Priming the charitable pump: an experimental investigation of two-stage raffles.
Goerg, Sebastian J. ; Lightle, John P. ; Ryvkin, Dmitry 等
Priming the charitable pump: an experimental investigation of two-stage raffles.
I. INTRODUCTION
Lotteries, or raffles, are widely used as a voluntary fund-raising
mechanism for a variety of causes. Lottery pot sizes range from hundreds
of dollars at small-scale church and community organized events to
hundreds of millions of dollars in state lotteries. (1) Small-scale
raffles are often conducted for charitable causes, such as disaster
relief efforts, with proceeds transferred to charitable organizations.
The implementation of fixed-prize raffles in the field may be
challenging because the organizers can end up losing money if the total
proceeds from the raffle are smaller than the value of the fixed-prize.
Self-financing raffles in which the prize is generated through donations
themselves are, therefore, an attractive alternative. Very popular in
this class are simple 50-50 raffles, in which one half of the ticket
proceeds goes to the winner and the other half is used for the
raffle's charitable cause.
The goal of a 50-50 charity raffle is simply to sell as many
tickets as possible in order to maximize revenue for the charity. One
way to sell more tickets may be to advertise the size of the pot while
raffle tickets are for sale. One common example is to announce the pot
size of a 50-50 raffle at halftime of a sporting event. (2) If a larger
pot size makes raffle tickets more attractive, then revealing the
intermediate pot size increases the sales to second-half buyers,
especially if the pot size is larger than what they expected it to be.
Another possibility is that the halftime announcement actually changes
the incentives that participants face when buying tickets. It may be
possible to observe strategic contributions by the more charitable
participants in the first half to make less charitable participants
contribute more in the second half as the pot size becomes more
attractive. We refer to the effect, be it strategic or not, of a larger
intermediate pot size inducing higher contributions in the second half
as priming the pump of a raffle.
The goal of this paper is to better understand bidder behavior in
these sorts of raffles where the intermediate pot size is revealed, so
that organizers can earn more money for their charity. By comparing
different raffle mechanisms in a controlled laboratory environment, we
can isolate those aspects of bidder behavior that an organizer may
capitalize on. More specifically, we study whether priming the pump
occurs with modifications of a simple 50-50 raffle. In our two-stage
raffles participants can buy raffle tickets twice. The proceeds from
ticket sales in the first stage are added to the pot of the second
stage. We consider two types of two-stage raffles. In the complete draw
down two-stage raffle, all the tickets purchased at the first stage are
destroyed, that is, the proceeds of the first stage are used as seed
money for the second stage. In the no draw down two-stage raffle, the
tickets purchased at the first stage continue to participate in the
second-stage draw, that is, the difference between this raffle and the
standard (one-stage) raffle is purely informational: participants
observe the first-stage donations and can donate more if they like.
Our study can be classified as a mixture of a laboratory and framed
field experiment (Harrison and List 2004; List 2008). Although the
experiment is conducted in standard laboratory conditions with students
as subjects, we do not use induced valuations of the public good, but
instead allow subjects to contribute money to an actual charity. (3)
This reduces the amount of control we have over subjects'
incentives but provides a more immediate external validity to our
results.
Using a model of a charity raffle where bidders have a
heterogeneous warm glow of donating to the charity, we show that under
certain conditions on the participants' preferences priming the
pump of the two-stage raffle occurs in equilibrium. However, priming the
pump increases revenues only if there is a drawing down of tickets after
the first stage. Therefore, the rational warm glow model predicts that
the complete draw down raffle outperforms the others. We also show that
in the class of two-stage raffles with a draw down, the complete draw
down raffle should produce the strongest priming effect.
In the experiment, we find that initially both two-stage raffles
yield significantly higher contributions than the one-stage raffle. Over
time, contributions in the complete draw down raffle decline, similar to
the often observed pattern of declining public good contributions in
voluntary contribution mechanisms. Surprisingly, contributions remain
high in the no draw down raffle.
People often purchase lottery tickets when no charity is involved.
However, a rational self-interested bidder would not choose to
participate in a 50-50 raffle regardless of pot size, unless they were
non-trivially risk seeking. Still, a large pot is attractive in a
pecuniary sense, and one can easily imagine that some participants
mistakenly believe that purchasing tickets when the pot size is large is
a good bet for their pocket books. Beliefs like that may arise in the
presence of boundedly rational cognitive biases. For example, a subject
who ignores the strategic element of the raffle and thinks that her
probability of winning depends only on her own number of tickets
purchased would hold such beliefs. Unlike in the rational warm glow
model, this effect would work whether or not the tickets in the first
stage are drawn down. Therefore, this type of bounded rationality can
explain why the no draw down raffle outperforms the others.
The rest of the paper is structured as follows. In Section II, we
provide a brief review of the related literature. In Section III, we set
up a rational warm glow-based model of two-stage raffles and derive its
testable predictions for our treatments. Thereafter, we introduce the
experimental design and procedures (Section IV) and analyze our
experimental data (Section V). Section VI provides a discussion of the
results and Section VII concludes.
II. RELATED LITERATURE
The literature on the efficiency of public good provision through
raffles goes back to Morgan (2000) who showed that a raffle can generate
more money than a standard voluntary contribution mechanism (VCM). (4)
The reason is that the free-riding problem of public good provision is
partially mitigated by the negative externalities imposed on one another
by the raffle participants. This finding is supported by a number of
experimental studies. (5) While in some environments fixed-prize raffles
can produce more money than 50-50 self-financing raffles (Dale 2004),
they also create a possibility for organizers to lose money (e.g.,
Landry et al. 2006).
Several authors explored multistage fundraising mechanisms where
the proceeds from earlier stages are revealed. Carpenter, Holmes, and
Matthews (2014) proposed a "bucket" all-pay auction in which
bidders sequentially add money to the pot until all but one bidder drop
out and find that it generates more money than the standard all-pay
auction in a laboratory experiment. Lange (2006) proposes a two-stage
modification of the public good lottery mechanism of Morgan (2000): the
second stage lottery prize is comprised of voluntary public good
contributions of the first stage. (6) It is shown that for a wide range
of conditions the resulting equilibrium donations exceed those of the
standard VCM under the same preferences. Although our complete draw down
two-stage raffle is similar to the mechanism proposed by Lange (2006),
the important differences in our setting are in that the second-stage
proceeds are also added to the prize, and the prize is then divided
equally between the charity and the winner. Thus, our second-stage
raffle has both the fixed prize and the variable prize elements to it.
III. MODEL
We model a two-stage charity raffle where there is a potential
drawing down of tickets from the first stage to the second. There are n
[greater than or equal to] 2 risk- neutral bidders indexed by i = 1,
..., n, whose utility functions are given by
[u.sub.i] = [w.sub.i] + [g.sub.i] ([d.sub.i]) + [[beta].sub.i]
[n.summation over (j=1)] [d.sub.j], i = 1, ..., n.
Here, [w.sub.i] is the amount of a numeraire good of bidder i and
[d.sub.i] is bidder i's donation to the charity. The functions
[g.sub.i](*) are common knowledge and [g'.sub.i] > 0,
[g".sub.i] < 0 for all bidders. Following Andreoni (1990), we
model charitable preferences with a concern for the total group
contribution, parameterized by commonly known coefficients
[[beta].sub.i] [member of] [0,1), as well as a concern for one's
personal level of contribution, measured by [g.sub.i](*). Each bidder
has an initial endowment e of the numeraire. Tickets are sold at a unit
cost. In Stage 1, bidder i chooses to buy [x.sub.i] tickets, with the
constraint [x.sub.i] [less than or equal to] e.
Let X = [[summation].sub.i] [x.sub.i] denotes the total number of
tickets sold in the first stage. After Stage 1, all but S(X) tickets are
removed from the active pool of tickets. In Stage 2, bidder i chooses to
buy [y.sub.i] tickets, with the constraint [x.sub.i] + [y.sub.i] [less
than or equal to] e. Let Y = [[summation].sub.i] [y.sub.i] denotes the
total number of tickets sold in the second stage, and these are added to
the S(X) tickets that remain after the first stage. One ticket out of
the S(X) + Y active tickets is randomly selected as the winner, and the
owner of the ticket receives a fraction [alpha] [member of] (0,1) of the
total amount collected while the charity receives a fraction 1 - [alpha]
of the proceeds.
In the following two sections we consider two special cases of the
general two-stage raffle described above corresponding to our
experimental treatments. First is the benchmark case of no draw down,
S(X) = X, which leads to no priming of the pump and the same aggregate
donations in equilibrium as the one-stage raffle. Second, at the other
extreme, is the case of complete draw down, S(X) = 0, which, in
equilibrium, produces the strongest priming effect in the class of
two-stage raffles with partial draw down (for a proof of this statement,
see Appendix S1, Supporting Information).
A. No Draw Down
Consider the two-stage charity raffle with no drawing down of
tickets, or S(X) = X. In the second stage, bidder i chooses [y.sub.i]
[member of] [0, e - [x.sub.i]]. Given the first-stage outcomes of
[x.sub.i] and X, bidder i's expected utility is equal to
[EU.sub.i] ([y.sub.i]|X) = e - (1 - [alpha]) ([x.sub.i] +
[y.sub.i]) + [g.sub.i] ((1 - [alpha]) ([x.sub.i] + [y.sub.i])) +
[[beta].sub.i](1 - [alpha]) (X + Y).
The first-order condition for maximization of expected utility over
[y.sub.i] is
(1) 1 - [[beta].sub.i] [greater than or equal to] [g'.sub.i]
((1 - [alpha]) ([x.sub.i] - [y.sub.i])),
with equality for [y.sub.i] [member of] (0, e - [x.sub.i]).
Equation (1) shows that each bidder's total optimal
contribution, [x.sub.i] + [y.sub.i] is independent of other
bidders' actions and constitutes a dominant strategy of buying a
total number of tickets equal to [(1 - [alpha]).sup.-1]
[g'.sup.-1.sub.i] (1 - [[beta].sub.i]), or e if their endowment is
reached. It does not matter to the bidders at which stage they purchase
the tickets. Let [P.sup.ND] = X + Y be the pot size when each bidder
chooses their optimal number of tickets in the two-stage charity raffle
with no draw down. Note that PND is the same as the pot size of a
standard one-stage raffle. This is because tickets purchased in the
first and second stage are perfect substitutes, and having multiple
opportunities to buy them does not change the aggregate equilibrium
outcome. Let [[??].sub.i] = min {[(1 - [alpha]).sup.-1]
[g'.sup.-1.sub.i] (1 - [[beta].sub.i]), e} be bidder i's
optimal number of tickets purchased in the second stage if X = 0, and
[??] = [[summation].sub.i] [[??].sub.i]. Then, because bidders are
indifferent to purchasing all their tickets in the second stage,
[P.sup.ND] = [??].
B. Complete Draw Down
Consider the two-stage charity raffle with a complete draw down
where every ticket from the first stage is eliminated from the active
pool of tickets, that is, S(X) = 0. In the second stage, bidder i
chooses [y.sub.i] [member of] [0, e - [x.sub.i]]. Given the first-stage
outcomes of [x.sub.i] and X, bidder i's expected utility is equal
to
[MATHEMATICAL EXPRESSION NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII]
The first-order condition for maximization of expected utility over
[y.sub.i] is
(2) 1 - [[beta].sub.i] - {[[alpha]X (Y - [y.sub.i])]/[(1 -
[alpha])[Y.sup.2]]} [greater than or equal to] [g'.sub.i] (1 -
[alpha]) ([x.sub.i] + [y.sub.i])),
with equality for [y.sub.i] [member of] (0, e - [x.sub.i]). Let
[P.sup.CD] = X + Y denotes the resulting pot size under complete draw
down. By comparing the first-order conditions (1) and (2), we arrive at
the following proposition.
PROPOSITION 1. Provided that there is at least one active bidder in
the first stage (X > 0), there are at least two active bidders in the
second stage (Y > [y.sub.i]), and for at least one active bidder the
budget constraint does not bind under no draw down ([[??].sub.i] <
e), the equilibrium pot size under complete draw down is greater than
under no draw down, [P.sup.CD] > [P.sup.ND].
The intuition behind this result is that the marginal cost of
purchasing a ticket under complete draw down is offset by the chance
that the bidder could win the raffle, when X > 0, and it is this term
(which appears in (2) but not in (1)) which implies [P.sup.CD] >
[P.sup.ND] because [g".sub.i] < 0.
Equation (2) also shows that every bidder's total
contribution, [x.sub.i] + [y.sub.i] is an increasing function of the
aggregate first-stage contribution, X. Thus, if bidder i did not
contribute in the first stage ([x.sub.i] = 0), her second-stage
contribution is an increasing function of the first-stage contributions
of other bidders. (7) We refer to this effect as "priming the
charitable pump" because it is through this mechanism that more
charitable bidders, by bidding in the first stage, can induce less
charitable bidders to bid more in the second stage.
PROPOSITION 2. (Priming the charitable pump) Suppose bidder i is
not active in the first stage, [x.sub.i] = 0. Then, provided
[[??].sub.i] < e and [[??].sub.i] < [??], bidder i's optimal
second-stage bid, [y.sub.i], is increasing in the first-stage donations
X.
We now turn to the analysis of equilibrium bidding in the first
stage and derive conditions under which X can be larger than zero in
equilibrium.
PROPOSITION 3. There exists a subgame perfect equilibrium of the
two-stage raffle with complete draw down with at least one bidder
priming the charitable pump by purchasing tickets in the first round (X
> 0) if for some bidder i,
(3) [MATHEMATICAL EXPRESSION NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII].
In Appendix S1, we prove Proposition 3 by showing that when X = 0,
the marginal utility of buying a ticket in the first stage is positive
for some bidder given the assumptions of the model and condition (3).
Proposition 3 establishes a sufficient condition for priming the
charitable pump in equilibrium. In Appendix SI, we demonstrate that the
condition can hold for a variety of parameterizations.
C. Hypotheses
Given the theoretical findings of this section, we establish the
following experimental hypotheses.
HYPOTHESIS 1: Two-stage raffles with no draw down generate the same
aggregate contributions as one-stage raffles.
HYPOTHESIS 2: Two-stage raffles with complete draw down generate
larger aggregate contributions than two-stage raffles with no draw down
(and one-stage raffles).
HYPOTHESIS 3: In a two-stage raffle with complete draw down, an
increase in group donations in the first stage leads to an increase in
individual donations in the second stage.
IV. EXPERIMENTAL DESIGN
The previous section demonstrated that in theory two-stage raffles
might have an advantage over traditional one-stage raffles. To provide
empirical support, we conducted an experiment with three different
raffle types: a classic one-stage raffle (1STAGE), a two-stage raffle
with complete draw down (2STAGECOMPDRAW), and a two-stage raffle with no
draw down (2STAGENODRAW). In all three treatments, a real charity
organization (United Way of the Big Bend, a local chapter of United Way)
was the beneficiary of half of the proceeds.
All sessions were conducted at the XS/FS laboratory at Florida
State University between November 2012 and January 2013. The experiment
was programmed in z-Tree (Fischbacher 2007), with 216 subjects recruited
through ORSEE (Greiner 2004) from a pool of roughly 3,000 pre-registered
FSU students. We conducted three sessions per treatment with 24 subjects
in each session divided into three groups of eight. Table 1 gives an
overview of observations and some of the subjects' characteristics.
Upon arrival, subjects were seated in cubicles, the printed
instructions were distributed and read to the subjects. Thereafter, a
printout of the mission statement of the charity (United Way of the Big
Bend) was distributed and read to the subjects. (8) Providing the
subjects with the mission statement ensured that all subjects were
informed about the main goals of the charity.
After the instructions had been provided and all questions posed by
the subjects were answered, the corresponding charity raffle was played.
Subjects received an endowment of $8.00 and could buy raffle tickets at
a cost of 10 cents per ticket. In the two treatments with two-stage
raffles, total proceeds after the first stage were shown before subjects
decided how many tickets to buy at the second stage.
After the first raffle had been played, it was announced that it
would be followed by an additional 10 periods of the same raffle in the
same fixed groups of eight subjects. In each of the 10 additional
periods, subjects started with an initial endowment of $8.00, but only
one of the 10 periods was randomly selected at the end for actual
payments, in addition to the first raffle.
At the end of the experiment, risk attitudes were elicited with the
Holt and Laury (2002) instrument, followed by a set of post-experimental
questionnaires. First, subjects self-assessed their risk attitudes in
different domains (Dohmen et al. 2011). Second, subjects were asked
whether they donated any amount during the last year. Third, subjects
reported their gender and age. For summary statistics of the Holt and
Laury (2002) task and the other post-experimental questionnaires refer
to Table S1 in Appendix S1. (9) After the experiment, all participants
were paid and one random participant monitored the transfer of half of
the total donations to the charity. Each session lasted between 60 and
90 minutes with average earnings per subject of around $22.45, including
a show-up fee of $7.00.
V. RESULTS
In this section we present the results of our experiment. We first
focus on the aggregate treatment effects, that is, identify the ranking
of the three raffles in terms of the revenue they generated. We then
take a closer look at the two two-stage raffles and investigate whether
priming of the charitable pump actually occurred in our experiment.
A. Overall Comparison of Raffles
Table 2 gives the mean, median, and standard deviation of the
number of raffle tickets bought in each treatment for the duration of
the whole experiment, as well as separately for the first and second
part of the experiment. Overall, both two-stage raffles lead to higher
mean/median donations than the one-stage raffle. However, only the
overall comparison of 2StageNoDraw with ISTAGE is statistically
significant (p=.0035, two-sided Mann-Whitney U test),10 while the
comparison of 2StageCompDraw with ISTAGE remains insignificant
(p=.4735). Overall, 2STAGENODRAW generates significantly higher ticket
sales than the other two-stage raffle, 2StageCompDraw (p=.0751).
The majority of the subjects participated actively in each period:
61% of subjects in 2STAGENODRAW buy raffle tickets in all 11 periods,
54% and 64% do so in 2StageCompDraw and 1STAGE, respectively. As a
result, no significant differences in the average number of periods in
which subjects participate in the raffle through the purchase of tickets
are observed (two-sided Kruskal-Wallis rank test p=.83).
Thus, the significant differences in overall contributions are
driven by an increased amount of tickets bought per subject and not by a
change in the inclination to buy raffle tickets at all. This is shown in
Figure 1 which gives the distribution of the fraction of the endowment
spent on raffle tickets. This distribution is skewed to the right in
ISTAGE with the mass of the distribution on low amounts of endowment
spent. This skewness is reduced in 2StageCompDraw and even more so in
2STAGENODRAW.
We now turn to the change in donations over time: Figure 2 shows
average total donations by period. Already in the first period are
donations significantly larger in 2STAGENODRAW compared to those of
1Stage (p=.0210, two-sided Mann-Whitney U test). However, the difference
between 2STAGECOMPDRAW and 2StageNoDraw develops only over time. In the
first period it is not significant (p=.5652), but the difference
increases over time as median ticket sales decrease in 2STAGECOMPDRAW.
Ultimately, it becomes significant for the second part of the experiment
(p=.0455). The comparison between2STAGECOMPDRAW and 1STAGE reveals a
significant difference for the first period (p=.0069), but over the
course of the second part of the experiment this difference vanishes
(p=.6546). Comparing the median ticket sales in the first part of the
experiment with the ones in the second part demonstrates rather stable
behavior in 2StageNoDraw (p=.5533, two-sided Wilcoxon signed-rank test),
while raffle sales drop significantly in 2StageCompDraw (p=.0283) and
1Stage (p=.0074).
Before taking a closer look at the two-stage raffles, we complement
the analysis presented above with a series of tobit regressions given in
Table 3. Models (1) and (2) replicate our previous results:
significantly higher donations in 2STAGENODRAW than in 1Stage and
donations that significantly decrease over time in 2STAGECOMPDRAW.
Donations increase with the number of raffle wins in the previous
periods included in Model (3). (11) In Model (4) we include additional
variables to control for subjects' individual characteristics. Age
and gender do not have a significant impact on the number of tickets
bought, but a higher willingness to take risks (12) and previous
donations to charities are associated with an increase in the number of
tickets bought. Our main treatment effects remain significant; we thus
arrive at the first result, which stands in sharp contrast to our
Hypotheses 1 and 2.
RESULT 1: (a) Overall, significantly more tickets are purchased in
the two-stage raffle with no draw down than in the one-stage raffle and
the two-stage raffle with complete draw down.
(b) In the two-stage raffle with complete draw down, the number of
tickets purchased decreases over time until they reach the level of the
one-stage raffle.
B. Comparing the Two-Stage Raffles
For comparison of the two-stage raffles, we analyze first-stage and
second-stage donations separately. Figure 3 gives the absolute number of
tickets bought as well as the fraction of possible tickets bought in the
first and second stages. (13)
Clearly, first stage donations are significantly higher in
2StageNoDraw compared to 2StageCompDraw (p = .0380, two-sided
Mann-Whitney U test). In 2StageCompDraw, donations in the first stage
are only driven by the concern for the charity as they do not increase
the likelihood of winning the raffle. However, tickets bought in the
second stage increase the chance to win the raffle in both treatments
and thus similar fractions of tickets are bought (p = .1711).
The tobit regressions presented in Table 4 explain the number of
tickets bought at each stage in the two-stage raffles. The dependent
variable in these regressions is the fraction of available tickets,
which is x/80 at stage 1 and y/(80 - x) at stage 2. Models (1) and (2)
replicate our nonparametric results and show that in the first stage
significantly less tickets were bought in 2StageCompDraw than in
2StageNoDraw. This difference increases even more over time as the
number of tickets bought decreases significantly in 2StageCompDraw.
Winning the raffle in previous rounds, being female, and/or having a
higher willingness to take risks leads to an increase in the number of
tickets bought in the first stage, while the main treatment and time
effects remain significant.
RESULT 2: Significantly more tickets are purchased in the first
stage of the two-stage raffle with no draw down than in the first stage
of the two-stage raffle with complete draw down. This difference
increases even further over time.
As Models (3) and (4) demonstrate, no significant treatment effect
(neither overall nor as a treatment-specific time trend) is observed in
the second stage. As in the first stage, lower risk-aversion leads to
more purchased tickets in the second stage. In addition, subjects who
won the raffle in previous rounds are more willing to buy new raffle
tickets. The most important result, however, emerges when we take a
closer look at the influence of the first-stage donations on
second-stage donations: an increase in the aggregate donations of the
other group members in the first stage ([X.sup.Others.sub.Stage1]) leads
to an increase in the number of tickets bought at Stage 2. Variable
[X.sup.Others.sub.Stage1] is defined as the sum of tickets bought in a
group minus the tickets bought by oneself and, thus, its impact on
tickets bought in the second stage can be substantial. The average total
number of tickets bought by others in a group in the first stage
([X.sup.Others.sub.Stage1] = 113) would increase the average fraction of
income spent on tickets in the second stage by roughly 13.5%. (14) This
effect was predicted by Hypothesis 3 for the treatment 2StageCompDraw.
However, it turns out that the effect is also present in 2StageNoDraw
and that it is equally strong in both two-stage raffles. (15)
RESULT 3: There is evidence of priming the charitable pump in that
the number of tickets purchased at the second stage increases in the
aggregate first-stage contributions of other group members.
VI. DISCUSSION
Our analysis reveals two important results. First, we identified a
two-stage raffle mechanism that performs significantly better than the
standard one-stage 50-50 raffle. Interestingly, and in stark contrast
with the theoretical predictions, the mechanism that leads to the
highest donation levels is the no draw down raffle. In what follows we
discuss possible alternate explanations for this result. Second, in
agreement with the theory, priming the charitable pump does occur.
Higher group donations in the first stage lead to higher donations of
individuals in the second stage. So, what is driving these results?
We can dismiss explanations based on the learning of charitable
preferences of the other group members. In each treatment the subjects
played 11 rounds, which should have given them enough time to learn
those preferences by observing past group donations even in the
one-stage raffle. Still we find that the difference between treatments
remains strong or even increases over time. Neither can the results be
explained by joy of winning as it should increase donations in all
treatments equally. Rather, we believe the observed results are amenable
to an explanation involving bounded rationality and heterogeneous
charitable preferences.
Recall that priming the pump works in both two-stage raffles and
now consider subjects' behavior in Stage 2 of the no draw down
raffle. If a subject has charitable preferences, it is rational for her
to purchase tickets in one of the two stages, and it might as well be
the second stage. This incentive to give does not depend on the pot
size. Furthermore, it is never rational to buy tickets for purely
pecuniary concerns regardless of the pot size unless the subject is very
risk seeking. (16) One plausible explanation for why many subjects
purchase more tickets in Stage 2 when the pot size is larger is a
version of bounded rationality termed solipsism bias', that is,
some bidders fail to account for the negative effect of pot size on
their probability of winning, or equivalently, they simply do not
consider the expected value of a raffle ticket when deciding how many
tickets to buy. The notion of solipsism bias was first introduced by
Guarino, Huck, and Jeitschko (2006) as a behavioral explanation for the
surprisingly high degree of coordination stability they observed in
networks. For raffles, the presence of solipsism bias is suggested by
the results of Lim, Matros, and Turocy (2009) who found that in a
one-stage raffle experiment subjects do not change the spending as the
group size increases from two to nine participants. A bidder with a
solipsistic bias will mistakenly believe that buying raffle tickets is
more attractive when the pot size is large. Thus, priming the charitable
pump can occur in an environment where theoretically it should not.
We also believe that subjects have heterogeneous preferences over
the total amount donated to the charity. (17) In the no draw down
raffles, the most charitable subjects have an incentive to buy more
tickets than they otherwise would in the first stage, in order to induce
noncharitable subjects to buy more tickets in the second stage. In our
experiment, the first-stage contributions in no draw down were larger
than the first-stage contributions in complete draw down. This is
exactly what we would expect to happen given the bounded rationality and
heterogeneous charitable preferences described above because buying a
first-stage ticket in the no draw down treatment has approximately the
same power to prime the charitable pump with the added bonus that the
ticket can win a substantial amount of money.
VII. CONCLUSIONS
In this paper, we experimentally investigated two-stage charity
raffles in which participants can buy tickets in two stages. The
proceeds of the first stage are used as the seed money for the second
stage. In the complete draw down two-stage raffle, the first stage
tickets are eliminated from the active pool of tickets, while in the no
draw down raffle they remain in the active pool. In addition, we
conducted a standard one-stage 50-50 raffle as a benchmark.
We find that both two-stage raffles initially perform significantly
better than the standard one-stage 50-50 raffle. Over time, the
aggregate contribution level in the complete draw down raffle declines
and approaches that of the one-stage raffle. In contrast, contributions
in the no draw down raffle are stable and remain significantly higher
than in the other two mechanisms. In agreement with the theory, priming
the charitable pump does occur. Higher group donations in the first
stage lead to higher donations of individuals in the second stage, and
this effect is especially strong in the two stage raffle with complete
draw down.
The charity raffles we studied have the advantage of being
self-financed, that is, the participants in the raffle generate the
prize. Thus, the organizers bear no risk while fixed-prize auctions or
raffles might lead to donations below the value of the prize and to
losses for the charity (e.g., Landry et al. 2006). Our paper
demonstrates that two-stage raffles can significantly increase the
proceeds of those risk-free raffles.
Our results cannot be explained by a standard warm glow model of
charitable giving or a combination of this model with joy of winning and
learning about others' preferences. One possible explanation is a
boundedly rational behavior which involves "solipsistic"
bidders who mistakenly believe that their probability of winning the
raffle does not depend on the pot size. The presence of such bidders is
consistent with the results of prior experiments on raffles (e.g., Lim,
Matros, and Turocy 2009). Of course, our experiment was not designed to
test for the presence of solipsism bias; therefore, we only propose it
as one possible explanation for our results and cannot exclude other
versions of bounded rationality as explanations.
The superiority of the no draw down two-stage raffle and the fact
that priming the charitable pump occurs has implications for a large
class of mechanisms designed to generate monetary contributions. If a
charity must use a self-financed raffle mechanism to generate revenue,
the organizers would benefit by making the number of tickets sold public
information. Having a first stage may be a useful way to coordinate the
efforts of charitable participants who will collectively create a pot
size large enough to attract less charitable individuals to participate.
Our experiment shows that it is not necessary for these first-stage
participants to be purely altruistic (as in the case of complete draw
down) and the optimal mechanism should exploit both the desire to win
and the incentive to prime the charitable pump as motivations for
contribution.
doi: 10.1111/ecin.12245
ABBREVIATION
VCM: Voluntary Contribution Mechanism
REFERENCES
Andreoni. J. "Impure Altruism and Donations to Public Goods: A
Theory of Warm-glow Giving." The Economic Journal, 100, 1990,
464-77.
Carpenter, J., J. Holmes, and P. H. Matthews. '"Bucket
Auctions' for Charity." Games and Economic Behavior, 88, 2014,
260-76.
Corazzini, L., M. Faravelli, and L. Stanca. "A Prize to Give
for: An Experiment on Public Good Provision Mechanisms." The
Economic Journal, 120, 2010, 944-67.
Dale, D. "Charitable Lottery Structure and Fund Raising:
Theory and Evidence." Experimental Economics, 1, 2004, 217-34.
Davis, D., L. Razzolini, R. Reilly, and B. Wilson. "Raising
Revenues for Charity: Auctions Versus Lotteries," in Experiments
Investigating Fundraising and Charitable Contributors. Research in
Experimental Economics, Vol. 11, edited by R. Mark Isaac and D. D.
Davis. Bradford, UK: Emerald Group Publishing Limited, 2006, 47-91.
Dohmen, T., A. Falk, D. Huffman, U. Sunde, J. Schupp, and G.
Wagner. "Individual Risk Attitudes: Measurement, Determinants, and
Behavioral Consequences." Journal of the European Economic
Association., 9(3), 2011, 522-50.
Fischbacher, U. "z-Tree: Zurich Toolbox for Readymade Economic
Experiments." Experimental Economics, 10, 2007, 171-8.
Franke, J., and W. Leininger. "On the Efficient Provision of
Public Goods by Means of Lotteries." Working Paper No. 399, RUHR
Economic Papers, Technical University of Dortmund. 2013.
Greiner, B. "An Online Recruitment System for Economic
Experiments," in Forschung und Wissenschaftliches Rechnen 2003.
GWDG Bericht 63, edited by H. Kramer and V. Macho. Goettingen, Germany:
Gesellschaft fur wissenschaftliche Datenverarbeitung Goettingen, 2004,
79-93.
Guarino, A., S. Huck, and T. Jeitschko. "Averting Economic
Collapse and the Solipsism Bias." Games and Economic Behavior, 57,
2006, 264-85.
Harrison, G., and J. List. "Field Experiments." Journal
of Economic Literature, 42(4), 2004, 1009-55.
Holt, C., and K. Laury. "Risk Aversion and Incentive
Effects." American Economic Review, 92(5), 2002, 1644-55.
Isaac, R. M., S. Pevnitskaya, and T. Salmon. "Do Preferences
for Charitable Giving Help Auctioneers?" Experimental Economics,
13, 2010, 14-44.
Landry, C., A. Lange, J. List, M. Price, and N. Rupp. "Toward
an Understanding of the Economics of Charity: Evidence from a Field
Experiment." Quarterly Journal of Economics, 121(2), 2006, 747-82.
Lange, A. "Providing Public Goods in Two Steps."
Economics Letters, 91, 2006, 173-78.
Lange, A., J. List, M. Price, and S. Price "The Optimal Design
of Charitable Lotteries: Theory and Experimental Evidence," in
Experiments Investigating Fundraising and Charitable Contributors.
Research in Experimental Economics, Vol. 11, edited by R. Mark Isaac and
D. D. Davis. Bradford, UK: Emerald Group Publishing Limited, 2006,
93-119.
Lim, W., A. Matros, and T. Turocy. "Raising Revenue with
Raffles: Evidence from a Laboratory Experiment." Department of
Economics Working Paper No. 377, University of Pittsburgh, 2009.
List, J. "Introduction to Field Experiments in Economics with
Applications to the Economics of Charity." Experimental Economics,
11, 2008, 203-12.
Morgan, J. "Financing Public Goods by Means of
Lotteries." Review of Economic Studies, 67, 2000, 761-84.
Morgan, J., and M. Sefton. "Funding Public Goods with
Lotteries: Experimental Evidence." Review of Economic Studies, 67,
2000, 785-810.
Orzen, H. "Fundraising Through Competition: Evidence from the
Lab." CeDEx Discussion Paper No. 2008-11, The University of
Nottingham, 2008.
Varian, H. R. "Sequential Contributions to Public Goods."
Journal of Public Economics, 53, 1994, 165-86.
Vesterlund, L. "The Informational Value of Sequential
Fundraising." Journal of Public Economics, 87, 2003, 627-57.
SUPPORTING INFORMATION
Additional Supporting Information may be found in the online
version of this article:
Appendix SI. (A) Proofs and Examples, (B) Instructions, (C)
Additional Tables and Figures.
(1.) For example, the Florida Lottery transferred more than $1.31
billion to the Educational Enhancement Trust Fund in fiscal year
2011-2012; see http://flalottery.com/education .do.
(2.) Similarly, state lotteries regularly advertise the size of
potential winnings.
(3.) Isaac, Pevnitskaya, and Salmon (2010) used a similar approach
in one of their treatments.
(4.) The total amount of money raised would still be inefficient.
Franke and Leininger (2013) propose an asymmetric mechanism similar to
Morgan (2000) that leads to efficient levels of public good provision.
(5.) See, for example, Morgan and Sefton (2000), Dale (2004), Davis
et al. (2006), Lange et al. (2006), Orzen (2008), and Corazzini,
Faravelli, and Stanca (2010).
(6.) See also Varian (1994) and Vesterlund (2003), among others,
who find that sequential VCMs can generate more revenue than the
standard VCM.
(7.) This would not be the case only for bidders who are giving
their full endowment already, or for those who would have been the only
one buying tickets in the second stage.
(8.) The instructions are provided in Appendix S1. The mission
statement was taken from the charity's website http:// uwbb.org/.
(9.) We did not identify any significant differences in
subjects' responses to the Holt and Laury (2002) measure and other
questionnaire items across the treatments (age: two-sided Kruskal-Wallis
rank test p=.87; gender: two-sided Fisher's exact test p=.50; Holt
and Laury (2002): two-sided Kruskal-Wallis rank test p=.77 financial
risk: two-sided Kruskal-Wallis rank test p=31). We conclude that the
randomization of the subjects into the treatments was successful.
(10.) All nonparametric tests are based on group medians, as
subjects can observe their group's behavior between periods/stages.
Thus, our nonparametric test results are rather conservative.
(11.) The result stays qualitatively the same if we replace the
cumulative number of wins with a dummy for a raffle win in the previous
period or for winning ever in the previous periods.
(12.) Risk attitudes elicited with the Holt and Laury(2002) measure
are significantly correlated with the self-assessed risk attitudes in
the domain of financial risks (Spearman's rank correlation [rho] =
.2464 withpc.001). In the following we base our analysis on the Holt and
Laury (2002) measure, but the results remain robust if the self-assessed
risk attitudes (given on a Likert scale) are used instead.
(13.) In the first stage a maximum of 80 tickets could be bought;
in the second stage the maximal possible number of tickets, 80 - x,
depends on the tickets already bought in the first stage.
(14.) For the highest sum of tickets bought by others in the first
stage ([X.sup.Others.sub.Stage1] = 337) the estimated effect would be
40%.
(15.) The coefficient on interaction 2StageCompDraw x
[X.sup.Others.sub.Stage1], if it is added, would be insignificant, while
the main effect would remain significant.
(16.) This is because the probability of one ticket winning the
raffle is 1/[P.sup.ND], while the revenue from winning is only
[P.sup.ND]/2, where [P.sup.ND] is the pot size of the no draw down
raffle.
(17.) We clearly have evidence that subjects differ in terms of
their charitable donations outside of the experiment. Overall, 76%
reported that they donated to charities at least once during the
previous year, while 24% did not.
SEBASTIAN J. GOERG, JOHN P. LIGHTLE and DMITRY RYVKIN *
* We are grateful to two anonymous referees and the audiences at
the 2012 ESA meeting in Tucson and the 2013 SEA meetings in Tampa for
very helpful comments. Special thanks to Philip Brookins for programming
and help with running the experiment.
Goerg: Department of Economics, Florida State University,
Tallahassee, FL 32311-2ISO. Max Planck Institute for Research in
Collective Goods, Bonn D-53113, Germany. Phone (850) 544-7950, Fax (850)
644-4535, E-mail sgoerg@fsu.edu
Lightle: Department of Economics, Virginia Commonwealth University,
Richmond, VA 23284-4000. Phone (804) 828-1717, Fax (804) 828-9103,
E-mail johnlightle@gmail.com
Ryvkin: Department of Economics, Florida State University,
Tallahassee, FL 32311-2180. Phone (850) 644-7209, Fax (850) 644-4535,
E-mail dryvkin@fsu.edu
TABLE 1
Subjects' Characteristics and Observations by Treatment
Number Number
Average % of of Number of
Treatment Age Female Subjects Groups Observations
1Stage 19.9 53 72 9 792
2StageCompDraw 19.9 60 72 9 792
2StageNoDraw 20.2 58 72 9 792
Overall 20 57 216 27 2,376
TABLE 2
Summary Statistics for Raffle Tickets Bought
Periods 1-11 Part 1 (Period 1)
Treatment Mean Median SD Mean Median SD
1Stage 21.95 10 26.91 23.99 12.5 25.70
2StageCompDraw 25.88 16 27.60 29.59 25 23.83
2StageNoDraw 32.91 25 30.20 35.36 30 26.44
Part 2 (Periods 2-11)
Treatment Mean Median SD
1Stage 21.75 10 27.04
2StageCompDraw 25.50 15 27.94
2StageNoDraw 32.66 25 30.55
TABLE 3
Tobit Regression--Tickets Bought per Subject
Total Tickets Bought (1) (2)
2StageCompDraw -9.2846 -3.3653
(5.731) (5.621)
1Stage -12.7211 ** -12.7163 **
(5.687) (5.684)
Period -0.6060 ** -0.2758
(0.273) (0.346)
2StageCompDraw*Period -0.9954 *
(0.548)
Number of raffle wins
Age
Female
Holt and Laury
Donated within a year
Constant 34.7797 *** 32.8126 ***
(4.001) (3.967)
Observations 2,376 2,376
Number of subjects 216 216
Probability > [chi square] p <.01 p < .005
Total Tickets Bought (3) (4)
2StageCompDraw -3.0854 -3.1659
(5.198) (5.002)
1Stage -12.3652 *** -10.9904 **
(4.535) (4.310)
Period -2.6001 *** -2.4927 ***
(0.413) (0.413)
2StageCompDraw*Period -1.0105 * -1.0181 *
(0.577) (0.569)
Number of raffle wins 18.3409 *** 17.5149 ***
(1.853) (1.836)
Age -0.8278
(1.040)
Female 3.4178
(3.753)
Holt and Laury 1.6184 **
(0.743)
Donated within a year 10.5861 **
(4.171)
Constant 32.9018 *** 30.8921
(3.596) (22.745)
Observations 2,376 2,376
Number of subjects 216 216
Probability > [chi square] p<.0001 p < .0001
Notes: 2StageNoDraw is the reference group, 522 of 2,376 observations
were left-censored (i.e., equal to zero) and 312 were right-censored
(i.e., equal to 80). Subject-level clustered robust standard errors
are in parentheses.
*** p < .01, ** p < .05, * p < .1.
TABLE 4
Tobit Regression--Fraction of Possible Tickets Bought
First Stage
Fraction of possible tickets bought (1) (2)
2StageCompDraw -0.0850 * -0.0822 *
(0.049) (0.049)
Period -0.0084 * -0.0201 ***
(0.005) (0.006)
2StageCompDraw*period -0.0185 *** -0.0185 ***
(0.007) (0.007)
Number of raffle wins 0.0857 ***
(0.020)
Holt and Laury 0.0242 ***
(0.008)
Female 0.1028 **
(0.044)
Age -0.0158
(0.014)
Donated within a year 0.0237
(0.048)
[X.sup.Others.sub.Stage 1]
Constant 0.2059 *** 0.3228
(0.036) (0.297)
Observations 1,584 1,584
Number of subjects 144 144
Probability > [chi square] p < .0001 p < .0001
Second Stage
Fraction of possible tickets bought (3) (4)
2StageCompDraw 0.0420 0.1014
(0.069) (0.067)
Period 0.0004 -0.0240 ***
(0.006) (0.007)
2StageCompDraw*period -0.0090 -0.0065
(0.008) (0.009)
Number of raffle wins 0.2264 ***
(0.032)
Holt and Laury 0.0314 **
(0.012)
Female 0.0042
(0.057)
Age 0.0072
(0.013)
Donated within a year 0.0765
(0.063)
[X.sup.Others.sub.Stage 1] 0.0012 ***
(0.000)
Constant 0.2002 *** -0.3337
(0.048) (0.314)
Observations 1,532 1,532
Number of subjects 144 144
Probability > [chi square] p = .0635 p < .0001
Notes: 2StageNoDraw is the reference group. Subject-level clustered
robust standard errors are in parentheses.
* p < .1; ** p < .05; *** p < .01.
COPYRIGHT 2016 Western Economic Association International
No portion of this article can be reproduced without the express written permission from the copyright holder.
Copyright 2016 Gale, Cengage Learning. All rights reserved.