Review of Plato and intellectual development: A new theoretical framework emphasising the higher-order pedagogy of the Platonic Dialogues.
Freebody, Peter
Review of Plato and intellectual development: A new theoretical framework emphasising the higher-order pedagogy of the Platonic Dialogues.
Review of Plato and intellectual development: A new theoretical
framework emphasising the higher-order pedagogy of the Platonic
Dialogues
by
Susanna Saracco, London, Palgrave, 2017
Why review a book on Plato in a journal dedicated to language and
literacy education? Some answers come to hand: Almost all we know of
Plato is due to his written products, so his contributions, and in a
sense even his identity, are arch-literate constructions. It is also
certain that Plato's teacher, Socrates, not only refused to read or
write, but was also, at best, semi-literate (Harris, 1989). Plato's
decision to render his teacher's dialogues into writing was based
on the premise that these highly contextualised, dynamic exchanges could
be reworked into texts--the hope being, accurately as it turned out,
that these 'readings of talk' might prove instructive across
time and place. Socrates had become a demi-god for many Athenians; how
much of the records of the Socratic Dialogues was Plato's
remodelling of the words of this demi-god into his own intellectual and
moral likeness is impossible to determine, simply because there are no
other documents to tell us (Griswold, 200 (1)).
But there are also practical reasons why literacy teachers might
take some interest in a philosopher's expedition into Plato's
take on the human intellect: Plato documented the arguments that
Socrates had with a variety of initially articulate and
self-assured--but eventually flummoxed--interlocutors, turning those
arguments into written language. It is a commonplace to point out that
teachers spend a lot of time talking with students back-and-forth about
matters that reappear, or that have already appeared, in printed
curricular texts, and that students are assessed in large part via their
ability, in writing, to synthesise the written forms of these
curriculum-related knowledge with the spoken interactions that frame and
interpret that knowledge. We still acknowledge Socrates' take on
productive exchange: 'Socratic teaching' generally is taken to
mean posing, re-posing, and reworking the kinds of questions that push
learners into uncertainty, and on toward more complex and coherent forms
of thought, and into more precise ways of using words that better
reflect the particular area of inquiry at hand. (It's an ironic
title for Socrates, given that he insisted he was not a teacher, in
Plato, Apology, 33a-b.)
The transformation of spoken interactions into writing raises
questions that contemporary educators should be interested in: How much
do we know about the relationship between spoken dialogue and written
texts, a relationship that underpins much of what counts as teaching and
learning in contemporary schooling? What are the different strengths and
weaknesses of these two modes of communication? How are these strengths
and weaknesses recognised and capitalised on in educational settings?
How are they, and how should they be 'played off against' one
another'? That is, how can--or should--educators know how to
mix-and-match spoken and written forms to help novice learners? If we
take seriously Olson's (1977) assertion of forty years ago that the
printed word is the base on which modern education systems are built,
then how it is that students might be productively alerted to, and
worked into, the talk-text relationship as it is acted out in the
variety of demands that make up the school curriculum areas (Freebody,
Barton & Chan, 2014).
In her recent book Plato and intellectual development Susanna
Saracco sets out to convince us that Plato's project was about the
continual stimulation of engagement with the ways we produce and use
knowledge, especially text-based knowledge, and how that engagement
comes with active reading--inquisitive, sceptical,
'take-it-personally' reading. She starts with the idea that a
genuine reader participates in an intellectual collaboration, and it is
this 'interpretative effort' as she calls it, that needs to
form both the basis, and the full potential of contemporary
literacy-based education. At the outset Saracco makes it clear that she
has no interest in claiming that Plato could foresee subsequent
developments in inquiry and research; rather she argues, and
demonstrates throughout the book, that Plato's message has powerful
resonance for educators who want to confront more deeply the challenges
they face in their work.
The chapters proceed to outline and illustrate the basic form of
Plato's position: To read is to contribute; a text is to be
recreated by a collaborating co-author, occasion by occasion; the role
of readers 'is not flattened to that of students who can merely
absorb the content proposed by the teacher' (p. 6). The
'epistemic game' (p. 25), as Socrates constructed it, sets out
the rules of engagement for the exchange: The reader, like
Socrates' interlocutor, accepts an invitation to enter a dialogue
knowing that the chances of winning are pretty slim. The
interlocutor's acceptance is sweetened partly by the apparent
straight-forwardness of the initial ideas that open the exchanges--just
simple, common-sense observations--even though the veteran Socratic
knows that the more self-evident the beginning statements, the rougher
the ride will be. The bases of this jointly-built 'game'
consist of Socrates' probing questions and the initially confident
but increasingly agreements and disagreements of the interlocutor to the
point of 'perplexity', where the interlocutor's initial
position is seen to be based on a mixture of myth and incoherence rather
than on rational thought.
These kinds of sometimes 'stagey', often uncomfortable,
and always risky exchanges between teacher and learner form the
foundational setting for engagement. Plato (and Saracco) invest heavily
on that setting's ability to foster a 'knowledge of the purely
intelligible' that is fundamentally grounded on an intellectual and
moral 'detachment from the tangible', an appreciation of, and
skill in the deployment of, coherent abstract thought in the search for
principled, rational solutions. Teachers who orchestrate sequences of
challenging questions make a similar investment--that, from
participating in these exchanges, students can read and write with more
substance, with more at stake.
The deep message is about the need to model active collaborative
engagement with texts, and, directly and indirectly, with the
writer's intellectual and moral reasoning practices, to rework and
refit those reasoning practices into the reader's time and place
via dialogic work with a teacher that is forceful but that has clear
rules of engagement. The critique, extension, aggregation, and redesign
of authors' arguments together constitute the base of
Saracco's line in this book and, she would argue, of Plato's
overall project:
Plato's written words are stimulations which help the readers
to develop an awareness of their rational capacity. This awareness has
to be used to reach the highest phase of rational development (p. 5)
Driving Saracco's argument is a specifically literacy-related
view of what she calls 'theoretical adulthood', of the
intellectual, cognitive, and moral features that constitute this
adulthood, and of the intensive work that needs to be done to attain it,
when we engage in serious exchanges with teachers, learners, and
authors. For Saracco this 'theoretical adulthood' is
facilitated but not guaranteed--by the ability to read and write
(Thomas, 2009); it is earned only through a particular kind of
high-engagement, collaborative, risk-taking reading and a form of
writing that invites and encourages such intensive collaboration. Plato,
and two-and-a-half millennia later Sarocco, name these as the essential
features of learning to read and write. This view puts pressure on
educators to make the content really matter to students (as shown, for
example, in Hynd, Holschuh, and Hubbard, 2004, in the case of History).
Saracco's own engagement in this work is evident on every
page: We encounter a combination of complex technical argument and
downright exuberance; she finds Plato's insights, his respect for
the intellect of the reader, and the range of implications for education
even today 'astonishing'. Her own reading of Plato, and in
turn of his reading of his teacher Socrates, embodies the enthusiastic
engagement that she espouses. She delivers, in the writing, on the sense
of intense intellectual and moral collaboration that the written word
offers us. She points out that Plato regularly reminded his readers
there was 'more to discover on this subject, and this is something
that they have to do' (p. 3). One unique feature of this book is
that the author provides an addendum in which she outlines an online
dialogic program, developed by Saracco and colleagues, entitled Journey
to critical inquiry. The program has been developed for upper primary
years school students and is based on high levels of engagement in
important topics, and focused questioning skills, all based on the
Platonic dialogues.
Detracting from this book are occasional clumsy expressions or
wordings that are not native to academic English, as well as an
alarmingly skimpy index. But Saracco shows us how the inclination to
seek solutions to contemporary problems in the ideas and words of
ancient thinkers is as old as modernity itself; that it can indeed be
thought of as one of the characteristics of modernity that, while the
past is, by definition, 'out of date', it is the
responsibility of genuinely modern thinkers to retrieve those elements
that provide direction to the construction of thought, morality, and
daily practice. Saracco's book shows us that this need be neither a
retreat from the tangles of the present into the nostalgia of simpler
days or a simpleminded reliance on some best-of, 'timeless nuggets
of wisdom' from the past. The project, as she demonstrates, is both
crucial and necessarily ongoing. Its preoccupations with thought, logic,
and the talk-text relationship connect with philosophers', social
scientists', and psychologists' inquiries into the nature of
science and human cognition (e.g., Deutsch, 2011) and in the nature of
human judgement (e.g., Kahneman, 2011).
Maybe in the end, the real interest in Plato and the potential
value for literacy educators of his and his mentor's work is that,
as Sarocco outlines, Socrates was sceptical about the benefits of these
new-fangled printed texts--their reckless tendency to find their way
into contexts where they would almost certainly be misunderstood and
misused, their ominous trick of luring people into believing they have
understood the message just because they have read the words, and their
false promise that writing offers us, even from a competent but shallow
reading, the status of public authority, the 'appearance of
wisdom'. The near-omnipresence of digital, online, and mobile
communication technologies shows no signs of easing his anxieties.
Almost two and a half millennia later, as we, and our students, swim
through oceans of 'news' (both fake, and only partly fake),
politicians' daily twitters, and globally-syndicated two-line
summaries of lengthy scientific reports on such complexities as economic
well being and climate deterioration, we have not yet proven Socrates
wrong in his complaint that literacy can actively help people to become,
in his words via Plato, more 'ill-informed' and therefore
'even harder to get on with'. Seems it's still down to
literacy educators themselves to be intense, collaborative readers, and,
through their patient daily work, to help produce a literate,
thoughtful, and informed citizenry that is up to the challenges of
democracy.
Note
(1) The first sentence of the book asserts: 'What you are
going to read is a non-standard work in Ancient Philosophy.' By the
end of the book, it has become clear that this is a colossal
understatement. It is also too modest; the book would be
'non-standard' in every conventional domain of inquiry.
References
Deutsch, D. (2011). The Beginning of infinity: Explanations that
transform the world. New York NY: Allan Lane.
Freebody, P., Barton, G. & Chan, E. (2014). Literacy Education:
'about being in the world'. In C. Leung & B.V. Street
(Eds.) The Routledge Companion to English Studies, (pp. 419-434).
London: Routledge.
Griswold, C., (Ed.) (2001). Platonic Writings/Platonic Readings.
University Park, PA: Pennsylvania State University Press.
Halliday, M.A.K. (1987). Spoken and written modes of meaning. In R.
Horowitz and S.J. Samuels (Eds.), Comprehending oral and written
language, (pp. 55-82). San Diego, CA: Academic Press.
Harris, W.V. (1989). Ancient literacy. Cambridge, MA: Harvard
University Press.
Hynd, C., Holschuh, J. & Hubbard, B. (2004). Thinking like a
historian: College students' reading of multiple historical
documents. Journal of Literacy Research, 36, 141-176.
Kahneman, D. (2011). Thinking, fast and slow. New York NY:
Macmillan.
Olson, D.R. (1977). The languages of instruction: The literate bias
of schooling In RC Anderson R. Spiro & W Montague (Eds.) Schooling
and the acquisition of knowledge, (pp. 65-89). Hillsdale: Erlbaum.
Plato Apology (translated B. Jowett). Retrieved 16/01/18 from
http://classics.mit.edu/Plato/apology.html
Thomas, R. (2009). 'Writing, Reading, Public and Private
Literacies: Functional Literacy and Democratic Literacy in Greece,'
in W.A. Johnson and H.N. Parker (Eds.) Ancient Literacies: The Culture
of Reading in Greece and Rome, (pp. 13-45). Oxford: Oxford University
Press.
Reviewed by Peter Freebody
The University of Wollongong
COPYRIGHT 2018 Australian Literacy Educators' Association
No portion of this article can be reproduced without the express written permission from the copyright holder.
Copyright 2018 Gale, Cengage Learning. All rights reserved.