MACINTYRE, Alasdair. Ethics in the Conflicts of Modernity: An Essay on Desire, Practical Reasoning, and Narrative.
Lewis, V. Bradley
MACINTYRE, Alasdair. Ethics in the Conflicts of Modernity: An Essay on Desire, Practical Reasoning, and Narrative.
MACINTYRE, Alasdair. Ethics in the Conflicts of Modernity: An Essay
on Desire, Practical Reasoning, and Narrative. Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press, 2016. xiii + 322 pp. Cloth, $49.99--In 1966 Alasdair
MacIntyre published A Short History of Ethics, a brilliantly subversive
if highly selective treatment of the main line of Western moral
philosophy that remains in print. MacIntyre has joked that ever since
that book's appearance he has been engaged in writing an
interminably long history of ethics, one that encompasses his trilogy of
After Virtue (1981), Whose Justice? Which Rationality? (1988), and Three
Rival Versions of Moral Enquiry (1990). Ethics in the Conflicts of
Modernity is not a history; nevertheless, MacIntyre's historical
method and subversive aims, so central to the influential 1966 book,
still powerfully animate this volume published almost exactly a half
century later. The book contains a direct and extended confrontation
between MacIntyre's Thomistic-Aristotelian approach to ethics and
that of the modern West.
The book is laid out in five large chapters. The first begins by
asking how desires can lead people's lives to go badly and argues
that making progress on this question requires asking what and under
what circumstances desires can count as good reasons for action. This in
turn leads to philosophical questions about goods themselves and
therefore into the theory of practical reasoning. In contemporary
philosophy this leads into the disagreements associated with the
doctrine known now as "expressivism," a successor to the
emotivism that played such a key role in the early part of After Virtue,
as expounded especially in the work of Alan Gibbard and Simon Blackburn,
supplemented by resources only to be found in Nietzsche and Harry
Frankfort, the last of whom emerges as one of the most indicative moral
thinkers of recent times. The chapter ends with a kind of impasse
between expressivism and MacIntyre's own neo-Aristotelian view.
Expressivism does, however, seem to describe well the culture of
modernity while also exposing incoherences in what MacIntyre calls
throughout "Morality," meaning the morality of modern West, a
view that presents itself as the universal morality of all rational
persons, but that is really the particular product of a certain time and
social order.
In the second chapter, then, MacIntyre addresses that social order
by way of an inquiry into the relationship between certain moral views
and certain social structures and practices. The key transition here is
from a context in which Aquinas's moral thought was taken for
granted into one in which it was almost invisible and for which David
Hume is taken to be the key spokesman. The deep structure of the change
from one to the other is visible with the aid of Marx's account of
the rise of capitalism, an economic system with far reaching effects on
how morality is understood, effects that systematically distort
agents' understanding of their own good.
The third chapter presents a historical and sociological account of
modernity centered on the mutually reinforcing relationship of the
capitalist market and the modern state, which simultaneously works to
impose a particular morality and prevent discussion of alternatives.
MacIntyre argues that we can see successively in the work of Oscar
Wilde, D. H. Lawrence, and especially Bernard Williams the shortcomings
and distortions of modern morality. Williams's concern for
authenticity and the dangers of self-deception pose stiff challenges to
the modern moral project, but MacIntyre argues that his view ultimately
lacks the resources needed to get beyond them. Here we need to acquire
some distance from ourselves and to be able, as it were, to examine our
desires and reasons from the outside and according to standards that
apply not only to me, but to others who may be similarly situated.
MacIntyre identifies such a perspective with his own
Thomistic-Aristotelianism, and it is against Williams's own
objections to Aristotelianism that MacIntyre sketches his alternative in
the book's fourth chapter. Here MacIntyre ranges widely over issues
in the interpretation of Aristotle, attempts by contemporary communities
in Denmark and Brazil to preserve their local autonomy against both
state and market, and recent literature on happiness by economists and
psychologists, all in the service of making his case for a contemporary
neo-Aristotelianism, and he replies explicitly to what he takes to be
Williams's main arguments against his view. The main work of the
chapter is to show how on the Thomistic-Aristotelian view persons come
to understand their moral obligations through reflection on their
desires in pursuit of goods both individual and common. It is the
pursuit of the common goods, however, that lead them into relationships
that provide both salutary distance from their own desires and occasions
for comm on deliberation that contribute both to the development of the
right virtues and to deeper understanding of goods. It is through such
practical and local cooperative activities that we learn and develop as
practical reasoners, but it is precisely those activities that are often
impeded by the social, political, and economic structures of the modern
world, which are grounded in a model of practical reasoning as
maximizing preference satisfaction, bounded, often in ways that are
contradictory, by the rules of "Morality," and managed through
political structures that consist mainly of bargaining among
disproportionately wealthy and privileged elites.
The fifth and final chapter is meant to show the importance of
narrative in the kind of moral thinking MacIntyre champions, not least
in its exemplary illustration of the mistakes and consequent learning
that make up the lives of reflective and self-critical practical
reasoners--in these cases, four practical reasoners from whom MacIntyre
claims to have learned important things: the Soviet novelist Vasily
Grossman, the American Supreme Court Justice Sandra Day O'Connor,
the Anglo-Trinidadian writer C. L. R. James, and the Irish Catholic
priest Dennis Faul.
Ethics in the Conflicts of Modernity is now MacIntyre's
principle statement of his views about moral and political philosophy;
it is a view with which many will disagree, but this fulsome statement,
dense with insights and arguments over a wide range of topics, will
provide great and rewarding labor on questions that cannot be
avoided.--V. Bradley Lewis, The Catholic University of America
COPYRIGHT 2018 Philosophy Education Society, Inc.
No portion of this article can be reproduced without the express written permission from the copyright holder.
Copyright 2018 Gale, Cengage Learning. All rights reserved.