An experimental study of alternative campaign finance systems: transparency, donations, and policy choices.
Fang, Hanming ; Shapiro, Dmitry ; Zillante, Arthur 等
An experimental study of alternative campaign finance systems: transparency, donations, and policy choices.
Just as troubling to a functioning democracy as classic quid pro
quo corruption is the danger that officeholders will decide issues not
on the merits or the desires of their constituents, but according to the
wishes of those who have made large financial contributions valued by
the officeholder.
--U.S. Supreme Court, McConnell v. FEC [540 U.S. 93 (2003)]
Sunlight is ... the best ... disinfectant.
--Justice Louis Brandeis, Other People's Money (National Home
Library Foundation, 1933, p. 62), quoted in Buckley v. Valeo [424 U.S.
1, 67, n. 80(1976)]
Just as the secret ballot makes it more difficult for candidates to
buy votes, a secret donation booth makes it more difficult for
candidates to sell access
or influence. The voting booth disrupts vote-buying because
candidates are uncertain how a citizen actually voted: anonymous
donations disrupt influence peddling because candidates are uncertain
whether givers actually gave what they say they gave. Just as
vote-buying plummeted with the secret ballot, campaign contributions
would sink with the secret donation booth.
--Bruce Ackerman and Ian Ayres, Voting with Dollars: A New Paradigm
for Campaign Finance (Yale University Press, 2002, p. 6)
I. INTRODUCTION
Campaign contributions and spending have many potential effects. On
the positive side, campaign resources allow the candidates to fund the
dissemination of useful information to voters. This information may lead
voters to make more informed electoral choices. On the negative side,
voters' interests may be harmed if candidates trade policy favors
to special interests, or large donors, in exchange for contributions.
While the First Amendment of the U.S. Constitution has repeatedly been
used by the Courts to strike down efforts to restrict overall campaign
spending, the first two quotes above suggest that the Supreme Court
nonetheless is concerned about the potential corruptive influence of
money in politics.
Throughout history, election procedures have been modified in order
to stem the degree of influence in elections and policy choices. Secret
ballots, for instance, are often thought of as protection for those who
vote against the winning candidate. However, once ballots were made
secret, candidates needed an alternative observable measure by which
they could reward those who supported them during their campaign.
Currently, nonanonymous campaign contributions may fill that role. A
candidate cannot tell if an individual votes for him but can see how
much money an individual contributes to his campaign. Based on that
knowledge, the candidate could choose policies to reward that individual
for monetary contributions. Indeed, the importance of money in American
electoral campaigns has been steadily increasing over time. In 2010, the
elected House of Representatives on average spent $1.4 million in their
campaigns, a 58% increase in real terms over the average expenditure in
1998. Over the same period, the average real cost of a winning Senate
campaign increased by 44% to $8.99 million. (1)
Given the suspicion that politicians, once elected, are likely to
reciprocate those who contributed to their election by enacting
favorable policies to their contributors, as forcefully expressed in the
quoted majority opinion of the U.S. Supreme Court in McConnell v. FEC
[540 U.S. 93 (2003)], there have been numerous attempts to control and
limit the influence of money in politics. The Federal Election Campaign
Act (FECA) of 1972 required candidates to disclose sources of campaign
contributions and campaign expenditures. Current campaign finance law at
the federal level requires candidate committees, party committees, and
political action committees to file periodic reports disclosing the
money they raise and spend. (2,3) Additionally, they must disclose
expenditures to any individual or vendor.
However, Yale Law School professors Bruce Ackerman and Ian Ayres,
in their 2002 book Voting with Dollars: A New Paradigm for Campaign
Finance, advocate a drastically different approach to reduce the
corruptive influence of money in politics. As highlighted in the third
quote above, a key part of Ackerman and Ayres' new paradigm
advocates full anonymity (FA), in which all contributions will be made
secretly and anonymously through the FEC, indicating which campaign they
will support. (4) Private donations would still be allowed but they
would be anonymous and the FEC would be the clearinghouse for these now
anonymous donations. To prevent donors from communicating to the
politician by donating a specially chosen amount, the FEC masks the
money and distributes it directly to the campaigns in randomized chunks
over a number of days.
What paradigm will be more effective in reducing the role of
corruptive influence of money in politics, the full transparency system
as advocated by FECA (1972), or the FA system as advocated by Ackerman
and Ayres? To date, little empirical evidence exists on this topic
because FA has rarely been utilized in elections. (5) In this article,
we use laboratory experiments to make a first step in addressing this
important question. (6) The advantage of the laboratory environment is
that it provides for a large degree of control for such factors as
individuals' preferences, the impact of donations, transparency,
voters' behavior, and so on. These factors may be difficult to
measure using data from actual elections, but are important in
determining the impact of the different systems. Furthermore, by fixing
all factors but one we can examine the role of the fixed factor. For
instance, we examine behavior between a candidate and his/her donors by
comparing different campaign finance systems--as characterized by their
transparency level--in terms of donors' contributions,
candidates' policy choices, and social welfare.
We consider three alternative systems as follows:
* Full Anonymity (FA). Donors are anonymous to the candidate. The
candidate observes neither donors' preferences nor the exact amount
contributed by each donor. Donors are anonymous to the public: the
donation impact on the electoral outcome does not depend on the
donor's identity. We interpret the FA system as corresponding to
the system advocated by Ackerman and Ayres (2002).
* Partial Anonymity (PA). The candidate observes the donors'
identities and their individual contribution amounts. Donors remain
anonymous to the public. As in FA, the donation impact does not depend
on the donor's identity. (7) Alternative interpretations for this
treatment are that voters are indifferent to the identities of
contributors to campaign funds, or that they may know who is
contributing the funds but do not know the preferred policies of the
donors.
* No Anonymity (NA). The candidate observes the donors'
identities and their individual contribution amounts. The donation
impact depends on the donor's identity. We assume that donations
from more (less) extreme donors are less (more) powerful. The NA system
will correspond to a perfectly enforced set of campaign finance
disclosure laws and can also be referred to as the Full Transparency
system. The PA and NA treatments represent the bounds of information
processing by voters, with PA being no information processing and NA
being full information processing.
These three systems are modeled as follows. There is a set of
potential policies represented by the interval [0,300]. There are two
candidates in the election and J potential donors. The candidate labeled
as Candidate 1 is played by one of the participants of the experiment.
The candidate labeled as Candidate 2 is nonstrategic and is
computerized. The candidates and donors have most preferred policies
(MPPs) and experience quadratic loss if the implemented policy differs
from their respective MPPs. Candidates' MPPs are common knowledge.
Only Candidate 1 can receive donations; thus in our model we abstract
away from candidate competition for donations as well as the
donor's choice of which candidate to support. In practice, it
appears as if large individual donors consistently contribute to the
same party across time. Using individual donor data from
opensecrets.org, 30 names appear on the top 100 list of individual
donors for both the 2010 and 2012 election cycles. Twenty-six people
contributed 100% to the same party each cycle, three additional people
gave over 90% to the same party each cycle, and only one individual made
100% of his contributions to one party in 2012 but less than 90% (74%)
to that party in 2010.
Donations do not directly benefit Candidate 1 but increase the
candidate's election probability. (8) Under the FA and PA systems,
each contributed dollar has the same impact on the election probability.
Under NA, the impact depends on donors' identities. Contributions
from donors with more extreme (closer to 0) MPPs have lower impact. The
reason that these contributions have a lower impact in the NA system is
because voters, who can observe donor identities in this system, would
be more likely to believe that the candidate would be captured by the
donor and implement policies further from the candidate's MPP. (9)
Candidates observe aggregate donations under all three systems, but in
PA and NA candidates also observe donors' MPPs and the donation
made by each individual donor. After observing this information,
Candidate 1 chooses a policy that will be implemented if he is elected.
We design nine treatments that vary along two dimensions: the
campaign finance system (FA, PA, or NA) and the number of donors (one,
two, or three). We find the following results. First, except under FA,
candidates are responsive to donations and they consistently choose
policies that favor donors. Under both PA and NA systems, larger
contributions prompt more favorable policies and candidates are willing
to deviate more when the donors are further away. FA, however, is
successful in limiting the impact of political contributions on policy
choice. Regression results show that donations in FA had either no
effect or a negative one on a candidate's willingness to deviate
from his MPP. Thus, we find that FA, and not Full Transparency (NA), is
most successful in reducing large donors' influence on policy
choice. We also show that having more donors weakens an individual
donor's influence in the NA and PA treatments. Given that most
campaign finance systems are a combination of PA and NA, this result
suggests that it might be desirable to foster competition between
donors. It also provides some justification for limiting contribution
amounts. We further explore this topic in the study by Fang, Shapiro,
and Zillante (2015).
Next, donor behavior is examined. Contributions are lowest under
FA, regardless of the number of donors, and are largest under PA with
one and two donors and under NA with three donors. The major and most
robust determinant of the contribution amount is the distance between
the MPPs of the donors and the candidate. As expected, donors who are
closer to the candidate donate more. In treatments with multiple donors,
there is evidence of free-riding and competition among donors.
Free-riding has a negative impact on individual donations and is
statistically significant in PA treatments. Competition has a positive
impact on individual donations and is statistically significant in all
two and three donor treatments except NA with three donors. The
competition effects in this article are similar to the effects of
counteractive lobbying by rich and poor donors in the experiments in
Grosser and Reuben (2013).
Finally, we compare donors' and social welfare with a
benchmark in which donations are not allowed. The institution of
political contributions considerably improves donors' welfare. The
ability to increase the election chances of a preferred candidate and
possibly induce an implementation of a more favorable policy by far
outweighs donation costs. As for social welfare, in treatments with one
and two donors, FA performs the best. Furthermore, it is the only system
that improves welfare when compared with the no-donation benchmark. In
three-donor treatments, however, the result is reversed. It is NA that
has the highest welfare while FA is the only treatment with welfare
below the no-donation benchmark.
Overall, this study is the first to examine Ackerman and Ayres
(2002) campaign finance reform proposal and our findings indicate that
implementing anonymity of donations is a successful method of limiting
the impact of money in politics. The remainder of the article is
structured as follows. Section II reviews related literature. Section
III presents a theoretical model of the donor-candidate relationship in
which donations increase the probability a candidate is elected. Section
IV describes our experimental design and Section V presents the results.
Section VI concludes the study.
II. RELATED LITERATURE
The theoretical literature on campaign finance has mostly focused
on the effect of contribution limits on election outcomes and welfare in
models that feature binding contracts between donors and politicians,
which are enforceable only if politicians are aware of donors'
identities. In the terminology of this study, the existing theoretical
research assumes that the campaign finance system is either NA or PA,
thus it does not allow for a comparison with the fully anonymous system
in which donors' identities are not known to the politicians. (10)
It is typically assumed that campaign contributions are used in
electoral races to provide information to voters, and candidates secure
contributions by promising favors.
The literature emphasizes two different ways that campaign
expenditures may provide information to voters. One strand of the
literature assumes that campaign advertising is directly informative
(e.g., Ashworth 2006; Coate 2004a, 2004b). For example, Coate (2004a)
presents a model in which limiting campaign contributions may lead to a
Pareto improvement. His main insight is that the effectiveness of
campaign contributions in increasing votes may be affected by the
presence of contribution limits. A second strand of the literature
instead assumes that political advertising is only indirectly
informative (e.g., Potters, Sloof, and van Winden 1997; Prat 2002a,
2002b; Sloof 1999). The core idea in these articles is that candidates
have qualities that interest groups can observe more precisely than
voters and the amount of campaign contributions a candidate collects
signals these qualities to voters, which is the informational benefit of
campaign contributions.
While there is a large experimental literature on voting, and a
growing literature using field experiments to study political science
issues, we are unaware of any existing study that investigates the
effect of different campaign finance systems distinguished by
information structures, though there are a few that discuss issues
related to campaign finance. (11) Houser and Stratmann (2008) conduct
experiments where candidates can send advertisements to voters in order
to influence elections. Advertisements may or may not be costly (to
voters) to send but they contain information about the candidate's
quality (high or low). Based on a model in which candidates are
motivated to trade favors for campaign contributions, they find that
high-quality candidates are elected more frequently and the margins of
victory for high-quality candidates are larger in publicly financed
campaigns than in privately financed ones.
Grosser, Reuben, and Tymula (2013) examine the effect of money on
political influence among small groups of voters. In their design, there
is one wealthy voter/(potential) donor and three poorer voters who
cannot make donations. Differently from our experimental design,
donations in this setting are direct transfers to the candidate, and the
donor can donate to both candidates. Candidates propose a binding
redistribution policy (ranging from no redistribution to full
redistribution) and voters then vote with the election winner determined
by majority rule. The only setting in which they find that candidates
will not propose full redistribution is the partner-donation setting.
(12) This finding is consistent with our finding that candidates
reciprocate donors by implementing policies that are more favorable to
the donor. In their design, however, candidates gain at the expense of
poor voters, while the wealthy donor on average breaks even.
III. A THEORETICAL MODEL
In this section, we provide a simple analytical framework to
understand the incentives for donors to contribute to the
candidates' campaign. The model is also used as the basis of our
experimental design described in Section IV. In this and the following
sections, we will be using terms MPP and location when referring to
agents' preferences interchangeably.
A. Candidate and Donor Characteristics
Consider a game between a politician who is a candidate in an
election and J potential donors who can contribute to the
candidate's campaign fund. The candidate receives benefit B if
elected and 0 otherwise. The candidate's strategy is to determine a
policy [y.sub.1] [member of] [0, b] that will be implemented should he
be elected. The candidate's preferences are characterized by his
MPP [c.sub.1] [member of] [0, b]. Specifically, if policy [y.sub.1] is
implemented then the candidate will experience quadratic loss,
[-([c.sub.1] - [y.sub.1]).sup.2].
Assume that there are two candidates who participate in elections.
To focus on the candidate's response to donations and to abstract
away from the competition for donations between candidates, we assume
that the second candidate is not a strategic player. His preferences are
characterized by policy [c.sub.2] [member of] [0, b] and if elected he
simply implements policy [c.sub.2]. Furthermore, donations can be made
only to the first, that is, to the strategic, candidate.
Candidates' preferences, [c.sub.1] and [c.sub.2], are common
knowledge (13) and without loss of generality we can assume that
[c.sub.1] < [c.sub.2]. Voters' ideal policies are uniformly
distributed on [0,6], so that the expected vote share of the candidates
is given by [c.sub.2] + [c.sub.1])/2b and (2b - [c.sub.2] -
[c.sub.1])/2b, respectively, under the assumption that a voter will vote
for the candidate whose ideal policy is closer to his own. We assume, as
is common in probabilistic voting models (see, e.g., Banks and Duggan
2005; Calvert 1985) that candidate i's probability of being
elected, denoted by [[rho].sub.i], corresponds to the theoretical vote
share, that is,
(1) [[rho].sub.1] = ([c.sub.2] + [c.sub.1])/(2b), [[rho].sub.2] = 1
- [[rho].sub.1] = (2b - [c.sub.2] - [C.sub.1])/(2b).
We refer to these as baseline winning probabilities, and we
describe below how campaign contributions affect these probabilities.
Donors can contribute to the first (strategic) candidate's
campaign fund. Contributions do not directly benefit the candidate but
increase his winning probability: (14) if donor j donates [d.sub.j]
[greater than or equal to] 0 to the candidate then it increases the
winning probability at a rate [r.sub.j]. Thus, if d = ([d.sub.1], ...,
[d.sub.J]) is the vector of donors' contributions then the winning
probability of Candidate 1 becomes
[[rho].sub.1] + [J.summation over (k=1)] [r.sub.k][d.sub.k].
Donors' preferences are characterized by their MPPs, and we
use [l.sub.j] to denote the MPP of donor j. Donor j always knows
[l.sub.j]. We consider two cases for [l.sub.-j], when preferences are
public and [l.sub.-j] is observed by donor j, and another when
preferences are private. The expected payoff of donor j with preferences
[l.sub.j] when Candidate 1 implements policy [y.sub.1] and Candidate 2
implements policy [y.sub.2] = [c.sub.2] is
(2) [MATHEMATICAL EXPRESSION NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII].
Here, w > 0 is the initial endowment and it is introduced to
allow positive payoffs for donors; [d.sub.j] is the donation of donor j
and it is directly subtracted from the donor's wealth regardless of
which candidate wins; [-([y.sub.1] - [l.sub.j]).sup.2] and [-([c.sub.2]
- [l.sub.j]).sup.2] are disutilities caused by policies implemented by
the winning candidates; the disutility from policy [y.sub.i] is
multiplied by the winning probability for candidate i.
Recall that the candidate's payoff in the case of losing
elections has been normalized to zero. Then the expected payoff of the
strategic candidate given a donation vector d is
([[rho].sub.1] + [J.summation over (j=1)][r.sub.j][d.sub.j]) x [B -
[([y.sub.1] - [c.sub.1]).sup.2]]
The timing of the game is as follows. In the beginning of the game,
donors observe their own preference, [l.sub.j], as well as the
preferences of both candidates, [c.sub.i]. If donors' preferences
are public then each donor can also observe the preferences of other
donors, [l.sub._j]. Donors know [[rho].sub.i] and the marginal impacts
of their donations, [r.sub.j]. Upon observing the available information,
each donor decides how much to contribute to Candidate 1. Elections
occur next. If Candidate 2 is elected, he implements policy [y.sub.2] =
[c.sub.2] and the game ends. If Candidate 1 is elected, then he decides
which policy to implement. Candidate 1 observes [c.sub.1] and the total
sum of donations. When donors' preferences are public then the
candidate can observe them as well as donations made by each donor. Upon
learning this information, Candidate 1 chooses policy [y.sub.1] and the
game ends.
B. Nash Equilibrium
Unbounded Payoffs. We solve the game using backward induction
assuming the game is played once. The politician, if elected, has no
incentive to choose anything other than the MPP, (15) [y.sub.1] =
[c.sub.1]. Because [y.sub.1] does not depend on the donor's
behavior, it follows from Equation (2) that the payoff of donor j is a
linear function of [d.sub.j] and therefore optimal donations are either
0 or w. It is optimal to donate w (assuming the winning probability of
the preferred candidate remains less than one) when the coefficient at
[d.sub.j] in Equation (2) is positive, that is when
(3) -1 + [r.sub.j] [[([c.sub.2] - [l.sub.j]).sup.2] - [([c.sub.1] -
[l.sub.j]).sup.2]] > 0;
and to donate 0 otherwise. From Equation (3), [d.sub.j] = w is
optimal when either the impact of donations, [r.sub.j], is large or when
there is a substantial difference between candidates' platforms
from the donor's point of view.
As long as the election probability is less than one, the optimal
donation level does not depend on donations of others. Therefore, the
set of Nash equilibria (NE) is as follows. Let [J.sub.w] be the set of
donors for whom Equation (3) holds. If [MATHEMATICAL EXPRESSION NOT
REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII] then the only NE is where donors from [J.sub.w]
donate everything and other donors donate nothing. Otherwise, we have a
multiplicity of equilibria where donors from [J.sub.w] will donate such
an amount that [MATHEMATICAL EXPRESSION NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII].
Bounded Payoffs, Public Preferences. To make the theoretical
framework compatible with the experimental setting, we consider the case
where ex-post payoffs are bounded from below by 0. That is, if winning
candidate i implements policy [y.sub.i] such that w - [d.sub.j] -
[([y.sub.i] - [l.sub.j]).sup.2] < 0 then j's payoff is zero.
When w [less than or equal to] [([c.sub.2] - [l.sub.j]).sup.2] the
donor's objective function then becomes
(4) [MATHEMATICAL EXPRESSION NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII].
Assuming an interior solution, the first-order condition implies
that the optimal amount of donations is
(5) [MATHEMATICAL EXPRESSION NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII].
Parameters affect the optimal donation level in an intuitive way.
Richer donors will donate more and donations are larger if the
candidate's ideal policy is closer to the donor's; also donors
with larger impacts on elections, that is, those with higher [r.sub.j],
donate more. Furthermore, we observe a free-riding effect: if other
donors donate more, then donor j donates less. These properties carry
through to the equilibrium donation levels given by Equation (6) below:
(16)
(6) [MATHEMATICAL EXPRESSION NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII]
Private Preferences. We now solve for the equilibrium in which
donors' locations are private information, which corresponds to the
Ackerman and Ayres proposal. Donor j does not observe preferences of
other donors and believes that they are distributed with cdf F(*). We
assume that the impact of donations that we denote as r is the same
because donors are indistinguishable.
The unbounded payoffs case remains unchanged because optimal
donations do not depend on preferences of other donors. In the case of
bounded payoffs, the FOC becomes
(7) [MATHEMATICAL EXPRESSION NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII]
Taking expectations of both sides and assuming symmetry, we obtain:
(8) [Ed.sub.j] = w/(J + 1) - [[rho].sub.1]/[r(J + 1)] -
[E[([c.sub.1] - [l.sub.j]).sup.2]]/(J + 1)
and therefore the equilibrium donations are
(9) [MATHEMATICAL EXPRESSION NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII]
Using Equations (6) and (9) to compare donations in public and
private cases, we obtain:
(10) [MATHEMATICAL EXPRESSION NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII]
From Equations (8) and (10), we have the following proposition:
PROPOSITION l. The average individual contributions in models with
public and private information are the same. On average, larger J leads
to lower individual contributions. Donor j will donate less than under
private information if his preferences are closer to [c.sub.1] or
preferences of other donors are further from [c.sub.1].
The intuition for the last statement is as follows. In the case of
public information, there is a free-riding effect: when other donors
contribute larger amounts, donor j has less incentive to contribute. For
example, if [l.sub.j] is close to [c.sub.1] and this is common
knowledge, other donors contribute less thereby making donor j
contribute more. This effect is absent in the case of private
information and therefore [d.sup.priv.sub.j] is lower. Similar intuition
is applied to the case when [c.sub.1] is further away from other donors.
(17)
C. Candidate's Responsiveness and Its Impact on Donations
In the previous section, we used backward induction to establish
that the candidate will always choose [y.sub.1] = [c.sub.1]. The same
argument would apply if the stage game is repeated T < [infinity]
times, where T is common knowledge. However, when T is unknown or is
infinite then backward induction is no longer applicable and it might be
rational for the candidate to choose [y.sub.1] [not equal to] [c.sub.1]
in anticipation of higher future donations, or to avoid potential
punishment of zero donations, adding another dimension to political
contributions. Donors would now contribute not only to support the
candidate but also to influence his policy choice upon winning the
election.
Assume that the policy choice [y.sub.1](d, [c.sub.1]) is a function
of donations, d. and the candidate's location, [c.sub.1]. A
donor's maximization problem under the bounded payoff becomes
(11) [MATHEMATICAL EXPRESSION NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII]
and under the unbounded payoffs
(12) [MATHEMATICAL EXPRESSION NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII].
Let [epsilon] = -[partial derivative][([y.sub.1](d; [c.sub.1]) -
[l.sub.j]).sup.2]]/[partial derivative][d.sub.j] be a measure of a
candidate's responsiveness to donations. It is defined so that if
larger donations lead to more favorable policies then [epsilon] > 0.
From the first-order condition with respect to [d.sub.j], we obtain:
(13) [MATHEMATICAL EXPRESSION NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII],
in the case of bounded payoffs and in the case of unbounded payoffs
we have:
(14) -1 + [r.sub.j][[([c.sub.2] - [l.sub.j]).sup.2] -
[([y.sub.1](d; [c.sub.1]) - [l.sub.j]).sup.2]] +
[r.sub.j][d.sub.j][epsilon] = 0.
For brevity we omit the arguments of d and [c.sub.1].
While full characterization of the equilibrium structure in this
model would go beyond the scope of the article, we use the equations
above to study how donors' behavior is affected by behavior of the
candidate and contributions of other donors. (18)
First, consider the unbounded payoff case. As before, corner
solutions are possible. When [epsilon] > 0 and (3) is satisfied it is
optimal to donate as much as possible. If Equation (3) is not satisfied
and [epsilon] is small it is optimal to donate 0. Finally, when Equation
(14) determines optimal donations (in this case, [epsilon]' would
have to be negative at the optimum) then higher e and lower
[([y.sub.1](d; [c.sub.1]) - [l.sub.j]).sup.2] mean higher [d.sub.j].
Intuitively, marginal cost remains equal to one and marginal benefits
increase.
Now consider the bounded payoff setting. When [epsilon] > 2 it
is optimal to donate as much possible, or at least until [epsilon]
remains above 2. Intuitively, the combined benefits of supporting and
influencing the candidate outweigh the cost of donations. When [epsilon]
< 2 then the best response is affected as follows. Higher [epsilon],
other things being equal, implies larger donations because benefits from
donations are larger. Similarly, other things being equal, an
expectation of a more favorable policy, that is, lower [[[y.sub.1](d;
[c.sub.1]) - [l.sub.j]].sup.2], implies a larger donation. Finally, the
response to [d.sub.-j] depends on whether [epsilon] < 1 or not. In
the former case, an increase in [d.sub.k] for some k [not equal to] j
should decrease [d.sub.j], which is similar to the free-riding effect
observed earlier. However, when [epsilon] > 1 then donations become
strategic complements in that higher [d.sub.k] leads to higher
[d.sub.j]. Intuitively, the benefits of influencing the policy (as
measured by [epsilon]) and the cost of supporting the candidate matter
only as much as the influenced candidate is likely to be elected. Higher
[d.sub.k] amplifies both effects, however, when [epsilon] > 1
([epsilon] < 1) the impact on benefits is higher (lower) and thus it
is optimal for donor j to increase (decrease) donations.
Note that a candidate's response to donations crucially
depends on the information structure. When donors' preferences are
private, for example, one would expect the candidate to be less
responsive to donations than in the case of public preferences and
therefore the donated amount would be smaller than in the public case.
That, in turn, would further limit the candidate's incentives to
respond. (19) In the experimental part of the study, we will test how
different information structures impact donors' and
candidate's behavior.
IV. EXPERIMENTAL DESIGN AND PROCEDURES
The experimental design is closely related to the model described
in the previous section. In this section, the details of the
experimental design, as well as the justifications for some of the
design choices, are presented.
A. Players and Basic Environment
There are two types of players: candidates running for office and
donors who finance candidates' campaigns. There are two candidates
and, depending on the treatment, one to three donors. The set of
potential policies that can be implemented by an elected candidate is
represented by a [0, 300] interval. All candidates and donors have
preferences over the set of policies. Each player has an MPP and incurs
quadratic loss when implemented policies differ from the MPP.
One candidate, labeled as Candidate 1 (hereafter C1), and all
donors are played by human participants. A uniform distribution on the
interval [0,150] is used to draw their MPPs. Candidate 2 (C2) is a
nonstrategic computer player with an MPP at [c.sub.2] = 225 (see Figure
1). The difference between the two candidates is that Cl, if elected,
can implement any policy from the interval [0,300], whereas the
computerized C2 always implements its MPP (225). Furthermore, only C1
can receive donations. In this design, we intentionally abstract away
from questions concerning competition between candidates for political
donations and focus on the interactions between one candidate and his
potential donors.
The key treatment condition in this study is the level of donor
anonymity. Three conditions are considered: FA, in which candidates
observe neither donors' preferences nor the amount of individual
contributions; PA, in which donors' preferences and individual
contributions are observed and each contributed dollar has exactly the
same impact regardless of the donor's preferences; and NA, in which
donors' preferences and individual contributions are observed and
donations from more (less) extreme donors have lower (higher) impact. NA
explicitly incorporates transparency proponents' argument that
voters observing large donors' identities will anticipate the
candidate favoring those donors. Therefore, large donations from an
extreme donor would mean a higher likelihood of more extreme policies if
the candidate is elected, which voters in our setup would find
undesirable. (20)
The timing and information structure is as follows. The game begins
with a donor stage in which each donor learns his MPP, [l.sub.j], as
well as the MPPs, [c.sub.1] and [c.sub.2], of both candidates. Donors
observe the initial probability of C1 winning the election. In PA and
NA, donor j is also shown the MPPs of other donors, [l.sub.-j] Given the
available information each donor decides how much to donate to C1.
Donations do not directly benefit the candidate, but do increase the
election probability for C1. Once donors decide on contribution amounts,
{[d.sub.j]}, the game moves to a candidate stage. Candidates observe
candidates' MPPs, the sum of donations, and the new election
probability given the donations. In PA and NA, the candidate also
observes {[l.sub.j]} and {[d.sub.j]}, the preferences and donated amount
for each donor j. The candidate chooses a policy [y.sub.1] [member of]
0,300] and the candidate stage ends. (21) The election outcome is
determined randomly given the updated election probability. Finally,
given the implemented policy, payoffs are calculated and displayed.
Note that each election outcome is determined by a probabilistic
draw rather than having an election with actual participants as voters.
This decision is made for several reasons. Most importantly, it allows
us to have full control over how donations impact the election outcome,
both within and between different anonymity levels. Furthermore,
excluding the voting stage keeps the experimental setup manageable and
allows us to focus on our main goal which is studying candidate--donors
interactions. Finally, our research is primarily motivated by elections
with large electorate, such as Presidential or Congressional elections
or primaries. These elections are difficult to implement using
participants as voters while retaining a negligible probability that any
voter is pivotal.
The exact parameter values and payoff functions used in the
experimental design are as follows. Given C1's MPP the initial
probability of winning the election, [[rho].sub.1], is
(15) [[rho].sub.1] = ([c.sub.1] + 225)/600.
Thus, more extreme candidates have lower probabilities of winning
than those candidates closer to the center.
Donors are given an initial endowment of w = 9000 experimental
currency units (ECUs) of which they can donate up to a maximum donation
amount of [bar.d] < 9000 to C1's fund. Under PA and FA, the
impact of a donation is set at the rate r = 0.0001, so that every 100
ECUs donated increase C1's election probability by 1%. The final
election probability for C1 is then
(16) [[rho].sub.FA] = [[rho].sub.PA] = [[rho].sub.1] + 0.0001
[j.summation over (j=1)] [d.sub.j].
The impact of donations under NA depends on donors' MPPs and
is given by (17)
[[rho].sub.NA] = [[rho].sub.FA] + (1/600)[[J.summation over (j=1)]
([d.sub.j]/[bar.d]) ([l.sub.j] - [c.sub.1]]/J
where [[rho].sub.FA](d) is defined in Equation (16) and J is the
number of donors. (22)
This particular rule is used for two reasons. First, Equation (17)
is a linear function of {[d.sub.j]} and, therefore, the marginal impact
of each donated ECU, [r.sup.NA.sub.j], depends neither on the donated
amount, [d.sub.j], nor on donations from other donors, [d.sub.-j]. This
assumption makes it particularly convenient for experimental purposes.
Second, it captures the desired effect that donations from more extreme
donors have a lower marginal impact on the election probability. To
compare the impact of donations in NA with that in FA and PA, note that
[r.sup.NA.sub.j] = 0.0001 + (1/600)[([l.sub.j] - [C.sub.1])/(J x
[bar.d])], so that [r.sup.NA.sub.j] > [r.sup.FA.sub.j] =
[r.sup.PA.sub.j] whenever [l.sub.j] > [c.sub.1], meaning that the
same size donation from a nonanonymous more centrist donor donor will
have a larger impact than from an anonymous donor, but the donation from
a nonanonymous extreme donor will have a lesser impact than that of an
anonymous donor. Intuitively, if [l.sub.j] = [c.sub.1], the voters do
not expect donations from donor j to distort the candidate's policy
choice and the donation's impact is the same as in PA. If [l.sub.j]
> [c.sub.1] ([l.sub.j] < [C.sub.1]), the public expects, other
things being equal, that the implemented policy will be more (less)
centrist which provides extra benefit (cost) to the candidate as
compared with PA.
Finally, payoffs are determined in the following manner. If a donor
with MPP [l.sub.j] donates [d.sub.j] to the human candidate, and the
policy implemented by the elected candidate (either human or computer)
is y, then the donor's payoff is given by (18)
[[PI].sub.D] (y;[d.sub.j], [l.sub.j]) = max {9000 - [d.sub.j] -
[([l.sub.j] - y).sup.2], 0},
where 9,000 is the donor's initial endowment.
The value to the human candidate of winning the election is set at
6,000. (23) If the human candidate wins the election and implements
[y.sub.1] then his payoff is [[PI].sub.C] = 6000 -([C.sub.1] -
[y.sub.1]).sup.2], and 0 otherwise. As mentioned earlier, in the
one-stage game the candidate has no incentive to choose [y.sub.1] [not
equal to] [C.sub.1], which is why the experiment is designed as a
repeated-game.
B. Sessions and Treatments
Overall, we conducted 3x3 = 9 treatments: three anonymity levels
times for each of three values for the number of donors, J = 1,2, or 3.
For all nine treatments, the aggregate amount that could be donated was
set equal to 3,000. Therefore, the maximum donation by one donor, d, is
3000/7. The treatments are labeled according to the values of treatment
parameters. For example, PA-2 is the treatment with the PA anonymity
level and two donors.
Each session consisted of three treatments. The anonymity level was
fixed within the session while the number of donors varied from one to
three. Sessions begin with a single donor phase in which each donor was
paired with the same human candidate each round, followed by a two-donor
phase in which two donors were paired with the same human candidate each
round, and then concluded with a three-donor phase in which three donors
were paired with the same human candidate each round. Participants knew
all three treatments would be conducted prior to making any decisions.
While a participant's role is fixed within a phase, participants
are randomly rematched across phases and some participants will play
both roles throughout the session.
While candidates for political office likely have more than three
donors, our results suggest that additional donors would be unlikely to
add insight into the processes in which we are interested. For instance,
if there were any X number of donors, then either the candidate has an
equal number on each side (which can be represented in our two-donor
treatments with one donor on each side) or an unequal number on each
side (which can be represented in our three-donor treatments with two or
three donors on one side and one or zero on the other). The phases
lasted for 14, 12, and 11 rounds, respectively. The number of rounds was
predetermined using a random number generator and was unknown to
participants in order to replicate the infinitely repeated-game
environment.
In order to facilitate the comparison of different treatments, the
same pregenerated values for candidates' and donors' ideal
policy locations were used. In all one-donor treatments, the same 14
pairs of candidate-donor locations are used (one pair for each period),
in all two-donor treatments the same 12 triplets of candidate--two-donor
locations are used, and so forth. Given that the same subjects
participate in treatments with one, two, and three donors, the ideal
locations for one-donor treatments differed from the ideal locations for
two- and three-donor treatments. Across sessions and candidate--donor
groups, however, the draws of the ideal policies were kept identical.
(24) One concern is how best to motivate our design choice as donors
interact with the same candidate repeatedly but all have (potentially)
different locations each round. Our view is that while the candidate and
donors come from the same side of the political spectrum on many issues,
different issues are of importance in each election. Thus, while the
candidate and donors interact repeatedly, their locations vary on
different issues. For some issues, a candidate may be to the left of a
donor, and for other issues a candidate may be to the right of the
donor.
The sessions were conducted using the z-Tree software (Fischbacher
2007). A total of 72 subjects participated with 24 subjects per given
information structure. Sessions were conducted at Florida State
University's xs/fs laboratory in September 2010. Payments averaged
about $18.25 for the 90-minute sessions.
V. RESULTS
In this section, we present results on behavior and welfare. The
terms MPPs, locations, and preferences are used interchangeably. We
refer to MPPs in [0,49] as extreme, those in [50,100] as moderate, and
those in [101,150] as centrist.
A. Descriptive Statistics
Panel A of Table 1 reports the actual (left columns) and the
theoretical (right columns) average donation levels. The theoretical
donations are calculated using the model developed in Section III under
the assumption that the candidate will implement his MPP as the chosen
policy as donors do not expect to influence the candidate. It follows
from Table 1 that for any number of donors average donations in the FA
treatments are lower than in the PA and NA treatments. This result
provides initial support for Ackerman and Ayres's (2002) proposal
for campaign finance reform, at least in reducing the level of money in
politics. Intuitively, in our setup there are two reasons to donate: to
support one's preferred candidate and to affect that
candidate's policy choice. By design, the latter reason is weakest
in the FA treatment, leading to lower average contributions in FA.
Panel B of Table 1 shows the average deviation (left columns),
[y.sub.1] - [C.sub.1], and the average absolute deviation (right
columns), [ly.sub.1], - [C.sub.1]l, between the candidate's MPP and
the chosen policy. The average deviation captures whether donations
influence a candidate's choice toward more centrist or more extreme
policies and the average absolute deviation captures a candidate's
responsiveness to donations. With the exception of PA-2, the
candidate's average deviation is positive. Recall that the location
of the human candidate, [c.sub.1], was drawn from the range [0,150],
while the range of policies is [0,300]. Thus, [c.sub.1] is always to the
left of the median voter and so a positive deviation by the human
candidate is socially desirable in our model. Interestingly,
contributions lead to more centrist policies, even though the donors are
from the same side of the political spectrum. In the PA-2 treatment,
however, the candidate's average deviation was slightly (less than
two units) negative indicating that under PA extreme donors exert the
most influence.
Finally, the average absolute deviation ranged from 7.21 to 27.70,
with the former corresponding to a candidate payoff loss of 52 ECUs (out
of the 6,000 ECUs obtained from winning the election) and the latter to
a loss of 767 ECUs. The average absolute deviation across all treatments
was 15.69, meaning the candidates, on average, would sacrifice 4.1% of
their election benefits. One peculiar finding is that candidates in FA-2
have a larger absolute deviation than those in PA2 or NA-2 despite the
exact same experimental parameters. We discuss what appears to be an odd
result, and certainly one that upon first glance does not support our
hypothesis, in Section V.B.
B. Policy Choices
Deviations in Candidates' Policy Choice. Figure 2 shows the
locations of donors and the human candidates for each period, as well as
the average policies implemented by the human candidates. Panel A shows
the data for one-donor treatments, panel B for two-donor treatments, and
panel C for three-donor treatments.
Deviations appear very common in Figure 2. The average chosen
policy differs from [c.sub.1] in almost every round of every treatment.
Interestingly, deviations also occur in the FA setting even though
donors' locations are unknown to candidates. In NA and PA
treatments, in which donors' locations are observed, candidates,
with few exceptions, choose a policy that is more favorable to donors.
For instance, in multiple-donor treatments having all donors to the left
of [C.sub.1] leads to a policy choice to the left of [c.sub.1].
Figure 2 also sheds light on why Table 1 shows such large absolute
deviations in FA-2 relative to PA-2 and NA-2. In particular, we focus on
periods 2, 5, and 12 in the two-donor treatments. In all of these
periods, the candidates in FA deviate more than the candidates in PA or
NA. This result likely occurs because the candidate draws are fairly
extreme (locations of 32,21, and 7, respectively) and the candidates
attempted to reciprocate donations by moving toward the center, but
unlike their PA and NA counterparts, they did not know that (at least in
periods 2 and 5) one of the donors was even more extreme than the
candidate. From this result, we infer that even candidates in FA will
attempt to reciprocate if there is a good chance that they know they are
reciprocating "correctly," and in each of those three periods
the odds of both donors being to the right of the candidate were at
least 61%. Similar patterns of deviation by FA candidates at extreme
locations can be found in the three-donor treatments (see Periods 2, 3,
4, 6, and 11), although in the three-donor treatment the FA candidates
typically deviate less than the PA or NA candidates because the donors
are generally all located to the right of the candidate and far from the
candidate's preferred policy (particularly in Periods 2,3,4, and
11). For more moderate candidate locations, FA candidates are deviating
less than PA or NA candidates, and an alternative experimental design
that eliminates extreme preferred policies for candidates may show a
more pronounced difference between the FA treatment and the PA and NA
treatments.
To test whether and when these deviations are statistically
significant we conduct Wilcoxon signed-rank tests comparing the
candidate's MPP, [c.sub.1], with the chosen policy, [y.sub.1]. As
described in Section IV.B, for a given number of donors, 7, and in a
given period, t, the locations of the candidate and donors were the same
in all three anonymity levels. For example, in Period 1 of all one-donor
treatments the candidate's location was 63 and the donor's
location was 12. In each treatment, there were 24 subjects with 7+1
subjects per group and therefore we have 24/(J+1) observations for a
given period in a given treatment. Table 2 reports the results, ordered
with respect to [C.sub.1], of the signed rank tests for each
candidate's location and each treatment.
The informal observations from Figure 2 are largely confirmed by
Table 2. First and foremost, there are many instances of statistically
significant deviation from [c.sub.1]. Second, in the NA and PA
treatments candidates consistently choose policies that favor donors,
especially in clear-cut cases when all donor MPPs are on the same side
of the candidate MPP. Third, while significant deviations in NA and PA
are more prevalent than in FA, significant deviations also occur in FA.
Most of these occur in FA-1 when the candidate's location is at the
left or the right extreme of the [0, 150] spectrum, making it possible
to guess whether the donor's location is right or left of
[c.sub.1]. Finally and most importantly, we do not find evidence that NA
is better than PA at filtering out the effect of extreme donors. There
are three instances when [y.sub.1] < [c.sub.1] in NA but not in PA
and the same number of instances (three) when [y.sub.1] < [c.sub.1]
in PA but not in NA. Additionally, there are five instances in which
both NA and PA lead to a choice of significantly more extreme policy.
Given statistically significant deviations in FA, it is worth
emphasizing that the pattern whereby extreme candidates move to the
right and centrist candidates move to the left is not due to mechanical
restrictions imposed on the candidate's policy space and
donors' locations. The key determinant for a candidate's
choice, especially in PA and NA treatments, is donors' locations.
For example, in PA-1 we observe candidates at [c.sub.1] = 119 choosing
an even more centrist policy. At the same time, in the NA-2 and PA-2
treatments, moderate candidates located at 87, 92, and 95 move left
toward more extreme donors.
RESULT 1. Candidates are less likely to deviate from their MPPs
under FA than under PA or NA.
RESULT 2. In NA and PA, candidates consistently choose policies
that favor donors, he they more extreme or more centrist. We observe
little evidence that NA filters out the impact of extreme donors.
Determinants of Policy Deviations. Having established the general
presence and direction of candidates' deviations, we now explore
the factors that affect candidate behavior. Table 3 reports panel-to-bit
regression results with the absolute value of the candidate's
deviation, l[y.sub.1] - [c.sub.1]l, as the dependent variable. The
explanatory variables include donated amounts, candidates' MPPs,
and the difference in preferences between candidates and donors.
Furthermore, for multiple-donor treatments, we expect the candidate to
respond differently to donations depending on the relative proximity and
contribution of one donor compared with other donors. To take this into
account, we separate variables related to the donor closest to (labeled
close) and furthest from (labeled far) [c.sub.1].
One-Donor Treatments. The donated amount, [d.sub.1], has a
significant effect on the deviation size in all three treatments, but
the sign of the effect differs depending on whether the donor's MPP
is observed by the candidate, as in PA and NA, or not, as in FA. In the
PA and NA treatments, larger donations lead to larger deviations, which
is consistent with the intuition that candidates are more willing to
reciprocate in response to larger donations. However, in the FA
treatment larger donations lead to smaller deviations. When candidates
do not observe the donor's preferences, they may interpret larger
donations as an indication that the donor's MPP is close and
reciprocate by not deviating.
The impact of our distance measure, [([l.sub.1] -
[c.sub.1]).sup.2], is as expected. Distance is insignificant in the FA
treatment, in which it is unobserved, while it is positive and
significant in the NA and PA treatments. Thus, in the NA and PA regimes,
the further away the donor is from the candidate, the more likely the
candidate is to deviate from his MPP and the larger the size of the
deviation is.
The candidate location [c.sub.1] is negative and significant in FA
and insignificant in NA and PA. The former means that the centrist
candidates are less likely to deviate under FA, which is socially
desirable in our model. In NA and PA treatments, however, this effect
disappears as the candidate's response is determined to a larger
extent by observed donors' preferences. Finally, in the NA
treatment, candidates' responses to donations differ depending on
whether donors were more or less extreme than the candidate.
Surprisingly, the response is stronger to donations from extreme donors.
This response is surprising because in NA donations from extreme donors
have a lower impact. The willingness of the candidates to respond more
aggressively to more extreme donors under the NA regime, despite the
lower impact of contributions, points toward a potential weakness of the
NA system.
Two-Donor Treatments. In FA-2, the only significant variable is
[C.sub.1] and, as in FA-1, it is negative. The sum of donations is used
as an explanatory variable because the candidate in FA-2 could not
distinguish contributions from individual donors. However, this variable
is insignificant because in FA-2 the total contribution is less
informative about donors' preferences than in FA-1.
In NA and PA treatments, as expected, the candidate responds
differently to donations from closer and more distant donors. The
variable [d.sub.far] - [d.sub.close] is positive in both treatments and
is significant in PA and marginally significant in NA. Thus, larger
donations from a donor further away cause a larger deviation by the
candidate, whereas larger donations from a closer donor cause smaller
deviations.
The distance between the candidate and donors is another
determinant of the candidate's decisions. In PA, the distance to
the closest donor has a positive and significant impact on the size of
deviation. As the distance of the closest donor increases, both donors
are further away from the candidate and reciprocating candidates are
willing to deviate more. In NA, it is the distance to the furthest donor
that has a positive and significant effect. Despite this difference
between the PA and NA systems, the main message is similar to what we
observed in one-donor treatments: in NA and PA treatments candidates are
favoring donors. In particular, when donors' ideal policies are
further away candidates are willing to deviate more to favor their
contributors.
Three-Donor Treatments. The three-donor case is different from the
one- and two-donor cases in that variables related to individual
donors' locations and donated amounts are mostly insignificant. The
insignificance is robust and holds for all three anonymity levels and
different regression specification. We interpret this as evidence that
having three donors creates enough competition to limit the individual
impact of any given donor. (25)
One robust finding is that the variable [c.sub.1] is negative and
significant in FA-3, just as it is in FA-1 and FA-2. Thus, that more
centrist candidates are less likely to deviate in FA does not depend on
the number of donors and appears to be a feature of the FA design.
RESULT 3. We find strong evidence that candidates respond favorably
to donors' contributions in both PA and NA treatments: larger
contributions prompt more reciprocation and candidates are willing to
deviate more when donors are further away.
RESULT 4. FA treatments are successful in limiting the impact of
political contributions. Contributions either have negative or no impact
on candidate's willingness to deviate.
RESULT 5. In three-donor treatments, an individual donor's
influence is limited.
C. Donations
Donation decisions are studied in this section. We estimate a
fixed-effect panel model to determine the impact different variables
have on donations. Estimation results are presented in Table 4. The only
variable that is significant in all nine treatments is the distance
between the candidates' and donors' MPPs. Its sign is
expectedly negative--donors contribute more to candidates who are
closer. Also, an important determinant of the donation amount in NA-1 is
whether the donor was more or less extreme than the candidate, although
this is unimportant in FA and PA. In NA, donors who were more extreme
and thus less powerful donate less. Notably, this effect disappears in
NA-2 and NA-3, which is why the dummy variable, [([c.sub.1] >
[l.sub.j]).sub.t], is excluded in regressions for multiple donor
treatments.
We are also interested in the nature of strategic interactions
between donors in treatments with more than one donor. There are two
strategic effects at play. The first is free-riding, as election of
[C.sub.1] is a public good for donors. If this effect is present then
greater distances between other donors and the candidate will positively
impact donation size. The second is competition, which occurs when the
candidate is located between the donors, as donors wish to influence the
policy choice by their contributions but have opposite views on which
policy is desirable. To identify the competition effect we introduce the
dummy variable Between, equal to one if the candidate is between the
donors. The expected sign of Between is positive.
The evidence of a free-riding effect is present in the PA-2 and
PA-3 treatments as the variables [Dist.sub.-j] and [DistFar.sub.-j] are
significantly positive. The variable Between is also significant in both
PA treatments, suggesting the presence of a competition effect. As the
two effects have the opposite sign we might expect them to cancel each
other when both are present. We test this conjecture via interaction
terms. In PA-2, the coefficient of the interaction term [Dist.sub._j].
Between is significantly negative and, furthermore, when Between = 1,
the effect of [Dist.sub._j] becomes insignificant (p value 0.27). (26)
The same holds in PA-3 for the variable [DistFar.sub._j] and interaction
term [DistFar.sub._j]. Between (p value is 0.39). Thus stronger
competition (Between = 1) removes the free-riding effect ([Dist.sub._j]
and [DistFar.sub._j] become insignificant).
In NA treatments, neither distance variables nor the variable
Between is significant. However, in NA-2 the sum of the coefficients for
[Dist.sub._j] and [Dist.sub._j]. Between is negative and significantly
different from zero (with p value 0.067). Thus, while we do not observe
free-riding in NA-2, there is evidence of a competition effect. When
competition is weak (Between = 0) the MPP of the other donor is
insignificant, but with strong competition (Between = 1) the effect is
negative as donations increase the closer other donors are to the
candidate, which is the exact opposite of the free-riding effect.
Finally, in FA treatments, there is neither a competition nor a
free-riding effect, which is as expected given that donors'
locations are private information.
RESULT 6. The key determinant of the contribution amount is the
distance between the donor and the candidate. Donors who are closer to
the candidate donate more.
RESULT 7. We observe the free-riding and competition effects in
PA-2 and PA-3. We also observe the competition effect in NA-2.
D. Welfare
While mitigating the influence of money in politics is the goal of
many campaign finance reform proposals, much of the theoretical research
mentioned in Section II emphasizes that campaign contributions can play
potentially important roles in improving electoral outcomes and
increasing social welfare.
In our framework, donations can impact social welfare via two
effects: by altering the probability of elections and by affecting the
implemented policy. The first effect damages social welfare if [c.sub.1]
<75. The second effect is detrimental for welfare if [y.sub.1] <
[c.sub.1]. Note that the two effects can work in opposite directions,
such as when an extreme candidate receives large donations but chooses a
more moderate policy.
We compare the expected social welfare generated by our
experimental data against a benchmark in which donations are prohibited.
In calculating social welfare, we assume that voters' preferences
are similar to those assumed for the donors, as specified by Equation
(18), particularly that voters' payoffs are bounded by zero. If the
election probability is [[??].sub.1] and the implemented policy is
[y.sub.1], then the expected utility of a voter with an MPP of
[[mu].sub.i] is:
(19) [MATHEMATICAL EXPRESSION NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII].
In the benchmark when donations are prohibited, [[??].sub.1] =
[[rho].sub.1] as determined by Equation (15), and [y.sub.1] = [C.sub.1].
For calculations, benchmark values for candidates' and donors'
MPPs were equal to those used in actual treatments. Finally, we assume
that voters' preferences are uniformly distributed on [0, 300].
Table 5 shows average voter welfare by treatment and number of
donors. We boldface the number that is larger than its counterpart in
each treatment. In treatments with one and two donors FA performs the
best and PA performs the worst. With three donors the effect of
anonymity is reversed as FA now performs the worst. One reason for this
difference is that in the treatments with fewer donors (one and two) it
is more likely that all donors are more extreme than the candidate,
leading to a more extreme policy under NA and PA. Adding the third
donor, however, makes such realization of preferences less probable
thereby reducing the chance of welfare decreasing outcomes in NA-3 and
PA-3. As for FA-3, the positive aspect of political contributions, which
is a choice of more moderate policies by extreme candidates, is absent.
Therefore, extreme candidates still obtain a greater chance of election
which is not offset by an implementation of more moderate policies. (27)
Table 6 shows donors' expected welfare in different treatments
and, in almost all treatments, donors benefit greatly from the
institution of political contributions. The ability to increase election
chances of a preferred candidate, combined with the ability to influence
an implementation of more favorable policies, far outweighs the cost of
donations.
RESULT 8. With a small number of donors (1 and 2) more anonymity
improves voters' welfare whereas partial and NA systems lead to
small reductions in welfare. With three donors the result is reversed.
The worst setting for voters' welfare is the PA treatment with two
donors.
RESULT 9. The institution of political contributions considerably
increases donors' welfare.
VI. CONCLUSION
Campaign finance reform is one of the biggest domestic policy
issues, yet important reform proposals are difficult to study
empirically. In this study, we compare alternative campaign finance
systems in a laboratory setting and focus on their effects on donations,
policy choices, and welfare. Three systems are considered. The first is
an FA system in which neither the politicians nor the voters are
informed about the donors' ideal policies or levels of donations,
which we believe corresponds in spirit to the reform advocated by
Ackerman and Ayres (2002). The second is a PA system in which only the
politicians, but not the voters, are informed about the donors'
ideal policies and donations, which we believe corresponds closer to the
current campaign finance system in the United States. The third is an NA
system in which both the politicians and the voters are informed about
the donors' ideal policies and donations, which corresponds to a
set of perfectly enforced campaign finance disclosure laws.
Our results provide supportive evidence for Ackerman and
Ayres's (2002) campaign finance reform proposal. A fully anonymous
campaign finance system seems to have the potential to reduce the
influence of money in politics more effectively than the current PA
system or the NA system. Indeed, under FA donations were lower and
contributions had either zero or negative impact on a politician's
willingness to deviate from the ideal policy. Furthermore, in FA
donations are more likely to make extreme candidates move to the center
than to make centrist candidates move to the extreme. The NA, or full
transparency, system was less successful in that regard. Candidates were
responsive to donations and consistently chose policies favoring donors,
including more extreme ones. Nonetheless, the NA system resulted in
higher welfare as compared with the PA, so if FA cannot be guaranteed a
system of full transparency may provide a second-best solution.
We should, of course, bear in mind that many important issues
related to campaign finance and political competition are abstracted
away in this study. For example, we assumed that candidate's ideal
policies are common knowledge to all donors and voters. This suppresses
one of the roles of campaign expenditures, namely to inform voters about
the candidate's policy platform. We also abstracted away from the
critical voter turnout issue as we do not consider at all how voter
turnout may be affected by whether or not donations are anonymous.
Moreover, we fixed the policy position of the computer candidate and
only included one human candidate in our experiment. Thus we cannot
comment on how political competition might affect the performance of
different campaign finance systems. It is important to study how
alternative campaign finance systems will perform when more of these
issues are incorporated and when these systems are possibly implemented
in the field rather in the laboratory.
doi: 10.1111/ecin.12209
ABBREVIATIONS
C1: Candidate 1
C2: Candidate 2
ECU: Experimental Currency Unit
FA: Full Anonymity
FECA: Federal Election Campaign Act
MPP: Most Preferred Policy
NA: No Anonymity
NE: Nash Equilibria
PA: Partial Anonymity
APPENDIX
INSTRUCTIONS
The instructions for the FA sessions are included here. There are
comments in italics and boldface when the instructions for the PA and NA
treatments differ. Figures A1 and A2 include screenshots of a
donor's screen and a candidate's screen from a PA treatment.
WELCOME TO A DECISION-MAKING STUDY!
Introduction
Thank you for participating in today's study in economic
decision-making. These instructions describe the procedures of the
study, so please read them carefully. If you have any questions while
reading these instructions or at any time during the study, please raise
your hand. At this time I ask that you refrain from talking to any of
the other participants.
General Description
In this study, all participants are assigned to one of two roles:
* a candidate who would like to be elected and
* a donor who may or may not provide financial support for the
candidate's campaign.
A candidate, if elected, determines the policy. The policy is
described by a number between 0 and 300. A policy of 0 corresponds to
one side of the political spectrum and a policy of 300 corresponds to
the other extreme of the spectrum. Candidates and donors have an MPP
that characterizes your preferences with regards to the implemented
policy. The closer the implemented policy is to your MPP the better off
you are.
Donor Stage. At this moment, I ask you to turn your attention to
the monitor. During the study, all of you will be assigned the role of
either a candidate or a donor. If you are assigned a donor role you will
see the screen similar to what you see now. You can see that there are
two candidates--C1 and C2--and that their MPPs are located at 75 and
225, respectively. You are a donor and your MPP is located at 100. The
candidate at 225, C2, will be played by a computer. This candidate
always chooses policy 225 if elected. The other candidate, C1, will be
played by a human.
Donors have funds, denominated in ECUs, available for contribution.
On the computer screen, you see that you have 9,000 ECUs, 3,000 of which
you can donate. Donations can be made only to the human candidate, C1.
Donors need to decide how much money they want to contribute to
C1's campaign fund. Contributions to the candidate change the
probability a candidate is elected as will be explained below.
Without any contributions, the initial chance of election is
determined by the human candidate's MPP. Having a more extreme
policy means a lower chance whereas having a more centrist policy means
a higher chance. The initial chance of election will be calculated and
displayed on the screen for you every period. You see on the screen that
when C1 is at 75 his chance of being elected is exactly 50%. When
C1's more preferred policy is to the left of 75, his chance of
being elected will be less than 50% and when it is to right of 75 it
will be larger than 50%.
If the human candidate receives contributions from donors then her
chance of being elected changes from the initial chance of election [NA:
The remainder of the paragraph reads as follows: In general,
donors' contributions increase the chance of election. The rate of
increase, however, depends on the donor's location. Donations from
donors with extreme preferred policies are less effective than donations
from those with more centrist preferences. The effectiveness of your
donations will be shown on the screen. In this example, the donor's
location is more centristic and so 100 ECUs of donations increase the
probability of election by 1.14%. The chance of election cannot be made
higher than 80%. At this time I ask you to enter a donation of 2,000 and
press the " Donate" button. You now see a new screen that
shows the size of your donation and the new probability for C1. Because
of your donations the new probability is higher and is equal to 73%.
Press the " Continue" button]. Contributions increase the
chance of election at the rate of 100 to 1. That is, a contribution of
100 ECUs increases the chance of election by 1%, a contribution of 200
ECUs by 2%, and so on. The chance of election cannot be made higher than
80%. At this time I ask you to enter a donation of 3,000 and press the
"Donate" button. You now see a new screen that shows the size
of your donation and the new probability for C1. Because of your
donations the new probability is higher and is equal to 80%. Press the
"Continue" button.
Candidate Stage. After donors make their donations it is the
candidate's turn to implement a decision. For technical reasons, we
ask candidates to decide on the policy before the actual outcome of
elections. If you are assigned the role of candidate you will see the
following screen. The screen shows you the location of your MPP, the
total amount of donations and your probability of winning [PA/NA: The
prior sentence is replaced by: The screen shows your chance of election
as well as the locations of donors and their contributions]. You can
enter any number between 0 and 300 as your implemented policy. Please
submit number 75. This policy will determine your own payoff and the
payoff of your potential donors. Notice that the policy you implement
has no impact on your chance of election. Your chance of election is
only determined by the donations and the initial chance of election. In
our example, the chance of election is 80% regardless of the implemented
policy.
Profit Stage. The next four screens will show you the profit for D1
and C1 when C1 wins and when C1 does not win. In the actual study, you
will only see one screen that corresponds to your role and the election
outcome. This screen shows the donor's profit if C1 is elected. The
profit is determined as follows. We take your initial endowment which is
9,000, subtract the size of your donation, 3,000 in our example, and
subtract the loss from the chosen policy. The loss is just the square of
the difference between the implemented policy and donor's MPP. In
our example, it is equal to (100-75) (2) = 625. Clearly, the further the
implemented policy is from a donor's MPP the larger is the loss.
Formally, a donor's profit is calculated as
9000 - Donation - (Implemented Policy -Donor Preferred Policy) (2).
Please press the "Continue" button. This screen shows the
donor's profit if C2 is elected. The profit is calculated according
to the same formula. As the implemented policy of 225 is too far from
100 the profit is negative. Whenever profit is negative it will be
counted as 0 for your cash payout. Please press the "Continue"
button.
The next screen shows C1's profit if C1 is elected. Whenever
C1 is elected he receives 6,000. If the implemented policy differs from
C1's MPP then C1 incurs a loss which is also a square of the
difference. In our example, C1 chose 75 and so the loss is 0. So the
total profit is 6,000. On the next screen, we show C1's payoff if
he loses the election. C1's profit is 0 in that case. Thus, the
candidate's profit is 0 when not elected and
6000 - (Implemented Policy -Candidate Preferred Policy) (2), if
elected. Press "Continue."
Two Donors. Within the study, the number of donors will be varied
depending upon the phase. The second example depicts the case of two
donors: D1 and D2. In this example, you are D1. You see the locations of
the MPPs for C1 and C2 which are 60 and 225 [PA/NA: The following
sentence is added: You also see the MPPs of both donors]. You see that
the initial election chance is less than 50% because C1 is to the left
of 75. You also see that when there are two donors you can donate only
1,500 of your endowment. Finally, notice that you do not know the
location of the other donor(s), only your own location [PA/NA: The prior
sentence is deleted]. Please enter 1,500 and the computer is programmed
so that D2's donation is 0. At the candidate's screen notice
that the candidate does not know the location of either of the two
donors. Please enter a policy of 75. When C1 wins D1 's payoff is
6,875. If C1 loses then Dl's payoff is negative and will be counted
as zero. When C1 wins now C1's payoff is not 6,000 but 6000 - (75 -
60) (2) = 5775 because his implemented policy differs from his preferred
policy. Again, when C1 loses his payoff is zero. This completes our
example. Notice that during the study you will either see the
donor's screens (if you are a donor) or the candidate's
screens but not both.
Phase Description
The study consists of three phases, time permitting. In each phase,
participants will be divided into groups. In the first phase of the
study, there will be two people in each group: one candidate and one
donor. In the second phase of the study, there will be three
participants in each group: two donors and one candidate. In the third
phase of the study, there will be four participants in each group: three
donors and one candidate. Within a phase your group assignment will not
change. Groups are re-assigned in the beginning of every phase. This
means that you will have the same groupmate(s) during each phase of the
study but your groupmates in different phases may be different.
Example: In the first phase, person A is a candidate and is matched
with person B who is a donor. During the entire first phase for person
A, there will be only one potential donor which is person B and person B
can only contribute to candidate A. Furthermore, it is the policy
implemented by candidate A, if elected, that will determine B's
payoff. In the second phase the group assignment will be randomly
redone. For example, person A can become a donor and will be matched
with person C who is the second donor and person D who is a candidate.
The assignment will be re-done for the third phase as well.
Cash Payoffs
Your cash payoff will be determined as follows. At the end of the
experiment we will randomly draw one of the three phases. Your cash
earnings will be equal to the total profit that you earned during that
phase with 6,000 points being equal to 1 dollar. This is in addition to
the $5 that you receive as a show-up fee. For example, if the phase with
two donors is chosen and you earned 60,000 points at that phase then
your cash payoff will be: 60000/6000 + 5 = $15.
REFERENCES
Abramowitz, A. "Explaining Senate Election Outcomes."
American Political Science Review, 82, 1988,385-403.
Ackerman, B., and I. Ayres. Voting with Dollars: A New Paradigmfor
Campaign Finance. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 2002.
Aranson, P. H., and M. I. Hinich. "Some Aspects of the
Political Economy of Election Campaign Contribution Laws." Public
Choice, 34(3/4), 1979, 435-61.
Ashworth, S. "Campaign Finance and Voter Welfare with
Entrenched Incumbents." The American Political Science Review,
100(1), 2006, 55-68.
Ayres, I., and I. Bulow. "The Donation Booth: Mandating Donor
Anonymity to Disrupt the Market for Political Influence." Stanford
Law Review, 50(3), 1998, 837-91.
Banks, I., and J. Duggan. "Probabilistic Voting in the Spatial
Model of Elections: The Theory of Office-Motivated Candidates, " in
Social Choice and Strategic Decision, edited by D. Austen-Smith, and J.
Duggan. Berlin: Springer-Verlag, 2005.
Calvert, R. L. "Robustness of the Multidimensional Voting
Model: Candidate Motivations, Uncertainty, and Convergence."
American Journal of Political Science, 29(1), 1985, 69-95.
Coate, S. "Pareto Improving Campaign Finance Policy."
American Economic Review, 94, 2004a, 628-55.
--. "Political Competition with Campaign Contributions and
Informative Advertising." Journal of the European Economic
Association, 2(5), 2004b, 772-804.
Fang, H., D. Shapiro, and A. Zillante. "Contribution Limits
and Transparency in a Campaign Finance Experiment." University of
North Carolina at Charlotte Working Paper, 2015.
Fischbacher, U. "z-Tree Zurich Toolbox for Readymade Economic
Experiments." Experimental Economics, 10(2), 2007, 171-8.
Gerber, A. "Estimating the Effect of Campaign Spending on
Senate Election Outcomes Using Instrumental Variables." American
Political Science Review, 92, 1998, 401-11.
Green, D., and J. Krasno. "Salvation for the Spendthrift
Incumbent: Reestimating the Effects of Campaign Spending in House
Elections." American Journal of Political Science, 32, 1988,
884-907.
Green, D. P, and A. S. Gerber. Get Out the Vote: How to Increase
Voter Turnout. 2nd ed. Washington, DC: Brookings Institution Press,
2008.
Grosser, J.. and E. Reuben. "Redistribution and Market
Efficiency: An Experimental Study." Journal of Public Economics,
101, 2013, 39-52.
Grosser, J., E. Reuben, and A. Tymula. "Political Quid Pro Quo
Agreements: An Experimental Study." American Journal of Political
Science, 57(3), 2013, 582-97.
Houser, D., and T. Stratmann. "Selling Favors in the Lab:
Experiments on Campaign Finance Reform." Public Choice, 136, 2008,
215-39.
Jacobson, G. "Money and Votes Reconsidered: Congressional
Elections 1972-1982." Public Choice, 47, 1985, 7-62.
Levitt, S. "Using Repeat Challengers to Estimate the Effects
of Campaign Spending on Election Outcomes in the U.S. House."
Journal of Political Economy, 102, 1994, 777-98.
Morton, R. B., and C. Cameron. "Elections and the Theory of
Campaign Contributions: A Survey and Critical Analysis." Economics
and Politics, 4(1), 1992, 79-108.
Morton, R. B., and K. C. Williams. Experimental Political Science
and the Study of Causality: From Nature to the Lab. Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press, 2010.
Palfrey, T. "Laboratory Experiments," in Handbook of
Political Economy, edited by B. Weingast and D. Wittman. Oxford: Oxford
University Press, 2006.
Potters, J., R. Sloof, and F. van Winden. "Campaign
Expenditures, Contributions, and Direct Endorsements: The Strategic Use
of Information and Money to Influence Voter Behavior." European
Journal of Political Economy, 13, 1997, 1-31.
Prat, A. "Campaign Advertising and Voter Welfare." Review
of Economic Studies, 69(4), 2002a, 999-1018.
--. "Campaign Spending with Office-Seeking Politicians,
Rational Voters, and Multiple Lobbies." Journal of Economic Theory,
103(1), 2002b, 162-89.
Sloof, R. "Campaign Contributions and the Desirability of Full
Disclosure Laws." Economics and Politics, 11(1), 1999, 83-107.
(1.) See http://www.cfinst.org and http://www.opensecrets .org for
the historical data on campaign expenditures.
(2.) Federal candidate committees must identify, for example, all
PACs and party committees that give them contributions, and they must
provide the names, occupations, employers, and addresses of all
individuals who give them more than $200 in an election cycle. The
Federal Election Commission maintains this database and publishes the
information about campaigns and donors on its website.
(3.) The Buckley Court did indicate a circumstance in which the
FECA's disclosure requirements might pose such an undue burden that
they would be unconstitutional. The Court opined that disclosure could
be unconstitutional if disclosure would expose groups or their
contributors to threats, harassment, and reprisals; and the Court
suggested a "hardship" exemption from disclosure requirements
for groups and individuals able to demonstrate a reasonable probability
that their compliance would result in such adverse consequences.
(4.) Ackerman and Ayres' proposal also includes a Patriot
dollar component in which each voter is given a $50 voucher in every
election cycle to allocate between Presidential, House, and Senate
campaigns.
(5.) Ayres and Bulow (1998) discuss various attempts at anonymous
contribution systems for judicial elections in a dozen U.S. states in
the 1970s. As they mention, many of these systems did not last long nor
does much data exist to determine what effect full anonymity had on
campaign contributions.
(6.) See Morton and Williams (2010) for an excellent introduction
of the use of lab experiments in political science.
(7.) Under the current federal election contribution laws, it is
widely known that the identity of contributions can be hidden from the
public via 501(c)(4) organizations and such. In our view PA approximates
the current system in the United States because voters are uninformed
about the identity of the donor, while candidates are likely to learn
the identity through other means (e.g., private fund-raising events,
etc.).
(8.) Aranson and Hinich (1979) provide an early theoretical model
in which donations affect election probability.
(9.) As an extreme example to motivate this assumption, consider a
sizable campaign contribution from an organization considered
contemptible by a large chunk of the voters (even those who have
political leanings to the same side). The monetary donation will
certainly benefit the candidate, but because the organization is so
extreme it may cause a loss in support from other donors/voters who feel
that by accepting the donation the candidate may enact policies that are
too extreme. It is in this way that donations from extreme donors have
"less impact" than anonymous donations. However, a donation of
the same size from a nonanonymous very moderate group would have a
larger impact than the same donation from an anonymous donor (as well as
a much larger impact than the same size donation from a nonanonymous
extreme group) on the candidate's election probability because less
voters would be turned away.
(10.) See Morton and Cameron (1992) for a comprehensive review of
the earlier literature.
(11.) See Palfrey (2006) for an insightful survey on laboratory
experiments related to political economy issues, and see Morton and
Williams (2010) for an updated review of experimental methodology and
reasoning in political science. Randomized field experiments are used
widely in political science, but mostly in studies on voter behavior
(see, e.g., Green and Gerber 2008) for studies on increasing voter
turnout using field experiments.
(12.) The partner-donation setting involves repeated elections
among group members in which the potential donor can make donations.
(13.) This would be the case if, for example, during the electoral
campaign or during prior political activities the preferences of
candidates became known to the public; alternatively, the
candidate's ideal policy could reflect the candidate's party
position. However, this assumption does preclude us from exploring the
role of campaign expenditures in informing the voters about the
candidates' positions.
(14.) For studies on the effects of campaign spending to vote
shares and probability of winning, see, for example, Jacobson (1985),
Abramowitz (1988), Green and Krasno (1988), Levitt (1994), and Gerber
(1998).
(15.) Admittedly there are other reasons, such as reciprocity, that
would cause the candidate to deviate from implementing the most
preferred policy in the one-shot setting. However, we abstract away from
these reasons in order to establish a benchmark theoretical case.
(16.) When w > [([c.sub.2] - [l.sub.j]).sup.2] a donor's
utility coincides with the unbounded payoff case if [d.sub.j] < w -
[([c.sub.2] - [l.sub.j]).sup.2] and it becomes (4) otherwise. Depending
on parameter values three cases are possible: the optimal donation can
be either 0, w - [([c.sub.2] - [l.sub.j]).sup.2], or the level
determined by (5). Having three cases makes the exact analytical
expression for the NE too cumbersome and so for parameter values from
our experiment we calculate NE numerically.
(17.) Our focus is on a setting in which one candidate receives
donations while the second candidate does not. A natural question is
what would happen to the amount of donations if both candidates could
receive them. While we have not included the model here, the end result
is that donations would increase because now it would be the amount of
donations beyond what the other candidate raises that shift the
probability of election. In essence, more donations would be needed to
offset the opposing candidate's donations.
(18.) Naturally, without deriving the equilibrium the applicability
of the analysis below is somewhat limited. Nonetheless, it will be a
useful benchmark for interpreting empirical results in Section V.
(19.) Again, the question arises as to what we expect would occur
in a setting with two strategic candidates. Because candidates now need
donations to offset the donations to the opponent's campaign, we
conjecture that in PA and NA treatments the candidate will become more
responsive, that is, higher e. The reason is that withdrawal of
donations is a harsher punishment than it would be in the case of one
strategic candidate. When harsher punishment is available more
cooperative outcomes can be achieved, which is why we expect to have
higher e in the PA/NA settings with two strategic candidates. In the
case of FA we do not expect any changes. We establish in the paper that
in the FA setting donors' preferences do not affect policy choices.
There is no reason it would change in the case with two strategic
candidates.
(20.) As the impact of donations depends on donors'
preferences under NA but not under PA, it is as if donors'
identities are known to the public in NA but remain anonymous, for
example, with help from 501(c)(4) organizations, in PA. This is why we
use the terms Partial Anonymity and No Anonymity for the last two
treatments.
(21.) We chose to have candidates make their policy decision prior
to the announcement of the election winner so as to have a complete set
of human candidate policy choices.
(22.) As it is implausible that donations from a few large donors
can guarantee a candidate wins the election with certainty, a maximum
final election probability for C1 of 0.8 is imposed for all three
anonymity conditions.
(23.) The donor endowment of 9,000 and the candidate benefit of
6,000 are chosen in an attempt to equalize expected payoffs between
donor and candidate participants. The reason that donors have a larger
endowment than the candidate is because when C1 loses then all
participants are essentially receiving 0, and when C1 wins donors are
likely to suffer larger losses than candidates because (1) donors
contribute some of their endowment as donations and (2) candidates
choose policies closer to their own MPPs.
(24.) Table 2 records the actual draws of the human
candidate's ideal policy location [c.sub.1] and the donor(s)'
ideal policy locations for each period.
(25.) Caution should be used when interpreting this result as our
experiment consists of three donors in a setting with a single policy
dimension. In settings with multiple policy dimensions a candidate could
alter policies in many different ways, which could reduce competition
among donors.
(26.) To be more specific, let [[beta].sub.1] be the coefficient at
[Dist.sub._j] and [[beta].sub.2] at [Dist.sub._j]? Between. When Between
= 1 the effect of [Dist.sub._j] is [[beta].sub.1] + [[beta].sub.2]. The
r-test could not reject the hypothesis [[beta].sub.1] + [[beta].sub.2] =
0, with p value 0.27.
(27.) Another reason may be due to the randomly chosen candidate
locations, as extreme locations are overrepresented in the three-donor
treatments. As candidates in the FA treatment deviate less than those in
other treatments, this random draw could be driving the result.
HANMING FANG, DMITRY SHAPIRO and ARTHUR ZILLANTE *
* We are grateful to helpful comments from Jared Barton, David J.
Cooper, Tom Palfrey, Michael Price, the editor, two anonymous referees,
and session participants at the 80th Annual Meetings of the Southern
Economic Association, 2012 European Economic Association meetings in
Malaga, and the 2012 SITE Summer Workshop. We would also like to thank
Tim Salmon for allowing us to use the xs/fs laboratory at Florida State
University to conduct our research experiments, and John Jensenius for
his help in conducting the experiments. All errors remain our own.
Fang: Professor, Department of Economics, University of
Pennsylvania, Philadelphia, PA 19104; Fudan University, Shanghai, China.
Phone 215-898-7767, Fax 215-898-7767, E-mail hanming.fang@econ.upenn.edu
Shapiro: Associate Professor, Department of Economics, University
of North Carolina at Charlotte, Charlotte, NC 28223. Phone 704-687-7608,
Fax 704-687-7608, E-mail dashapir@uncc.edu
Zillante: Associate Professor, Department of Economics, University
of North Carolina at Charlotte, Charlotte, NC 28223. Phone 704-687-7589,
Fax 704-687-7589, E-mail azillant@uncc.edu
TABLE 1
Donations and Candidates' Response
(A) Total Donations (out of 3,000)
Actual Theoretical
1 2 3 1 2 3
FA 1,397 1,599 1.645 962 1.358 1.326
PA 1,735 2,209 1,666 962 1,268 1.225
NA 1,522 1,939 2,392 944 1,250 1,345
(B) Policy Choices
[absolute value of
Deviation Deviation]
1 2 3 1 2 3
FA 4.74 13.90 2.33 9.65 21.73 7.21
PA 1.25 -1.13 14.55 10.39 12.06 19.18
NA 2.86 2.59 24.30 23.95 13.78 27.70
Notes: Theoretical predictions are calculated using the
theoretical framework in Section III and under the assumption
that donors expect the candidate to implement his MPP.
TABLE 2
Comparing the Chosen Policy, yx with the Candidate's Most Preferred
Policy, [c.sub.1]
One Donor
[C.sub.1] FA PA NA [l.sub.1]
3 1 1 1 42
33 1 1 1 125
46 1 0 1 29
49 0 -1 0 17
63 1 0 0 12
66 0 0 1 76
75 0 1 0 143
97 0 1 0 138
116 0 0 0 116
119 0 1 0 148
132 -1 -1 -1 57
145 -1 -1 -1 122
146 0 0 -1 48
149 -1 0 -1 96
Two Donors
[C.sub.1] FA PA NA [l.sub.1] [l.sub.2]
1 1 1 1 138 56
21 0 1 1 63 11
32 0 1 1 100 4
32 0 0 1 32 128
56 0 1 1 128 111
68 0 0 0 70 42
87 0 -1 -1 52 81
92 0 -1 -1 6 28
95 0 0 -1 41 18
95 0 -1 -1 13 5
103 0 0 0 114 21
126 0 0 -1 133 40
Three Donors
[C.sub.1] FA PA NA [l.sub.1] [l.sub.2] [l.sub.3]
3 1 1 1 76 130 108
3 1 1 1 64 86 78
9 1 1 1 144 23 124
13 0 0 1 4 116 121
29 0 1 1 100 148 91
56 0 0 0 29 125 48
89 0 1 1 102 119 146
92 0 0 0 28 99 77
95 0 -1 0 17 29 89
104 0 1 0 146 101 39
108 0 -1 0 85 96 20
Notes: Wilcoxon's signed rank test of the null [y.sub.1] = [c.sub.1]
for each candidate's MPR Label "1" (label "-1") means the null is
rejected in favor of [y.sub.1] > [c.sub.1] ([y.sub.1] < [C.sub.1]) at
the 10% level; label "0" means the null cannot be rejected.
TABLE 3
The Panel Tobit Regression Analysis of the Candidate Behavior
FA
Coef p value
(A) One Donor
[d.sub.1] -0.0105 0.008
[([l.sub.1] - [c.sub.1]).sup.2] 0.0011 0.345
[c.sub.1] -0.3685 0.000
[DidCMove.sub.t-1] 0.3308 0.018
[([c.sub.1] > [l.sub.1]).sub.t] 8.8681 0.241
[DidCWin.sub.t-1] -12.8371 0.082
Const 15.0598 0.333
Pseudo-[R.sup.2] 0.19
(B) Two Donors
[d.sub.1] + [d.sub.2] -0.0091 0.141
[d.sub.far] - [d.sub.close] -- --
[([l.sub.far] - [c.sub.1]).sup.2] -0.0011 0.299
[([l.sub.close] - [c.sub.1]).sup.2] -0.0002 0.981
([l.sub.far] - [c.sub.1])([l.sub.close] - 0.0019 0.362
[c.sub.1])
[c.sub.1] > max [l.sub.j] 0.5705 0.966
[c.sub.1] -0.2647 0.079
[DidCMove.sub.t-1] 0.0136 0.866
[DidCWin.sub.t-1] -5.9948 0.582
Const 38.2178 0.125
Pseudo-[R.sup.2] 0.08
(C) Three Donors
[d.sub.1] + [d.sub.2] + [d.sub.3] -0.00454 0.703
[([l.sub.far] - [c.sub.1]).sup.2] -0.00157 0.107
[([l.sub.close] - [c.sub.1]).sup.2] -0.00448 0.419
([l.sub.far] - [c.sub.1])([l.sub.close] - 0.00552 0.101
[c.sub.1])
[c.sub.1] -0.36602 0.033
[DidCMove.sub.t-1] -0.11660 0.568
[DidCWin.sub.t-1] -3.83488 0.719
Const 3.70581 0.917
Pseudo-[R.sup.2] 0.17
PA
Coef p value
(A) One Donor
[d.sub.1] 0.0042 0.053
[([l.sub.1] - [c.sub.1]).sup.2] 0.0018 0.003
[c.sub.1] -0.0291 0.500
[DidCMove.sub.t-1] 0.2684 0.042
[([c.sub.1] > [l.sub.1]).sub.t] -0.8718 0.827
[DidCWin.sub.t-1] -6.8602 0.098
Const -5.7233 0.495
Pseudo-[R.sup.2] 0.12
(B) Two Donors
[d.sub.1] + [d.sub.2] -- --
[d.sub.far] - [d.sub.close] 0.0073 0.056
[([l.sub.far] - [c.sub.1]).sup.2] 0.0006 0.559
[([l.sub.close] - [c.sub.1]).sup.2] 0.0043 0.060
([l.sub.far] - [c.sub.1])([l.sub.close] - -0.0008 0.604
[c.sub.1])
[c.sub.1] > max [l.sub.j] -14.4236 0.118
[c.sub.1] 0.1807 0.112
[DidCMove.sub.t-1] 0.2564 0.102
[DidCWin.sub.t-1] -2.5762 0.702
Const -20.0482 0.152
Pseudo-[R.sup.2] 0.16
(C) Three Donors
[d.sub.1] + [d.sub.2] + [d.sub.3] -0.02277 0.089
[([l.sub.far] - [c.sub.1]).sup.2] -0.00227 0.194
[([l.sub.close] - [c.sub.1]).sup.2] -0.00143 0.864
([l.sub.far] - [c.sub.1])([l.sub.close] - 0.00419 0.424
[c.sub.1])
[c.sub.1] -0.32116 0.238
[DidCMove.sub.t-1] -0.25801 0.245
[DidCWin.sub.t-1] -19.64494 0.122
Const 92.06109 0.015
Pseudo-[R.sup.2] 0.16
NA
Coef p value
(A) One Donor
[d.sub.1] 0.0083 0.006
[([l.sub.1] - [c.sub.1]).sup.2] 0.0032 0.000
[c.sub.1] -0.0609 0.306
[DidCMove.sub.t-1] 0.1357 0.067
[([c.sub.1] > [l.sub.1]).sub.t] 13.4470 0.017
[DidCWin.sub.t-1] -11.6556 0.032
Const -5.9320 0.585
Pseudo-[R.sup.2] 0.18
(B) Two Donors
[d.sub.1] + [d.sub.2] -- --
[d.sub.far] - [d.sub.close] 0.0073 0.100
[([l.sub.far] - [c.sub.1]).sup.2] 0.0017 0.077
[([l.sub.close] - [c.sub.1]).sup.2] -0.0020 0.385
([l.sub.far] - [c.sub.1])([l.sub.close] - -0.0041 0.013
[c.sub.1])
[c.sub.1] > max [l.sub.j] -6.5492 0.501
[c.sub.1] 0.1649 0.166
[DidCMove.sub.t-1] -0.0885 0.650
[DidCWin.sub.t-1] -14.3803 0.032
Const 6.9814 0.519
Pseudo-[R.sup.2] 0.16
(C) Three Donors
[d.sub.1] + [d.sub.2] + [d.sub.3] 0.00636 0.454
[([l.sub.far] - [c.sub.1]).sup.2] 0.00077 0.534
[([l.sub.close] - [c.sub.1]).sup.2] -0.00577 0.279
([l.sub.far] - [c.sub.1])([l.sub.close] - 0.00495 0.123
[c.sub.1])
[c.sub.1] -0.33498 0.076
[DidCMove.sub.t-1] 0.01469 0.926
[DidCWin.sub.t-1] -3.08585 0.771
Const 18.60955 0.575
Pseudo-[R.sup.2] 0.18
Notes: The dependent variable is [ly.sub.1], - [c.sub.1] I. Subscript
"far" ("close") refers to the furthest (closest) donor from the
candidate. Dummy "[DidCMove.sub.t-1]" equals 1 if the candidate
deviated in the last round; dummy ([c.sub.1] > [l.sub.1]), equals 1
if the candidate is more centrist than a donor; [DidCWin.sub.t-1] is
1 if the candidate won in the last period.
TABLE 4
Fixed-Effect Panel Estimation of Donors' Behavior
FA
Coef p value
(A) One Donor
[Dist.sub.j] -0.2365 0.007
[[rho].sub.1] -17.3125 0.627
[c.sub.1] > [l.sub.j] 10.4892 0.063
[Winner.sub.t-1] -0.3626 0.949
[r.sub.j] * *
Const 61.3734 0.001
[R.sup.2] 0.07
(B) Two Donors
[Dist.sub.j] -0.2039 0.000
[Dist.sub.-j] 0.0153 0.774
[Dist.sub.-j] x Between -0.0444 0.594
Between -3.2730 0.487
[[rho].sub.1] -35.5745 0.050
[r.sub.j] * *
Const 56.3912 0.000
[R.sup.2] 0.18
(C) Three Donors
[Dist.sub.j] -0.0997 0.000
[DistFar.sub.-j] 0.0151 0.652
[DistClose.sub.-j] 0.0573 0.142
[DistFar.sub.-j] x Between -0.0596 0.259
[DistClose.sub.-j] x Between -0.0149 0.784
Between 5.8475 0.110
[[rho].sub.1] 6.0823 0.776
[r.sub.j] * *
Const 17.3861 0.205
[R.sup.2] 0.23
PA
Coef p value
(A) One Donor
[Dist.sub.j] -0.1997 0.011
[[rho].sub.1] -50.8287 0.122
[c.sub.1] > [l.sub.j] 0.3994 0.937
[Winner.sub.t-1] -17.6179 0.001
[r.sub.j] * *
Const 103.5374 0.000
[R.sup.2] 0.12
(B) Two Donors
[Dist.sub.j] -0.1721 0.000
[Dist.sub.-j] 0.1112 0.016
[Dist.sub.-j] x Between -0.1638 0.023
Between 6.9265 0.089
[[rho].sub.1] -8.0679 0.605
[r.sub.j] * *
Const 43.6188 0.000
[R.sup.2] 0.17
(C) Three Donors
[Dist.sub.j] -0.1585 0.000
[DistFar.sub.-j] 0.1303 0.003
[DistClose.sub.-j] -0.0013 0.979
[DistFar.sub.-j] x Between -0.1821 0.007
[DistClose.sub.-j] x Between 0.0840 0.226
Between 10.3648 0.026
[[rho].sub.1] 0.1208 0.996
[r.sub.j] * *
Const 17.3162 0.321
[R.sup.2] 0.29
NA
Coef p value
(A) One Donor
[Dist.sub.j] -0.1321 0.094
[[rho].sub.1] -51.8785 0.174
[c.sub.1] > [l.sub.j] -18.2987 0.037
[Winner.sub.t-1] -6.8306 0.176
[r.sub.j] -284,320 0.088
Const 125.1650 0.000
[R.sup.2] 0.08
(B) Two Donors
[Dist.sub.j] -0.0801 0.030
[Dist.sub.-j] 0.0283 0.573
[Dist.sub.-j] x Between -0.1231 0.115
Between 6.0070 0.172
[[rho].sub.1] -10.8731 0.660
[r.sub.j] 31,459 0.469
Const 36.6782 0.027
[R.sup.2] 0.06
(C) Three Donors
[Dist.sub.j] -0.0631 0.021
[DistFar.sub.-j] 0.0183 0.579
[DistClose.sub.-j] -0.0409 0.287
[DistFar.sub.-j] x Between 0.0259 0.616
[DistClose.sub.-j] x Between 0.0304 0.574
Between -4.6547 0.192
[[rho].sub.1] -6.7470 0.776
[r.sub.j] 5,465 0.859
Const 33.6528 0.036
[R.sup.2] 0.07
Notes: The dependent variable is donation of donor j as a percentage
of total donatable endowment. Independent variables include
[Dist.sub.j] = [absolute value of [l.sub.j] - [c.sub.1]];
[Dist.sub.-j] = [absolute value of [l.sub.-j] - [c.sub.1]] in
two-donor treatments; [DistFar.sub.-j] = [max.sub.k [not equal to] j]
[absolute value of [l.sub.k] - [c.sub.1]] and Dist-[Close.sub.-j] =
[mink.sub.k [not equal to] j] [absolute value of [l.sub.k] -
[c.sub.1] in three-donor treatments. Variable [[rho].sub.1] is the
initial election probability. Variable Between is equal to 1 if the
candidate is located between donors; [c.sub.1] > [l.sub.j] is equal
to 1 when donor j is to the left of the candidate; [Winner.sub.t-1]
is equal to 1 if the candidate won the election last period. Finally,
[r.sub.j] is the marginal impact of donor j's contributions.
TABLE 5
Average Voter Welfare and the No Donation Benchmark by Treatment
One Donor Two Donors Three Donors
Observed Benchmark Observed Benchmark Observed Benchmark
FA 3607 3594 3547 3536 3373 3432
PA 3578 3594 3464 3536 3457 3432
NA 3590 3594 3514 3536 3506 3432
TABLE 6
Average Donor Welfare and the No Donation Benchmark by Treatment
One Donor Two Donors Three Donors
Observed Benchmark Observed Benchmark Observed Benchmark
FA 3339 3439 2889 2648 3153 2626
PA 3526 3439 3550 2648 3412 2626
NA 3442 3439 3529 2648 3779 2626
COPYRIGHT 2016 Western Economic Association International
No portion of this article can be reproduced without the express written permission from the copyright holder.
Copyright 2016 Gale, Cengage Learning. All rights reserved.