component of social achievement is going to have an
undue influence. This is not an esoteric notion: think, for instance, of
a member of a high-achievement family who suffers a terrible car
accident as a youth, leaving him with severe brain damage. It is quite
likely that whether measured by income, profession, or educational
level, that member will do significantly worse than the family average.
But this accident will not change the family's basic
"social competency" (Clark's term). If the injured son
has children, they will not inherit his brain damage. Their level of
achievement will tend to return toward the family baseline. So, Clark
suggests, if we really want to measure social mobility, we should look
at the social status of families over many generations.
The way he and his team of researchers did so is ingenious: they
found relatively rare surnames primarily associated with high social
standing, such as the names taken by the nobility in Sweden, or low
social standing, such as names characteristic of the Travellers in
England, and tracked their appearance in historical records showing
elite status, such as admissions to top universities--for Oxford and
Cambridge, we have data dating back 800 years-large estates bequeathed
in probate, or presence in high-status professions such as law and
medicine.
The results confirm that the popular intuition has been correct all
along:
The intergenerational correlation
in all the societies for which we
construct surname estimates-medieval
England, modern England,
the United States, India, Japan,
Korea, China, Taiwan, Chile,
and even egalitarian Sweden--is
... much higher than conventionally
estimated. Social status is inherited
as strongly as any biological
trait, such as height.
What's more, it matters little what social policies are put in
place: Clark and his team find that social mobility remains nearly
constant over time despite the arrival of free public education, the
reduction of nepotism in government, modern economic growth, the
expansion of the franchise, and redistributive taxation.
Clark introduces us to the reality of this persistence of status
with a few notable examples. For instance, the family of famed diarist
Samuel Pepys has had high social status from 1500 until today, while
that of Sir Timothy Berners-Lee, creator of the World Wide Web,
apparently has been upper crust since the Domesday Book of 1086. And in
noting the many prominent members of the Darwin family, he remarks,
"It is also interesting that Darwin's fourth-generation
descendants include Adrian Maynard Keynes and William Huxley
Darwin." The elite tend to marry the elite.
But if such isolated examples were the crux of Clark's case,
it would be a rather flimsy one: even if the standard social science
take on mobility were correct, we would expect to find notable
exceptions to the general rule. His main backing for his thesis is a
number of studies conducted across many countries and many centuries.
Nevertheless the anecdotes are an important aspect of this work: they
are a component of how Clark continually turns what could have been an
extremely dry executive summary of a number of demographic surveys into
a consistently engaging book.
While I am no expert on the literature concerning social mobility,
it seems to me that Clark has backed his thesis with very significant
and relevant data. But I would want to see responses from those
defending the more traditional social-science view on social mobility
before unconditionally awarding the victory to Clark.
One way in which Clark gauges the social status of an ethnic group
is to see how the proportion of doctors in the group compares to the
proportion in the population as a whole. This measure is not flawless:
in the case of Filipinos, I think it must overstate their status, as
they seem to be a people that just love the medical professions. (Having
married a Filipina, I have found that roughly 80 percent of my in-laws
are doctors or nurses.) But it is a good rough gauge nonetheless. Clark
uses this gauge to evaluate the elite status of various ethnic groups by
looking at the surnames of registered physicians in America. Which
ethnicities top the charts of U.S. doctors?
Here they are, starting with a group that produces physicians at 13
times the national average: 1) Coptic Egyptians, 2) Indian Hindus (about
12 times the average), 3) Indian Christians, 4) Iranian Muslims, 5)
Lebanese Christians, 6) Ashkenazi Jews, 7) Sephardic Jews, 8) Koreans,
9) Chinese, 10) Filipinos, 11) black Africans (we've reached about
four times the average here), 12) Greeks, 13) Armenians, 14) Japanese,
15) Vietnamese, 16) black Haitians.
So, what do we find among the top 16 doctor-producing groups in the
United States? No European Protestant group. This calls into question
the notion of "white privilege": being a physician is a
high-income, high-status profession. If white privilege is a significant
social force, why doesn't a single European-Protestant ethnicity
appear among this top 16? Why do our populations of black Africans and
black Haitians produce doctors at significantly higher rates than
Dutch-Americans, Swedish-Americans, or Finnish-Americans, all groups
that make up a low enough percentage of our population that they cannot
be said to constitute the average merely by their numerical
preponderance? Clark does not try to deny that many white Americans
harbor prejudice against non-whites. But this prejudice, however real,
apparently is not preventing many non-white ethnic groups from achieving
high social status.
And if white privilege is really a major force in the United
States, what are we to make of the persistently low social status of
French Canadian immigrants, a group of people that is, after all, pretty
darned white, and many of whom have been in the States for a couple of
centuries? (I had no idea this low social status was even the case
before reading Clark's book. Did you?) Clark explains this fact as
being due to a double-selection for low social achievement: the initial
population of French Canada came primarily from the lower-status
population of France, and then it was chiefly lower-status Quebecois who
emigrated to America. Americans of French Canadian descent are in fact
reverting to the mean and becoming more like the rest of our population;
but starting from a very low initial position, they are doing so slowly,
just as Clark's model predicts.
Clark discusses several apparent exceptions to his "law of
social mobility." He finds they all fall into one of two
categories. A group with exceptionally lengthy high or low social status
may persist in that status because members do not intermarry with other
groups, such as the Brahmins in India. Or the group in question may
experience selective in--and out-migration, such as the Travellers in
England--whom Clark argues are not ethnically distinct from the general
population--so that lower-status people who want a migrant lifestyle
joined the Travellers, while those wishing to move up in status let the
group.
A law in this book is Clark's tendency to treat the abstract
model he has developed to capture his findings as if it were an actual
causal agent operating in the real world. Consider the following
passage:
If a group deviates in the current
generation from the mean social
status, set at zero, then on average
will have deviated by a smaller
amount, determined by b, in the
previous generation. A group of
families now of high social status
have arrived at the status over
many generations by a series of
upward steps from the mean. And
the length and speed of that ascent,
paradoxically, are determined by
the rate of persistence, b.
This is a perfect example of what Alfred North Whitehead referred
to as "the fallacy of misplaced concreteness." In reality,
what we have are particular, concrete individuals, members of families,
doing this and that in the world and succeeding or failing to some
degree or another. From a large number of such individuals, Clark has
devised a model of changes in social status. Within that model, there is
a parameter, which he calls b, that is determined by the average speed
of ascent or descent in social status among family members.
It is these actual, concrete activities that make b what it is. But
Clark gets this exactly backwards: for him, this abstract entity, b, is
somehow controlling the actions of real-world individuals. It is like
thinking that a baseball player's batting average determines how
often he will get hits, as if somehow a number on the TV screen can
influence his swings, rather than how often he gets hits determining his
batting average.
Enough with the details: what is the general upshot of Clark's
findings? For one thing, even if we believe that social mobility ought
to be as high as possible, his data do not support the idea that we
ought to undertake major social engineering projects with the goal of
increasing it. If public education, a universal adult franchise,
redistributive taxation, or even the radical egalitarianism of
Mao's China did not alter social mobility in any significant way,
just what would we have to do to dramatically change it?
We might have to adopt the sort of dystopian measures that Kurt
Vonnegut contemplated in his short story "Harrison Bergeron,"
where people who are too intelligent are subjected to deafening noises
that continually interrupt their thoughts. If that sort of thing is the
only ix available, then perhaps we ought to accept social mobility for
what it is and welcome the contributions to social life made by the more
adept without seeking to cripple them with equal-outcome producing
handicaps.
Clark notes that his findings do not indicate that we will have
perpetual upper and lower classes: although social mobility for families
is slower than others had estimated, it is real, and it means that over
the centuries no particular clan will remain on top or at the bottom. In
the meantime, Clark suggests a broad adoption of a Scandinavian-type
social-welfare model: after all, if social status is largely a matter of
being born into the right or wrong family, why shouldn't public
policy act to balance out such an effect of mere luck? Whether Clark is
correct in drawing such a conclusion from his data, I leave it to my
reader to decide. But if such issues concern you, you should read this
important book.
Gene Callahan teaches economics at SUNY Purchase and is the author
of Oakeshott on Rome and America.