Ori and Neuroscience: A Contextualization of the Yoruba Idea of Causality in the Age of Modern Science.
Adebola, Gbadamosi ; Adebola, Oluwatoyin
Ori and Neuroscience: A Contextualization of the Yoruba Idea of Causality in the Age of Modern Science.
Introduction
Various philosophies guide the way of life of the Yoruba, and the
concept of Ori, a dominant idea of causality, is one of them. Ori, to
the Yoruba, is not just the physical head; rather, it is a force that
features prominently in questioning whether humans are free or not. The
philosophical debate about freewill has been of great importance in the
history of philosophy and within religious circles. Recently,
neuroscientists have joined the quest for an answer to this significant
subject. Within the past few decades, advances in neuroscience have led
to claims that threaten the existence of freewill by the position that
human will is determined by cerebral activities. The concept of Ori
clearly shows that a human being has no power on what has been affixed
to his/her destiny. If what has been affixed to a person must take
place, then he/she is not free.
Thus, the actions of human beings are deterministic, which
threatens the whole idea of human freedom. Abimbola (2006) believes that
the Yoruba concept of Ori cannot be about the standard freewill
determinism issues that exist in Western philosophy. (1) A Yoruba will
say that once destiny is "fixed" by Olorun (God), it cannot be
changed. It must take place. (2) On a similar note, despite the
different issues of determinism between the Yoruba and Western
philosophy, there is a basis for comparison because both the concept of
Ori and the current trends in the field of neuroscience favour
determinism. Recent advances in neuroscience have led to a proposal that
seems incongruent with the traditional notions on freedom. The famous
work of Benjamin Libet has attracted a great deal of attention in a
variety of fields, including philosophy. In a recent article, Libet
vividly asserts: "If the 'act now' process is initiated
unconsciously, then conscious freewill is not doing it". (3) This
connotes that certain electric changes occur in the brain before actions
that are done voluntarily, thereby making the initiation of such acts
unconscious processes. (4) In a laywo/man's language, this
discovery in neuroscience shows that decision-making is a biological
process which occurs before human beings are conscious of the urge,
intention or will to perform such an act. Thus, the issue of a human
being's freedom might be an illusion.
Determinism, however, implies the absence of freedom. This study
therefore examines the common themes found in the modern sciences
-Neuroscience--and Yoruba traditional religion--Ori. Incidentally, the
brain which features prominently in the findings of neuroscience on
human will is situated in the head, which is called Ori among the
Yoruba. It also explores the implications of some of the salient issues
being advanced in neuroscience. It argues that accepting the Yoruba idea
of Ori, literally, would constitute a pose to our understanding of human
freewill. Moreover, this research discusses how the advances in
neuroscience can be upheld, while recognizing the concept of Ori, and,
at the same time, logically sustaining some, if not all, of the
religious beliefs on human freewill, which anchors on responsibility,
reward and punishment.
Scientific positions are based on empirical facts which can be
verified. Thus, refuting them without any concrete reason for doing so
is a daunting task. However, there are serious implications for the
sustenance of the submission of neuroscience, which posits that freewill
might be an illusion in any civil society. Therefore, the Yoruba of
South-western Nigeria are not an exception. Besides, since the concept
of responsibility is central in any society, we cannot but find a way to
reconcile the position of science--neuroscience--with its obvious
implications, which this study intends to achieve. On the other hand,
traditional belief systems still form an integral part of the Nigerian
society despite the fact that civilization and foreign religions have
eroded some of the elements of indigenous culture. Hence, finding a
place for the concept of Ori in the "modern-day" Nigerian
society is quite challenging. This is a task this research intends to
achieve.
Ori and Ideas of Causality among the Yoniba
Ori is a very important component in the Yoruba understanding of
human personality. In other words, it is seen as a vital force that
guides human life. This further influences the usual Yoruba prayer for a
new bride as she leaves her father's house: Mo ri lo, ma mu ewa
lo--Depart with your Ori and not with just your beauty. Although there
are various philosophies that shape the way of life of the Yoruba, the
concept of pre-destination or causality cannot be undervalued. According
to Beir (1980), the Yoruba see their lives as partly dominated by fate
and predestination, and partly controlled by their own actions. Beir
further believes that "although a man is born with a fate and a
career in life, what he makes out of his fate depends on his
actions" (p.61). Thus, a wo/man picks the type of life s/he is
going to lead, even up to the period of her/his death, before s/he
enters into this world. This unchangeable part of a wo/man's
fortune is symbolized by her/his Ori, which literally denotes
'head', but in this context, signifies 'inner head'
or soul. (5) According to Awolalu (1979), Ori is a complex concept. It
is a physical head as well as that force that is responsible for
controlling one's being; however, to the Yoruba, Ori means head.
Literally, it is actually more than the physical head because it
represents the personal force that guides and also controls the
activities in the life of a person. The quality of Ori also determines
the success or failure of a life. (6)
Idowu (1982) makes a very comprehensive argument for determinism in
Yoruba thought, which is outstanding on the subject of discourse. Idowu
believes that it is the Ori that kneels down and makes a choice in the
process of 'taking' destiny. The fulfillment of destiny is
also done by the coming of Ori into the world. However, what makes the
individuality of each Ori is its quality. The destiny of a person is
known as Ipin-ori (iponri)--the portion of Ori or its lot--which is
usually abbreviated as 'Ipin'--portion. (7) The Yoruba believe
that the end for which a person is made is inextricably bound up with
her/his destiny since wo/man's deeds on earth have been predestined
by Olodumare (God in Yoruba belief). (8) Idowu makes arguments for
strong determinism here, which he supports with a few sayings:
A-kunle-yan ni 'adaye-ba
A-kunle a yan 'pin
A 'd' aiye tan oju n ro ni
Meaning,
That which is chose kneeling is that which is found on getting to the
world
We knelt down and chose a portion
We get to the world and are not pleased. (9)
Another saying to make a strong case for determinism is A-yan-mo
'o gbo 'ogun--That which is affixed to one cannot be rectified
by medicine. (10)
The concept of Ori among the Yoruba is closely related to what is
understood as destiny. There are different types of interpretation used
interchangeably to express destiny. Some connote the meaning of destiny
as understood by the Yoruba accurately, while some others are
misinterpretations. A line of understanding that runs through different
interpretations and misinterpretations of destiny is the belief that
there are certain factors that affect the quality of a wo/man's
life on earth. These factors are derivable from certain events that take
place prior to her/his present existence on earth. Dasylva (1998), while
attempting to address some of the misinterpretations of the term,
destiny, begins by establishing the difference between the Western view
of destiny and that of the Yoruba. He holds that many writers, including
Ola Rotimi, the writer of the famous tragic play, The gods are not to
Blame, situate the Yoruba view of destiny erroneously in the Western
context. The Western conception of destiny is synonymous with fate which
is not so among the Yoruba. (11) Dasylva posits further that the nearest
equivalent of destiny is Ayanmo--that which is chosen and sticks. The
difference between the Western and the Yoruba view of destiny is that
while the westerners believe that destiny is imposed by the gods on
wo/man in the pre-life and that wo/man was not a party to this choice,
the Yoruba believe that Ayanmo is the pre-life selection or choice
consciously made bowing in the presence of Olodumare, and which is being
confessed before Onibode (heaven gate-keeper) as a witness. (12)
Contrarily, Adetunji (2001) explains the clear distinction between
Ayanmo and Ori. She holds that destiny is Ori and not Ayanmo. Ori, she
holds, represents the configuration or structure of a person's
destiny. It is also a god. The contents of Ori are what Ayanmo entails,
and a person's Ayanmo is discovered in his/her destiny. Ayanmo also
plays the role of the creator. This belief is illustrated in the Yoruba
saying: "Ori lo ni se, eda la'Ayanmo)--Ori is the creator, the
human being is its fulfillment." (13)
Another terminology related to the concept of destiny is the word
Kadara which could also be interpreted as destiny. Kadara is a word
believed not to be originally Yoruba but having its roots in the Arabic
language. This belief system became infiltrated into Yoruba thought over
time, and now, it is believed to be an important concept in Yoruba
religion especially because of its close relationship with human
destiny. Olaleye (2014) holds a divergent view; he sees Kadara not
directly as the direct terminology for destiny but as a particular type
of destiny. He opines that Kadara is the part of destiny that cannot be
altered. Even though it may experience some delays, it cannot be
changed, except by Olodumare. This can be done through Ifa by the
offering of ebo-sacrifice- and etutu-rituals to Olodumare to make an
appeal for changes in a destiny. (14)
Ogo (glory) and Irawo (star) are two close terminologies that are
also related to the concept of destiny in Yoruba belief. This is a
belief system that is held in different religions apart from Yoruba
religion, including Christianity. This is very obvious in the case of
Jesus Christ in which three wise men saw his star in the east and could
deduce from the sight of the star the greatness of the destiny of the
newborn child. (15)
Similarly, in Yoruba religion, according to Olaleye, Ogo and Irawo
are the resources applied to gauge the success of a newborn later in
life. Ogo depicts the level of glory in the destiny of such a child,
while Irawo displays the brightness of a destiny. Olaleye, quoting from
the information received from babalawos, Ifa priests, states:
"these two: Ogo and Irawo are what people of the underworld--Aye;
or Aje--[also known as] witches usually work on when they want to tamper
with a person's destiny". (16) Quoting Idowu Arifalo, a
babalawo in Itapa Ekiti, Nigeria, Olaleye says further,
"Aje;-witches cannot and will not sit at a place to study or look
at any child's Ipin, Kadara or Ayanmo. Rather, they only look out
for the Ogo and Irawo of such a child; however, they can only see the
brightness of the Ogo and Irawo, not the Ogo and Irawo. The density of
the brightness shows how successful the newborn will be, later in life.
When the Aje-witches realise a very bright star, they will try at all
cost to block such Ogo and Irawo". (17) However, delay or blocking
of destiny can only be done for a limited time because of the belief in
the inalterability of a wo/man's destiny; they (the wicked people
of this world) can only defer destiny but cannot change it. (18)
There are several myths showing the relationship between Ori and a
person's destiny. One of them shows the concept of choice in human
destiny. The Yoruba believe that before coming to the world from heaven,
everyone must go and make a choice of Ori from a well-stocked store in
Ajala's house. Ajala is said to be the one appointed by Olodumare
to build or mould Ori. It is believed that the quality of Ori cannot be
determined by its physical appearance (whether size, shape, colour,
etc.). Ajala alone knows the good and bad ones. (19) In another popular
story of Ifa, told under Ogundameji by Ayo Salami, Oriseeku (the child
of Ogun), Orileemere (the child of Ifa) and Afuwape (the child of
Orunmila) were all coming to the earth. The story climaxed at how they
turned out when they arrived on the earth based on the choices of Ori
made in heaven. (20) There are a lot of badly mis-shaped heads of people
who turn out to be successful in life. However, there are other
well-shaped heads further having beautiful and handsome faces with no
success story. It is all about one's Ori. This validates the belief
in Ori and its relationship with human destiny.
One of the important lessons from these myths is that all Oris are
not the same since people make different choices of Ori. Subsequently,
their Ayanmo--contents of their destiny--will be different. This belief
system is seen as the Yoruba see Ori as an antidote to the problem of
evil in this world. It is believed that a wo/man's station in this
world is directly predicated on the type of choice s/he had made in
heaven. The belief in the importance of divination is also highly held.
A good destiny can be preserved if its contents are known, while the
other that is not desired can be rectified. The Yoruba idea of human
will is clearly laden with metaphysical ideas.
On a divergent note, some empirical findings on human will have
emerged from the field of neuroscience. It would be necessary at this
juncture to discuss them critically in order to juxtapose the scientific
views on human will with the metaphysical one held in Yoruba philosophy.
Neuroscience and Human Will
The recent discovery in neuroscience which challenges the notion of
freewill is not totally new but must have been influenced directly or
indirectly by philosophers, scientists or ancient scholars. Hodgson
(2009) revisits Pierre Laplace's eighteenth-century deterministic
argument with no allowance for free choices from Newton's law of
motion. (21) Hodgson traces the notion of determinism in scientific
studies further to the nineteenth century in the works of Charles
Darwin, where his famous theory of evolution provided insights on how
random mutations and selection make it appear to be responsible for
decision making, whereas, it is the brain that is in control of this
process. This position is similar to the recent position of neuroscience
which suggests that decision-making processes are controlled by the
brain, while humans are unconscious of these processes. Similar
positions are seen also in the works of Sigmund Freud and the British
philosopher Galen Strawson towards the end of the nineteenth century.
(22)
All these scientific notions have been strengthened in various ways
by recent studies in the field of neuroscience. According to Sachs
(2009), "the issue of freewill is an ancient debate, but we can now
approach it with breathtaking, scientific advances. Neuroscience has the
potential to provide one of the breakthroughs of our time... human
conscience are being opened up to dazzling scientific inquiry"
(Sachs 2009:7). (23) The notion that configurations of human behaviour
may be ultimately determined by other factors outside "conscious
control" has become quite popular and at the same time has also
rekindled interests in the hoary debate on freewill in recent decades.
These renewed interests are as a result of the developments in
behavioural and cognitive neurosciences. These developments indicate,
for example, that much of what we do takes place at an automatic and
unaware level and that the belief that our voluntary actions emerge from
conscious intentions and volitions is mistaken. (24)
The pungent position of the famous work of Benjamin Libet is that
our brains decide or prepare to initiate actions long before a reported
subjective awareness of such a decision occurs. (25) Libet's
conclusion further implies that cerebral processes precede conscious
intentions, meaning that a specific electrical change in the brain (the
"readiness potential" RP) occurs before voluntary acts and
that it begins 550ms before such act. Human subjects are aware of
intention to act 340-400ms after RP starts. Thus, the volitional process
is initiated outside of consciousness, that is, unconsciously. (26)
Thus, the issue of wo/man's will as being free might not be totally
true as previously believed. The submission of Libet is that the
initiation of voluntary action is unconscious, and if an act is
initiated unconsciously, then freewill is not doing it. This experiment
shows that there is a gap between the time the brain initiates an action
and the time humans are aware of the urge, intention or will to perform
that same act, and this time gap is called Readiness Potential (RP).
Mele (2011), a contemporary philosopher, also discusses the work of
Libet and sees his position as an argument for skepticism about
freewill. He summarizes the position of Libet that intentions that are
conscious (and their physical correlates) do not contribute to the
production of corresponding overt actions.
He also discusses the experiment of Libet and his findings
extensively by using less scientific terms in the narration of these
experiments. These are experiments in which subjects are instructed to
flex their wrists at any time they wish to while also reporting the
particular time of the urge, will or decision to do so. (27)
Another contemporary philosopher, Harris, makes a rather witty
account of the determinism in neuroscience; his position is nonetheless
valid and one that a non-philosopher or a person without any inclination
of science can readily relate to. According to him,
We are conscious of only a tiny fraction of the information that our
brains process in each moment. Although we continually notice changes
in our experience- in thoughts, mood, perception, behavior and so, we
are utterly unaware of the neurophysiological events that produce them.
In fact, we can be very poor witnesses to experience itself. By merely
glancing at your face or listening to your tone of voice, others are
often more aware of your state of mind and motivations than you are.
(28) (S. Harris, 2012, p.7)
According to Caruso (2012), the common sense belief in conscious
freewill is in fact contradicted by empirical evidence. The strong and
pervasive belief in freewill, which Caruso considers an illusion, can be
found in a detailed examination of human phenomenology and a proper
theoretical understanding of consciousness. (29) The issue of
"empirical evidence" is the greatest threat neuroscience poses
to our existing understanding of freewill. If the position of
neuroscience can be accounted for empirically, then it challenges other
positions, religious or cultural, though popular, as they are
speculative and not in any way testable or verifiable. This is the
dilemma that forms the basis of this study.
The freewill problem premised on the position of neuroscience
revolves around the issue of 'self-awareness of causes of
actions': are we actually aware of the causes of our actions? Or
are we actually conscious of processes that initiated what we call
voluntary behaviour? The position of neuroscience calls to question what
we have believed about wo/man and her/his autonomy in the
decision-making process. 'Initiation' and 'control'
are the two important elements in human will which are now debated.
Implications of Determinism: Ori, and the Findings of Neuroscience
In spite of all these empirically verified truths, there are some
serious implications for the sustenance of this discovery in the field
of neuroscience on human freewill. These include the religious and
cultural implications especially among the Yoruba. The other challenge
is how to reconcile this truth, the position of neuroscience, with these
implications.
The freewill problem is premised on the position of neuroscience
which revolves around the issue of 'self-awareness of causes of
actions'. Are we actually aware of the causes of our actions? Or
are we actually conscious of processes that initiated what we call
voluntary behavior? If indeed we are not free, as neuroscience or Ori
seems to suggest, then our actions are beyond our control. Who takes
responsibility for our actions if indeed they are beyond our control? In
the light of these germane questions, we cannot discard the proven
discovery of science because of our speculative but established beliefs
influenced by our religious, cultural or ethical ideas. According to
every Yoruba, these beliefs are not just mere assumptions; they are
stern beliefs taken very seriously which shape the behaviours of the
Yoruba people. Is it possible then to accept the conclusion of
neuroscience which threatens freewill and jeopardizes the so-called
assumptions of the Yoruba on human personality? This is an important
question that has grave implications on both the personal and the
communal level. It is therefore necessary to note that the Yoruba have a
unique idea of human personality. This is considerably geared towards
the understanding of the implications of a scientific finding on human
will.
A human being, according to Yoruba belief system, is not just a
mere physical being whose existence is dictated alone by physical
factors present in this world. According to Adebola Akintola (1999), at
the stage of divine creation of humanity, there was a free intercourse
between God and the divinities, which predicated the creation of wo/man
in heaven and her/his subsequent establishment on earth. (30) It is
necessary to note also that religion has a strong influence on the
entire life of a Yoruba person; therefore, the Yoruba conception of
humanity is religious-driven. (31) The unique concept of human
personality held by the Yoruba is influenced by certain beliefs, namely:
the belief in the physical and non-physical nature of a human being;
wo/man's preparation in heaven before coming to the earth; the
roles of God's powerful agents in the world; the concepts of Ori,
Enikeji, wo/man's guardian angel or double; death and immortality
of the soul of wo/man.
Reconciling Ori and Neuroscience with Contemporary Ideas on Human
Will
In spite of the evidences against freewill from the findings of
neuroscience, some scholars are skeptical of the position that freewill
is an illusion. Walter Glannon (2015) challenges the belief that humans
lack freewill by holding that findings of neuroscience in the past few
decades have driven a departure in the external factors on freewill such
as natural laws or events to internal factors related to the brain and
the mind. (32) Glannon gives a devastating analysis of the findings of
neuroscience regardless of the enormous empirical evidences used to
prove that freewill is an illusion. According to him, sufficient
evidence emerges from neuroscience to allow a conclusion that there is a
deterministic relationship between neural processes and mental processes
connected to behaviour. However, as a result of limitations in
functional neuroimaging and other similar neurophysiological procedures
of brain activity, neuroscience at best can show correlations between
brain activity and the mental activity involved in the decision-making
process and action.
Correlation is different from causation, and accordingly, there is
no warranty for the belief that neural processes are responsible for
particular mental states and choices to act in particular manners. (33)
Similarly, the Yoruba believe that even though Ori plays a critical role
in a person's life, there is a guarantee that certain factors
outside of Ori affect his or her actions and his or her outcomes in
life.
It is necessary to note also that the Yoruba believe that a
person's destiny can be changed because of the Yoruba saying in the
form of a prayer--Kaye ma pa Kadara mi da--May the wicked people of this
world not alter my destiny. This prayer suggests that the Yoruba believe
that it is possible for a person's destiny to be changed.
Regardless of the enormous and convincing argument against freewill,
Julian Baggini (2015) raises a pertinent question, thus: So is the game
really up for freewill? She answers: "it is true that commonsense
notion of freewill is not fit for the purpose. It rests on a naive and
simplistic assumption that we can rise above our biology and our history
to make choices in a condition of unconstrained freedom. The challenges
to freewill need to be met not by rejecting them wholesale, but by
thinking more carefully about what it really means to be free, rather
than what we assume it to mean" (p.3). (34) Baumister (2010) says
assertively, "I do not think it (neuroscience) will be able to show
that there is no such thing as consciousness, and thus, no freewill;
either it will explain consciousness or we would conclude that we have
not yet explained it while it may make the notion of a unitary enduring
self seems illusory; our concept of freedom does not depend upon the
truth of that notion" (p.168). (35) Baumister's position is
obvious; he believes that the best neuroscience can do is to explain the
processes of consciousness.
Sally and Lilienfield share the opinion of Glannon about the
limitations in neuroimaging and other barring processes used as the
bases of conclusion that freewill does not exist. (36) They ask:
"consider the law, when a person commits a crime, who is at fault,
the perpetrator or his/her brain?" (37) Similarly, Nicole Vincent
opines that freewill or its absence is not a criterion for criminal
responsibility or non-responsibility. This is because it is not relevant
to the real practice of criminal law when the locution used for it is
simply a confused proxy for the conclusion that some genuine culpability
doctrine was or was not present. Sometimes, it is meant that freewill is
an important primary justification for responsibility, regardless of if
it is not even a criterion in any legal system. (38) On a similar note,
no attorney will make a case for his client on the defense of Ori,
"that it was his Ori that made him do it". It can be inferred
that what Vincent means is that in the "real world" outside of
the academic definition of freewill, whether a person has it or does not
have it, as some schools of thoughts in neuroscience suggest, does not
really matter. This is because Vincent believes it is immaterial in the
real exercise of criminal law. This is also because freewill is assumed
to be present or the affirmation of freewill is a crucial criterion in
any legal doctrine because it is a primary justification for
responsibility.
The brain is not an inflexible determined mechanism, but a process
that is more flexible and changeable than we had for decades thought. It
is not a central computer directing the human machinery with a fixed,
deterministic logic, but an organism of great plasticity that actively
interferes in coincidences and necessity. (39)
Thomas Nagel believes there are at least two ways in which freewill
is important, and these are interrelated. The first is our autonomy,
which shows that we are not just mere observers of the activities of our
lives; we are the ones that fashion out their course. The second is
accountability, which is an issue closely related to responsibility.
(40) If freewill is an illusion as some scholars, such as Sam Harris
(2012) (41), D. Wegner (2002) (42), Heidi Ravven (2013) (43) and P.
Smith (2014) (44) to name a few, have argued, then we truly lack
autonomy; we only observe activities of our lives, and there is no need
for responsibility. This kind of thinking is at odds with everyday
living, and neither is it easily acceptable nor practicable.
Adetunji (2001) also examines the concept of Ori from a
soft-deterministic approach; she discusses it within the precincts of
morality which is the major problem for hard determinism. According to
her, a person's Ori can be altered by societal influences, such as
western education, foreign religions, western culture, western medical
care and changes in economic system. Intrinsic values, such as good
character, offering of sacrifices, hard work and ability to struggle,
are free actions of an individual that can affect a person's life.
She further posits that the Yoruba strongly believe in human destiny
because success or failure of any man largely depends on the type of
choice he has made in heaven; though human efforts cannot be ruled out
of success or failure, the greater part of it can be ascribed to
destiny. (45)
Under Dehaene's (2001) analysis, "a physical system whose
successive states unfold according to a deterministic rule can still be
described as having freewill, if it is able to represent a goal and
estimate the outcomes of its action before initiating them". (46)
The distinctiveness of Dehaene's argument rests on his thinking
that highlights the seriousness of the human decision-making process. He
believes that this process includes the setting of goals and the
selection of a course of action in the midst of various alternatives,
while weighing the consequences of each decision and possible outcomes.
A wo/man's decision to resign from her/his job to join, for
example, politics, for further studies or for full-time ministry is a
kind of serious decision that involves human freewill. This kind of a
decision is not made in a split of a second, and such a wo/man cannot
present her/his defense as follows: 'It is my brain that made me do
it', for one might wonder how responsible this kind of a statement
is; nonetheless, this is what it means if freewill is truly an illusion.
However, Penderins (2013) opines that it is a fact that the courts
of nearly all the world's judicial systems allow mitigating
circumstances to be considered before verdict is passed. This is our way
of conceding that humans have, at least under certain circumstances, no
freewill and could not always be held responsible for their actions.
(47) Some of such mitigating circumstances could be in cases of
insanity, when there is no freewill. Penderins says further that it is
especially the gatekeepers of the religious fraternity who are
vehemently against the notion of no freewill. Being able to exercise
freewill is seen as the basis of human morality. The belief that humans
are free to decide whether they want to land up in heaven or hell one
day is the foundation of mainstream religious movements. (48)
On a religious note, Dasylva (1998) believes that a person's
destiny can also be changed under certain circumstances. These
conditions are not self-choice, but induced by certain forces or
actions. It may take the form of a curse (egun idile) imposed on an
individual or a lineage because of a social misdemeanor, such as
breaking of a taboo or because of a sheer vendetta. Or it may take the
form of Ire-blessing, consequent upon some good deeds performed by an
individual and enjoyed by his lineage. The curse-Eegun or Ire -blessing
is usually invoked by the power of the spoken words, which in turn
activates cosmic forces to carry out the decreed assignment, regardless
of its rightness or wrongness. (49) It is then obvious that the Yoruba
believe in what could be termed a "two-sided conception of
destiny" using the words of Olusegun Oladipo (1992). (50) The
Yoruba believe destiny is something given and unalterable and something
which in certain circumstances and under certain conditions like the
scenarios cited above can be altered. This two-sided conception of the
Yoruba on human destiny suggests a problem and indicates determinism or
fatalism.
According to Idowu (1982), given certain conditions, a
person's destiny can be altered: by the aid of Orunmila, a
'happy' destiny can be preserved and an 'unhappy'
one rectified through rituals. The destiny of a person can be altered
and made worse by omo araye--'children of the world': these
are persons in whom the evil powers of the world are vested. A
person's character can also alter his/her destiny for worse or
better, since a good destiny coupled with a bad character is of no
worth. An 'unhappy' destiny can be rectified if it can be
ascertained. This rite is called Iko'-se-waye or Esen-t aye. Its
main purpose is to find out what sort of child it is and things to be
done to preserve his/her good destiny or rectify an unhappy one. This is
done in the case of a newborn child. The destiny of a person can also be
made worse by the machinations of the person's Enikeji-"double
or counterpart" which has a strong influence on his/her destiny.
(51) Three of these ways--the first, the third and the fourth--show the
influence of the actions or inactions of a person on his destiny.
The fate of a person, therefore, is not totally determined by
factors beyond his/her control or cerebral activities of his/her
brain--the course of his/her life can also be affected by his/her own
actions. Olaleye (2013) shares some of these views of Idowu to show that
the course of a person's life can be improved by his personal
actions through sacrifice. According to Olaleye (2013), Ebo (sacrifice)
is necessary to ensure that predictions of good fortune will come
through and bad ones averted. It is offered to change bad and unpleasant
situations to a better one, to retain, maintain and improve good
situations. (52)
Hylomorphism as a Solution to the Dilemma of Determinism
Hylomorphism is a philosophical theory used to solve the
metaphysical problem of the nature of the existence of human beings. It
is from the Greek words hyle, "matter"; morphe,
"form". This theory is often traced to Aristotle because he
left a lasting legacy on the ontology of wo/man which is still relevant
in contemporary discourses.
This is why Merriam Webster Dictionary defines it as a theory that
corporeal being consists of Aristotelian forms and primordial matter.
(53) Similarly, the Catholic Dictionary defines hylomorphism as the
theory that all physical beings consist of two basic forms: the prime
matter, which is an undefined primitive, and a substantial form, which
is a definite mode of existence. (54) In the Yoruba philosophy, Bolaji
Idowu has written extensively on the subject which is in accordance with
the Aristotelian school of thought, showing the dual nature of wo/man.
To the question, 'what is wo/man?', Idowu (1996) responds
succinctly that the Yoruba will answer offhandedly that wo/man is body
plus emi (spirit). The body is the material concrete entity of flesh and
bones which can be perceived or known by the five senses. Emi, on the
other hand, is invisible and intangible; it is that which gives life to
the whole body. While the body can be created and is created by a
divinity, it is Olodumare alone who puts emi into wo/man, thus giving
her/him life and being. (55)
The Yoruba, like many other races in the world, believe that
wo/man's nature is partly material and partly immaterial. They
believe that wo/man has a material body by means of which s/he acts and
reacts to her/his physical environment. They also believe that s/he has
an immaterial entity. (56) This belief that wo/man is not only a
biological phenomenon but also a spiritual phenomenon whose sojourn on
earth being a continuation of what began in heaven is only possible if a
human being has two natures, one physical and the other non-physical.
Every part of the human body is important to the Yoruba, not only in the
biological sense, but most importantly in the spiritual sense. Organs
like the eyes, the hands or feet are understood metaphysically. Thus,
the Yoruba will take a lot of offence if an object is passed or received
through the left hand. Also, when a person steps out to embark on a
journey or any important venture and the left foot steps out first it
has a spiritual significance on which the success of the venture or
journey rests. Ese-feet are very important to the Yoruba, and the shape
of the foot, as well as how it rests on the ground, is taken seriously.
Every part of the human body is important to the Yoruba both in the
material and spiritual sense, because, to them, a wo/man is seen as
having both physical and non-physical natures.
Conclusion
The Concept of Ori is not just a mere physical organ but a body
part that has both physical and spiritual meanings. A significant point
is obvious from the hylomorphic theory of Idowu. Here, he argues that
among the Yoruba, the physical part of wo/man is recognised and
acknowledged, but it is just a part of the whole package. Thus, the
Yoruba understanding of wo/man tilts more towards the metaphysical part
than the physical. The Yoruba believe that a person is not just what we
see. This is expressed when a person has just died and all the physical
parts of the person are still intact. Such a body is lifeless, and it
shows that the major controlling force of the person is not physical.
Lack of freewill is simply inconvenient within any practical milieu
because once the case of insanity is ruled out, human beings take
responsibility for their actions in the real world.
The concept of Ori or the submission of neuroscience on human will
can only fit into practical realities by conceding to soft determinism
and hylomorphism. Soft determinism is the belief that humans are not
free, given certain conditions. At the same time, since human beings
have to take responsibility for their actions, they should also be
considered free. This gives room for both neuroscience and Ori because
sometimes humans do not have control over their wills even though they
take responsibility for their actions. Hylomorphism also shows that
humans have both the physical and also the spiritual nature that cannot
be subjected or explained by empirical experiments. It is important to
note that there is a limit to what science can know or does; some
knowledge just simply defys scientific or empirical understanding.
Scientists should know that metaphysical answers to issues can come in
courtesy of religion. This means an understanding of human will cannot
be limited to scientific knowledge. Religious scholars on the other hand
should be more open to other ideas outside of their domain. It is
therefore necessary to form a mutually benefiting framework between
these two important fields of study. According to Albeit Einstein,
"Science without religion is lame and religion without science is
blind". (57) In the past it was believed that religion and science
are two parallel lines that cannot meet. Recent studies in works of
scholars like H. Noris, 199 3 (58), J. Peacock, 1999 (59), J. Goddard,
2012 (60), M. Thompson, 2013 (61), J. Goddard, 2012 (62), B. Sweetman,
2010 (63), I. Barbour, 1990 (64) and other scholars with similar thought
have disproved this belief. These scholars are finding a meeting point
between these two fields. A symbiotic relationship between them is
possible, and future studies should focus on how both fields tend to
profit from a mutually benefiting framework, especially in the context
of indigenous religions.
End Notes
(1) K. Abimbola. 2006. Yoruba Culture: A Philosophical Account.
Great Britain: Lap Publishers. 72-73.
(2) K. Wiredu. 2004. A Companion to African Philosophy. U.S.A:
Blackwell Publishing Ltd. 321.
(3) "Freewill and Neuroscience". Retrieved from
http://www.centenary.edu/attachments/philosophy/aizawa/courses/neuroscience/mele2006.pdf. Accessed 23rd April, 2018.
(4) B. Libet. 2014. "Do we have Freewill?" Journal of
Consciousness Studies. Retrieved from
http://www.ingentaconnect.com/contentone/imp/jcs/1999/00000006/F0020008/966. Accessed 23rd April, 2018.
(5) U. Beir. (ed). 1980. Yoruba Myths. Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press. 61.
(6) J. Awolalu. 1979. Yoruba Beliefs and Sacrificial Rites. Essex:
Longman. 9.
(7) B. Idowu. 1982. Olodumare: God in Yoruba Belief. 3rd Imp.
Lagos: Longman Nigeria Ltd. 170-172.
(8) B. Idowu. 1982. 173-175.
(9) B. Idowu. 1982. 175.
(10) B. Idowu. 1982. 175.
(11) A. Dasylva. 1998. "Kadara- Ayanmo: The Yoruba Concept of
Fate-Destiny". Orita: Ibadan Journal of Religious Studies. Ibadan:
Department of Religious Studies, University of Ibadan. XXX/1-2. 4.
(12) A. Dasylva. 1998.
(13) H. Adetunji. 2001. "Ori and Moral Responsibility in
Yoruba Belief". Ph.D. Thesis. Department of Religious Studies.
University of Ibadan. 73.
(14) S. Olaleye. 2014. "Akosejaye: Trend and Status in Yoruba
Communities of South-western Nigeria". Ilorin Journal of Religious
Studies, (IJOURELS), 4: 1.89.
(15) Matthew 2:1
(16) S. Olaleye. 2014.
(17) S. Olaleye. 2014.
(18) S. Olaleye. 2014. 89-90.
(19) S. Abogunrin. 1972. "Man in Yoruba Thought". B.A.
Project, Department of Religious Studies, University of Ibadan. 38.
(20) A. Salami. 2008. Yoruba Theology & Tradition: The Man and
the Society. Lagos: NIDD Limited. 31-33.
(21) D. Hodgson. 2009. "Criminal Responsibility, Freewill and
Neuroscience". M. Nancey et al (eds.) Downward Causation and the
Neurobiology of Freewill. Germany: Springer. 231-232.
(22) D. Hodgson. 2009. 231-232.
(23) J. Sachs. 2009. Neurosciences and Freewill. R. Pollack (ed.)
New York: Columbia University Press. 7.
(24) G. Caruso. 2012. Freewill and Consciousness: A Determinist
Account of the Illusion of Freewill. Plymouth: Lexington Books. 1-2.
(25) "Freewill and Neuroscience". Retrieved from
http://www.centenary.edu/attachments/philosophy/aizawa/courses/neuroscience/mele2006.pdf. Accessed 23rd April, 2018.
(26) B. Libet. 2014. "Do We have Freewill?" Journal of
Consciousness Studies. Retrieved from
http://www.ingentaconnect.com/contentone/imp/jcs/1999/00000006/F0020008/966. Accessed 23rd April, 2018.
(27) A. Mele. 2011. "Freewill and Science". The Oxford
Handbook of Freewill. 2nd Edition. Kane R. (ed.) 499-501.
(28) S. Harris. 2012. Freewill. New York: Simon & Schuster. 7.
(29) G. Caruso. 2012..
(30) A. Akintola. 1999. Yoruba Ethics and Metaphysics. Ogbomoso:
Valour Publishing Ventures Limited. 53.
(31) J. Lucas. 1948. The Religion of the Yorubas. Lagos: C.M.S
Bookshop. 245.
(32) W. Glannon. 2015. Freewill and the Brain: Neuroscientific,
Philosophical and Legal Perspectives. Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press. 58.
(33) W. Glannon. 2015. 6.
(34) J. Baggini. 2015. Freedom Regained: The Possibility of
Freewill. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. 3.
(35) R. Baumister, A. Mele and K. Vohs. 2010. Freewill and
Consciousness: How Might they Work? Oxford: Oxford University Press.
168.
(36) S. Satel and S. Lilienfield. 2013. Brain Wasted: The Seductive
Appeal of Mindless Neuroscience. New York: Basic Books. Xii-Xv.
(37) S. Satel and S. Lilienfield. 2013. Xii-Xv.
(38) N. Vincent. 2013. Neuroscience and Legal Responsibility.
Oxford: Oxford University Press. 38.
(39) J. De Vos (ed.) 2016. Neuroscience and Critique: Exploring the
Limits of the Neurological Turn. New York: Routledge. 16.
(40) G. Watson (ed.) 2003. Oxford Readings in Philosophy: Freewill.
Oxford: Oxford University Press. 1.
(41) S. Harris. 2012. Free Will, New York: Simon & Schuster.
5-8
(42) D. Wegner. 2002. The Illusion of Consciousness. Cambridge:
Bradford Books. 1-2
(43) H. Ravven. 2013 The Self Beyond itself: An Alternative History
of Ethics, the New Brain Sciences and the Myth of Free will. New York:
The New Press. (Np: Ebook)
(44) P. Smit. 2014. Enlightenment for Lazy People. Retrieved 24th
November, 2015 from http://www.paulsmit.nu
(45) H. Adetunji. 2001. "Ori and Moral Responsibility in
Yoruba Belief". Ph. D Thesis. Dept. of Religious Studies.
University of Ibadan. Xiv+215pp.
(46) S. Dehaene. 2001. The Cognitive Neuroscience of Consciousness.
Cambridge: MIT Press. 29-30.
(47) A. Penderins. 2013. The Carpet Mind: The Laws of Thinking
Defined. Bloomington: Author House. 44.
(48) A. Penderins. 45.
(49) A. Dasylva. 1998. 5
(50) O. Oladipo. 1992. "Predestination in Yoruba Thought: A
Philosopher's Interpretation". Orita: Ibadan Journal of
Religious Studies. Ibadan: Department of Religious Studies, University
of Ibadan. XXIV/1-2: 36.
(51) B. Idowu. 1982. 175-182.
(52) S. Olaleye. 2013. Ebo as a Healing Technique in Ifa Divination
System. Deutschland: Lambert. 35-36.
(53) Retrieved from
https://www.merriam-webster.com/dictionary/hylomorphism. Accessed 10th
February, 2016.
(54) Retrieved from
https://www.catholicculture.org/culture/library/dictionary/index.cfm?id=34027. Accessed 10th February, 2016.
(55) E. Idowu. 1996. 179.
(56) J. Lucas. 1948. The Religion of the Yorubas. Lagos: C.M.S
Bookshop. 245.
(57) Albert Einstein. 1941. Science, Religion and Philosophy: a
Symposium.
(58) H. Noris. 1993. Cosmology: Historical, Literary,
Philosophical, Religious and Scientific Perspectives. New York: Garland
Publications Inc.
(59) J. Peacock. 1999. Cosmological Physics. Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press.
(60) J. Goddard. 2012. Faith Vs Science: The Unnecessary Dichotomy
(ebook). Retrieved 15th January, 2016 from
www.firsteditiondesignpublishing.com
(61) M. Thompson. 2013. Religion and science. Np: Hodder Education
(ebook)
(62) J. Goddard. 2012
(63) B. Sweetman. 2010. Religion and Science: An Introduction. New
York: Continuum International Publishing Group, Ltd.
(64) I. Barbour. 1990. Religion in an Age of Science. San
Francisco: Harper San Francisco (ebook).
by Gbadamosi, Oluwatoyin Adebola, Ph.D.
tygbadamosi@gmail.com
Department of Religious Studies
University of Ibadan, Ibadan, Nigeria
COPYRIGHT 2018 Journal of Pan African Studies
No portion of this article can be reproduced without the express written permission from the copyright holder.
Copyright 2018 Gale, Cengage Learning. All rights reserved.