首页    期刊浏览 2025年06月18日 星期三
登录注册

文章基本信息

  • 标题:The Environmental Genome Project: Ethical, Legal, and Social Implications
  • 作者:Richard R. Sharp
  • 期刊名称:Environmental Health Perspectives
  • 印刷版ISSN:0091-6765
  • 电子版ISSN:1552-9924
  • 出版年度:2000
  • 卷号:April 2000
  • 出版社:OCR Subscription Services Inc

The Environmental Genome Project: Ethical, Legal, and Social Implications

Richard R. Sharp

The National Institute of Environmental Health Sciences is supporting a multiyear research initiative examining genetic influences on environmental response. Proponents of this new initiative, known as the Environmental Genome Project, hope that the information learned will improve our understanding of environmentally associated diseases and allow clinicians and public health officials to target disease-prevention strategies to those who are at in creased risk. Despite these potential benefits, the project presents several ethical and social challenges. Of immediate concern is the protection of individual research participants. Other ethical issues relate to the application of research results and how study findings could affect social priorities. Clarifying these emerging areas of concern, many of which have not received adequate attention in the existing bioethics literature, is an important step toward minimizing potential research-related risks and defining research needs. Key words: Environmental Genome Project, environmental genomics, ethics, genetic susceptibility, human subjects research, informed consent. Environ Health Perspect 108:279-281 (2000). [Online 14 February 2000]

http://ehpnet1.niehs.nih.gov/docs/2000/108p279-281sharp/abstract.html

The National Institute of Environmental Health Sciences recently launched a new research initiative known as the Environmental Genome Project (EGP) (1-3). The EGP will examine how genetic variation affects response to environmental exposures. Initially, the project will identify polymorphic variation in genes that appear to play an important role in environmentally associated diseases. Having identified these genetic polymorphisms, researchers then will examine their functional implications more carefully (4). These functional studies will be multidisciplinary in approach, incorporating research methodologies from biochemistry, epidemiology, genetics, pharmacology, and toxicology (5).

Proponents of the EGP hope that the information learned will be instrumental in improving public health (6). A better understanding of genetic influences on environmental response could lead to more accurate estimates of disease risks and provide a basis for disease prevention and early intervention programs directed at individuals and populations at increased risk (7). Identifying functionally significant polymorphisms also could shed light on disease pathways and suggest targets for therapeutic intervention (8,9).

As with all research, these potential benefits must be weighed against possible risks. Following the precedent developed in connection with the Human Genome Project (10,11), there are plans to support research on the ethical, legal, and social implications of the EGP (12). By examining these issues, we may be able to anticipate problems before they arise and develop policies that maximize the benefits of the EGP while minimizing its risks (13).

In this paper we highlight several ethical, legal, and social issues raised by the EGP. These issues are presented in the order that they likely will present themselves to researchers, beginning with the protection of research participants and concluding with potential long-term implications of environmental genomic research. Our goal in providing this overview is to draw attention to future research needs and encourage others to join us in thinking about these difficult and complex issues.

Current Issues: Protecting Research Participants

The most immediate ethical, legal, and social issues raised by the EGP relate to the protection of individual research participants (14-16). Genetic studies often present special challenges in protecting human subjects because genetic research frequently poses psychosocial risks that may be difficult to anticipate and convey to prospective participants (17). These risks can include possible discrimination or stigmatization, disrupted relationships between family members, and adverse effects on a participant's self-image (18).

The presentation of research-related risks to participants is especially troublesome in connection with the EGP because of the many uncertainties surrounding the study of genetic hypersensitivities to environmental exposures. Studies of gene-environment interactions often do not allow for precise quantification of the respective genetic and environmental contributions to disease (19). As a result, research findings may be difficult for researchers and participants to interpret. A study may identify a genetic polymorphism that appears to play a role in environmental response, but the extent to which its effects are mediated by environmental factors often will remain unclear. Without more information on an individual's genome and past environmental exposures, the detection of such a polymorphism is of uncertain value in predicting future disease. These uncertainties complicate the process of informed consent, particularly the communication of potential risks and benefits to prospective participants (20). The inability to quantify the precise extent to which a particular polymorphism increases disease risks also makes it difficult to determine whether research results should be disclosed to participants, and if so, in what manner (21).

If study results are conveyed to participants, still other complications present themselves (22). In many genetic studies, specially trained genetic counselors discuss findings with participants. This approach helps minimize potential psychosocial risks. Although genetic counselors could be used to convey results obtained in connection with the EGP, the current shortage of these professionals likely would make this a practical impossibility. Moreover, if many laypersons overestimate the predictive value of genetic information (23), it may be difficult to present findings on genetic hypersensitivities to environmental exposures in a manner that avoids placing too much emphasis on genetic contributions to disease. It is more likely that information on increased susceptibility to environmentally associated diseases will be viewed fatalistically, prompting some to infer that because they have a genetic predisposition to a disease, they will eventually develop that condition. Such misunderstandings are a concern in presenting study results to individual participants, as well as in presenting research findings more generally.

Other immediate ethical, legal, and social issues relate to the breadth of the consent obtained in connection with EGP studies (24). Associations between individual alleles and particular environmental exposures are difficult to identify. As a result, researchers are interested in designing studies that look at possible associations between many different allelic variants and many different exposures concurrently. Although such studies increase the likelihood of identifying functionally significant polymorphisms, they complicate the consent process. As more genes and exposures are considered simultaneously, it becomes increasingly difficult to anticipate the potential risks and benefits of the research (25,26). Hence, it also becomes more difficult to ensure that individual participants are fully informed about the possible risks and benefits of their participation. At the extreme, the worry is that individual consent becomes a blanket permission for genetic research in general (27). These broad permissions are considered morally problematic because it is unclear how participants could be fully informed about such a wide range of potential research uses (28).

A related concern is that current policies governing informed consent could place inappropriate restrictions on research in environmental genomics (29). Although the present standards for informed consent in genetic research may be appropriate for studies of highly predictive alleles, they may be overly demanding for studies of genetic hypersensitivities to environmental exposures, particularly because such studies generally present more limited risks to individual participants. Thus the challenge facing the EGP is to establish consent procedures that allow individuals to make genuinely informed choices about their participation in studies that examine many different alleles and multiple exposures concurrently. The permissions granted by participants should be broad enough to permit diverse research interests, yet specific enough to allow individual participants to assess the possible risks and benefits of their participation.

Emerging Issues: Protecting Socially Identifiable Groups

Many of the ethical, legal, and social issues surrounding the EGP are familiar to experienced researchers and Institutional Review Boards. Although the EGP complicates these familiar areas of concern, studies of genetic influences on environmental response also introduce other less familiar ethical and social considerations. These concerns will become more prominent as research in environmental genomics expands and information on common genetic hypersensitivities becomes more widely available.

One such issue is the protection of socially identifiable groups, including racial and ethnic populations. Some allelic variants are more common in certain populations and less common in others. As specific genetic polymorphisms are associated with increased susceptibility to environmental exposures, it is likely that some genetic hypersensitivities will be associated with particular social groups (30). The association of genetic hypersensitivities with race or ethnicity could threaten the employment and insurance opportunities available to entire groups of individuals, not just those who choose to participate in research (31,32). Members of these populations also could encounter broader forms of discrimination and stigmatization, for example, in child custody disputes or adoption efforts (33,34). In this regard, the association of Ashkenazi Jews with BRCA1 mutations (and increased risk of breast cancer) is suggestive of the type of risks presented by studies of genetic influences on environmental response (35,36).

In response to these research-related risks, some have proposed that members of study populations be involved directly in the review of proposed research (37,38). Involving community representatives early in the design of research protocols could help identify potential risks that otherwise could go unnoticed (39). This approach has been controversial and the effectiveness of these supplemental protections has been questioned (40,41). Additional discussion and empirical research are needed to determine how best to incorporate the perspectives of study populations in the review of genetic research (42).

Long-Term Issues: Shifting Social Priorities and Responsibility for Health

Although it is difficult to speculate on the long-term consequences of any area of research, there are a number of broad social considerations suggested by the EGP. One such concern is that research on genetic influences on environmental response could affect how we view an individual's responsibility for his or her overall health. It seems reasonable to suggest that individuals with known genetic hypersensitivities to particular exposures are responsible for avoiding those adverse exposures. Individuals who know that they are particularly susceptible to the toxins found in cigarette smoke, for example, should quit smoking. What is less clear, however, is how far this moral obligation extends.

For instance, suppose an individual has a known hypersensitivity to an environmental exposure that is very common and difficult to avoid--exposure to low levels of direct sunlight, for example. An individual may be able to avoid such adverse exposures, but only by taking extraordinary measures. Although preventive interventions are available, it is unclear how we should view those individuals who fail to take such extraordinary measures to lower their risk of disease. Insurers, for example, may claim that individuals who do not minimize their exposure to these agents are responsible for any subsequent illness because they knowingly placed themselves at risk. Employers asked to pay for health costs through workers' compensation may refuse based on the idea that it was the individual who knowingly took a job that placed him or her at increased risk. In contrast, individuals with heightened genetic sensitivities may seek protection under the Americans with Disabilities Act or state legislation protecting against genetic discrimination (43). Currently, it is unclear how to resolve such disputes or the extent to which information on genetic hypersensitivities might be inappropriately used to avoid responsibility for illness. In part, these disputes concern possible discriminatory uses of genetic information, but the more fundamental issue is how information on genetic risks will alter our views on personal responsibility for one's health (12).

Other examples suggest further complications to the notion of personal responsibility. Suppose gene-modification techniques become more effective than they are at present. When certain genetic polymorphisms help protect against adverse exposures, individuals may wish to alter their genetic makeup to increase their tolerance to these exposures. Given the scarcity of medical resources, such applications of gene-manipulation techniques are unlikely to become commonplace. However, because these genetic enhancements could be purchased by wealthy individuals, their availability would contribute to existing health disparities between the rich and the poor. Genetically enhanced millionaires could live recklessly, engaging in unhealthy behaviors, whereas the poor would be held to a higher standard of accountability for their health.

Related to these considerations regarding medical responsibility are concerns about the effect the EGP and projects like it may have on how we view at-risk, but currently asymptomatic, individuals. As with other known genetic susceptibilities to disease, some individuals who are at increased risk of developing environmentally associated diseases will view themselves, and will be viewed by others, as ill--even though they may not be exhibiting any symptoms of the disease and may never develop the illness in question (44). If associations between particular polymorphisms and specific diseases prove difficult to quantify, the EGP could foster such fatalistic attitudes by making it difficult to specify the precise extent to which an individual is at increased risk.

Other long-term considerations relate to increased emphasis on the genetic causes of disease. This trend, which has been described as the geneticization of disease (45), could foster the belief that social problems are primarily the result of genetic causes. This reduction of social problems to biological problems could change how we think about social priorities. For example, employers may be viewed as less responsible for improving workplace conditions, with the focus of disease causation shifting from the hazardous workplace to the predisposed worker. Similarly, research funding may be diverted away from preventive strategies for improving public health, moving instead to approaches stressing genetic influences on disease (46).

Areas for Future Research

It is expected that as the EGP develops, a wide range of ethical, legal, and social issues will emerge as important areas for additional consideration. There is already extensive literature examining the social implications of genetic research, much of which is directly relevant to the EGP. All too frequently, however, policy recommendations focus on rare alleles that are highly predictive of disease. It is unclear whether these moral and legal perspectives are appropriate guides when the alleles under investigation are much more common and less predictive of future disease (47,48).

In many ways, the EGP is representative of a new type of genetic research program, with its emphasis on the incorporation of detailed genomic information into our understanding of disease susceptibility and individual response to environmental exposure. Thus, it is not surprising that the social implications of the project have not been adequately discussed in the existing bioethics literature. As the field of environmental genomics develops, researchers, legislators, and policy makers will need to consider the extent to which traditional bioethical perspectives apply to this new area of research. Thoughtful discussions of the ethical, legal, and social implications of environmental genomic research are critical to the overall success of projects like the EGP. We hope that this paper plays a role in fostering those discussions.

For additional information on the ethical, legal and social implications of the EGP, visit the project's web site (49).

REFERENCES AND NOTES

(1.) Albers JW. Understanding gene--environment interactions [Letter]. Environ Health Perspect 105:578-560 (1997).

(2.) Kaiser J. Environment institute lays plans for gene hunt. Science 278:569-570 (1997).

(3.) Shalat SL, Hong J-Y, Gallo M. The Environmental Genome Project. Epidemiology 9:211-212 (1998).

(4.) Guengerich FP. The Environmental Genome Project: functional analysis of polymorphisms [Letter]. Environ Health Perspect 106:A365-A368 (1998).

(5.) Brown PO, Hartwell L. Genomics and human disease--variations on variation. Nat Genet 18:91-93 (1998).

(6.) Wilson S. Response: Environmental Genome Project [Letter]. Environ Health Perspect 106:A368-A369 (1998).

(7.) Khoury M. Genetic epidemiology and the future of disease prevention and public health. Epidemiol Rev 19:175-180 (1997).

(8.) Collins F. Shattuck lecture: medical and societal consequences of the Human Genome Project. New Engl J Med 341:28-36 (1999).

(9.) Chakravarti A. It's raining SNPs--hallelujah? Nat Genet 19:216-217 (1998).

(10.) Marshall E. The genome program's conscience. Science 274:488-490 (1996).

(11.) Meslin EM, Thomson EJ, Boyer JT. The ethical, legal, and social implications research program at the National Human Genome Research Institute. Kennedy Inst Ethics J 7:291-298 (1997).

(12.) Sharp RR, Barrett JC. The Environmental Genome Project and bioethics. Kennedy Inst Ethics J 9:199-212 (1999).

(13.) Loffredo CA, Silbergeld EK, Parascandola M. The Environmental Genome Project: suggestions and concerns [Letter]. Environ Health Perspect 106:A368 (1998).

(14.) Schulte PA, Lomax GP, Ward EM, Colligan MJ. Ethical issues in the use of genetic markers in occupational epidemiologic research. J Occup Environ Med 41:639-646 (1999).

(15.) Brandt-Rauf PW, Brandt-Rauf SI. Biomarkers--scientific advances and societal implications. In: Genetic Secrets: Protecting Privacy and Confidentiality in the Genetic Era (Rothstein MA, ed.). New Haven, CT:Yale University Press, 1997;184-196.

(16.) Grandjean P, Sorsa M. Ethical aspects of genetic predisposition to environmentally-related disease. Sci Total Environ 184:37-43 (1996).

(17.) National Institutes of Health Office of Protection from Research Risks. Protecting Human Research Subjects: Institutional Review Board Guidebook. Washington, DC:U.S. Government Printing Office, 1993.

(18.) Andrews LB, Fullarton JE, Holtzman NA, Motulsky AG, eds. Assessing Genetic Risks: Implications for Health and Social Policy. Washington, DC:National Academy Press, 1994.

(19.) Schulte PA, Perera FP. Validation. In: Molecular Epidemiology: Principles and Practices (Schulte PA, ed). New York: Academic Press, 1993;79-107.

(20.) Schulte PA, Hunter D, Rothman N. Ethical and social issues in the use of biomarkers in epidemiological research. IARC Sci Publ 142:313-318 (1997).

(21.) Reilly P, Boshar MF, Holtzman SH. Ethical issues in genetic research: disclosure and informed consent. Nat Genet 15:16-20 (1997).

(22.) Schulte PA, Singal M. Ethical issues in the interaction with subjects and disclosure of results. In: Ethics and Epidemiology (Coughlin SS, Beauchamp TL, eds). New York:Oxford University Press, 1996;178-196.

(23.) Nelkin D, Lindee M. The DNA Mystique: The Gene as a Cultural Icon. New York:W.H. Freeman, 1995.

(24.) Hunter D, Caporaso N. Informed consent in epidemiologic studies involving genetic markers. Epidemiology 8:596-599 (1997).

(25.) Clayton EW, Steinberg KK, Khoury MJ, Thomson E, Andrews L, Kahn MJE, Kopelman LM, Weiss JO. Informed consent for genetic research on stored tissue samples. JAMA 274:1786-1792 (1995).

(26.) Knoppers BM, Laberge C. DNA sampling and informed consent. Can Med Assoc J 140:1023-1028 (1989).

(27.) Kopelman LM. Informed consent and anonymous tissue samples: the case of HIV seroprevalence studies. J Med Philos 19:525-552 (1994).

(28.) ASHG report. Statement on informed consent for genetic research. The American Society of Human Genetics. Am J Hum Genet 59:471-474 (1996).

(29.) Wilcox AJ, Taylor JA, Sharp RR, London SJ. Genetic determinism and the over-protection of human subjects. Nat Genet 21:362 (1999).

(30.) Shriver M. Ethnic variation as a key to the biology of human disease. Ann Intern Med 127:401-403 (1997).

(31.) King PA. Race, justice, and research. In: Beyond Consent: Seeking Justice in Research (Kahn J, Mastroianni A, Sugarman J, eds). New York:Oxford University Press, 1998;88-110.

(32.) Caplan AL. Handle with care: race, class, and genetics. In: Justice and the Human Genome Project (Murphy TF, Lappe MA, eds). Berkeley, CA:University of California Press, 1994;30-45.

(33.) Rothstein MA, ed. Genetic Secrets: Protecting Privacy and Confidentiality in the Genetic Era. New Haven, CT:Yale University Press, 1997.

(34.) Wolf SM. Beyond "genetic discrimination": toward the broader harm of geneticism. J Law Med Ethics 23:345-353 (1995).

(35.) Stolberg SG. Concern among Jews is heightened as scientists deepen gene studies. New York Times, 22 April 1998;A24.

(36.) Struewing JP, Hartge P, Wacholder S, Baker SM, Berlin M, McAdams M, Timmerman MM, Brody LC, Tucker MA. The risk of cancer associated with specific mutations of BRCA1 and BRCA2 among Ashkenazi Jews. N Engl J Med 336:1401-1408 (1997).

(37.) Foster MW, Sharp RR, Freeman WL, Chino M, Bernsten D, Carter TH. The role of community review in evaluating the risks of human genetic variation research. Am J Hum Genet 64:1719-1727 (1999).

(38.) Greely HT. The control of genetic research: involving the "groups between." Houston Law Rev 33:1397-1430 (1997).

(39.) Weijer C. Protecting communities in research: philosophical and pragmatic challenges. Camb Q Healthcare Ethics 8:501-513 (1999).

(40.) Juengst ET. Groups as gatekeepers to genomic research: conceptually confusing, morally hazardous, and practically useless. Kennedy Inst Ethics J 8:183-200 (1998).

(41.) Reilly PR. Rethinking risks to human subjects in genetic research. Am J Hum Genet 63:682-685 (1998).

(42.) National Human Genome Research Institute, National Institute on Deafness and Other Communication Disorders, National Institute of Environmental Health Sciences, National Institute of General Medical Sciences. Studies of the ethical, legal and social implications of research into human genetic variation. RFA HG-99-002. In: NIH Guide for Grants and Contracts. Bethesda, MD:National Institutes of Health, 29 April 1999.

(43.) Reilly PR. Laws to regulate the use of genetic information. In: Genetic Secrets: Protecting Privacy and Confidentiality in the Genetic Era (Rothstein MA, ed). New Haven, CT:Yale University Press, 1997;369-391.

(44.) Weir RF, Lawrence SC, Fales E, eds. Genes and Human Self-Knowledge. Iowa City, IA:University of Iowa Press, 1994.

(45.) Lippman A. Prenatal genetic testing and screening: constructing needs and reinforcing inequities. Am J Law Meal 17:15-50 (1991).

(46.) Edlin GJ. Inappropriate use of genetic terminology in medical research: a public health issue. Perspect Biol Med 31:47-56 (1987).

(47.) Juengst ET. The ethics of prediction: genetic risk and the physician-patient relationship. Genome Sci Technol 1:21-36 (1995).

(48.) Parker LS. Ethical concerns in the research and treatment of complex disease. Trends Genet 11:520-523 (1995).

(49.) Environmental Genome Project. Available: http:// www.niehs.nih.gov/envgenom/home.htm [cited 23 December 1999].

Address correspondence to R.R. Sharp, National Institute of Environmental Health Sciences, PO Box 12233, 111 Alexander Drive, Research Triangle Park, NC 27709-2233 USA. Telephone: (919) 541-3489. Fax: (919) 541-5465. E-mail: sharp@niehs.nih.gov

Received 19 August 1998; accepted 14 October 1999.

Richard R. Sharp and J. Carl Barrett

Office of the Scientific Director, National Institute of Environmental Health Sciences, Research Triangle Park, North Carolina, USA

COPYRIGHT 2000 National Institute of Environmental Health Sciences
COPYRIGHT 2004 Gale Group

联系我们|关于我们|网站声明
国家哲学社会科学文献中心版权所有